Page 34«..1020..33343536..4050..»

Category Archives: Freedom of Speech

Opinion: What the Biden Administration Can Expect To Meet in Court – Prescott eNews

Posted: February 2, 2021 at 7:11 pm

Shortly after the 2016 election, the American Civil Liberties Union launched an extremely effective ad campaign. The ACLU believed the incoming administrations agenda to be contrary to the values of its organization and its constituency. See you in court, the ACLUpromised. The money poured in. And they indeed went to courta lot.

President Joe Biden likewise has made commitments and promises that Alliance Defending Freedomthe largest conservative, non-profit, legal organization in the nationbelieves to be contrary to the values of our constituents and organization. Indeed, they are contrary to values essential to any healthy society.

We aim to replicate the ACLUs strategybut with laser focus and greater success. We will not stand idly by while the Biden administration threatens the fundamental rights, values, and the very freedom of millions of Americans.

The gravest threat that arises from Bidens plans is the clear and present danger presented to one of our most basic freedoms: freedom of speech. Americans used to all unite behind the idea, I may disagree with everything you say, but I will defend to the death your right to say it. But no more.

Bidens promisesas well as the political history of both Biden and Vice President Kamala Harrisindicate they are committed to retreating from this fundamental principle.

Harris was the attorney general of California when she helped to engineer and defend a law suppressing the free speech of pro-life pregnancy centers. Naturally, as an abortion advocate, Harris despises the messages coming from pro-life voices, but she went beyond disagreeing; she sought to force pro-life advocates to deliver her favored pro-abortion message.

California law forced these pro-life centers to tell their clients that the state of California offered free or low-cost abortionsand who to call to get one. Coercing someone to communicate a message they believe is immoral is a classic violation of freedom of speech. And in the California case, it was done with the full expectation that these pro-life centers would not comply and thus would close their doors. Coercion was the means; silencing pro-life voices was the ultimate objective. Fortunately, after I argued this case before the U.S. Supreme Court, Californias law was held to be unconstitutional by a 5-4 vote.

Similarly, the Equality Actchampioned by Biden and Harriscontains multiple attacks on freedom. It will erect a federal standard that forces people like our client Jack Phillips, the cake artist who owns Masterpiece Cakeshop, to promote messages and celebrate events through their artwork that violate their religious beliefs. And the bill eliminates protections available under the federal Religious Freedom Restoration Act.

This is an assault on two First Amendment freedoms: freedom of speech (coerced artistic expression) and the free exercise of religion (the freedom to live your life consistently with your beliefs).

Additionally, the Equality Act outlaws counselingwhich is clearly speechthat seeks to advise young people struggling with gender dysphoria. Counseling is legal if the counselor urges the young person to identify with a new gender, but it is illegal if the counselor wishes to help the young person work to return to comfort with their biological sex.

That is called viewpoint discrimination and is likewise a classic violation of the freedom of speech.

The ACLU also supports the Equality Act. The irony is the ACLU used to be the organization that would defend those with whom they disagreed. They used to understand that if you want freedom of speech for yourself you must defend it for others, even those with whom you vehemently disagree.

But the ACLU has abandoned its classical view of freedom of speech. And ADF has arisen to fill the gap.

On the issue of campus free speech alone, we have won over 400 victories against public universities that have restricted the free speech of students based on their viewpoints. Invariably, it is conservative speakers who are censored these days. But our commitment is unequivocal. We will vigorously pursue litigationin the university context and elsewhereaccording to the principle that free speech is for everyone, regardless of ideology.

We have every reason to believe the Biden administration will pursue policies and actions that silence, harass, punish, and persecute those who fail to measure up to their progressive standards.

Let me say this clearly: We will not be silenced. See you in court.

Originally posted here:
Opinion: What the Biden Administration Can Expect To Meet in Court - Prescott eNews

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Opinion: What the Biden Administration Can Expect To Meet in Court – Prescott eNews

Academics should put freedom of speech in the context of other values (opinion) – Inside Higher Ed

Posted: January 29, 2021 at 11:34 am

As important as freedom of speech may be, the failure to put it in the context of other values leads us to some serious problems for our society and, more specifically, for our educational institutions.

In terms of our national political life, we have seen the consequences of defending freedom of speech while attending insufficiently to other essential matters, notably the difference between truth and lies. We face a difficult task if we are to rise to the occasion of saving our form of government.

The damage a fundamentalist approach to free speech can cause our educational systems should be easier to address, given a commitment to core values regarding facts, logic and evaluating sources of information. Where we cannot arrive at the truth about a particular matter definitively, we can still get closer and at least move into the neighborhood. And when we are not ourselves in a position to judge the truth value of what we encounter, we must have ways of evaluating sources and learning how particular experts obtain their special knowledge.

Faculty members who have been especially focused on defending their freedom of speech need to be paying more attention to the quality of their speech. They need to be mindful of their professional responsibilities as well as their rights. That is why they are the ones getting paid and students are the ones paying.

An emphasis on rights is understandable and important at a time that is difficult for faculty generally and especially so for those without tenure. Moreover, some measures taken against faculty members in particular cases -- removal from the classroom or even termination -- have been clearly out of scale with the specific offense. But there is no downside to complementing a concern for faculty rights with a concern for the professional responsibilities that entitle faculty members to take pride in their calling.

In addition to emphasizing the importance of speech supported by facts, sourcing and an interest in truth, faculty members need to teach their students -- and themselves -- how to engage most effectively with those holding different views. They should help students resist the attractions of indulging in self-righteous disdainful abuse. Trying to find out why a person holds certain beliefs is a necessary ethnographic step in the process of dialogue.

While respectful dialogue does not work with everyone, it shapes the ground rules of what is rightly defined as education. And education takes place not only in the classroom, but also in campus free speech zones, since students do not shed their perceptions of faculty/student roles and relationships -- and the unequal nature of them -- when they enter such places.

A breakdown between private and public spheres has especially aggravated our current problems about speech. What faculty members used to say in private -- for example, while enjoying a drink with some colleagues -- is now shared on various nonprivate platforms. What was fine in the former context is not so fine in the latter. We now live with the danger of privacy disappearing altogether.

Our attitudes to free speech are part of a wider, uncritical cultural celebration of freedom abroad in our land. And thus we see many of our fellow citizens refusing to wear masks during a dangerous pandemic and some of our legislators insisting on their right to carry firearms when they report for their day jobs.

An unreflective approach to freedom of speech is often paired with promotion of a marketplace of ideas. Let us note, however, that a marketplace is where you can sell anything -- anything -- that someone else is willing to buy. That may be a less than helpful or inspirational way to think about a democracy, or, for that matter, a society more generally.

We have already followed the path from First Amendment/freedom of speech fundamentalism to Citizens United, a major contribution to turning our democracy into an oligarchy. Will we follow it to where it undermines what education itself is supposed to give to us?

Read the original:
Academics should put freedom of speech in the context of other values (opinion) - Inside Higher Ed

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Academics should put freedom of speech in the context of other values (opinion) – Inside Higher Ed

Forum: Freedom of speech should be exercised with responsibility – The Straits Times

Posted: at 11:34 am

The Jan 6 riot at the United States Capitol in Washington damaged the US' reputation internationally and brought disrepute to Americans.

It was carried out by disgruntled people who were allegedly incited by then President Donald Trump.

Twitter's action two days later to permanently ban Mr Trump's account was, in my opinion, appropriate.Facebook has also indefinitely suspended his account.

European Commission president Ursula von der Leyen said on Tuesday at theWorld Economic Forum that it was wrong for tech giants to make such a decision(EU chief takes aim at tech giants over freedom of speech, Jan 27).

She said "such serious interference with freedom of expression should not be based on company rules alone".

I beg to differ. Freedom of speech should be exercised with responsibility.

No one, especially leaders, should have the liberty to say whatever they like with no regard to the effect their words will have on the public.

We in Singapore enjoy peace solely because the misuse of this liberty is closely monitored here.

Chandra Bose

Read the original:
Forum: Freedom of speech should be exercised with responsibility - The Straits Times

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Forum: Freedom of speech should be exercised with responsibility – The Straits Times

Free Speech and the Question of Race – Los Angeles Review of Books – lareviewofbooks – lareviewofbooks

Posted: at 11:33 am

JANUARY 24, 2021

IS FREE SPEECH the friend of equality and justice? Or is it the foe? Is free speech a tool wielded by conservatives and white nationalists to provide aid and comfort to the spread of their racist ideologies and hateful messages? Or is free speech a valuable weapon used throughout history by oppressed groups to speak truth to power and bring about radical change to reverse centuries of racism and discrimination? Have accusations against progressives for promoting a cancel culture given conservatives a perfect opportunity to seize the mantle as the valiant defenders of free speech?

A frontpage article in the October 18, 2020, edition of The New York Times Magazine reports that some people question the way we have come to think about the First Amendments guarantee of free speech and wonder if perhaps our way of thinking about free speech is not the best way. Was free speech ever meant to take sides in these fraught debates? Was it intended instead to simply create a marketplace where competing ideas wrestle to be heard, with the hope that truth might emerge? And is that very marketplace rigged to protect only the speech of those already in power?

We are in the midst of a historic reckoning on race and democracy that demands that the American people take stock of the lasting legacies of its original sin of slavery and consider the future of our political system. With every institution under scrutiny, the origins, purposes, and future of free speech are no exception. Three new books, with a range of perspectives, sharpen this debate and together help us navigate this moment that is so laden with strident charges and countercharges.

In Is Free Speech Racist?, Gavan Titley, a senior lecturer at the National University of Ireland, Maynooth, questions whether the false and discredited practice of racism deserves the respect and protection afforded to free speech, or whether it in fact enables, facilitates, and legitimizes hatred and discrimination. In Confessions of a Free Speech Lawyer: Charlottesville and the Politics of Hate, prominent First Amendment attorney Rodney A. Smolla examines the consequences of his career dedicated to defending the free speech rights of people who espouse ideas with which he vehemently disagrees. And in Dare to Speak: Defending Free Speech for All, Suzanne Nossel, the chief executive officer of PEN America, while making the case promised by her title, recognizes the real harms inflicted by hateful racist, sexist, homophobic, ableist, and other forms of offensive and demeaning speech, and offers a path forward. Taken together, these three books initiate a far more sophisticated, nuanced, and realistic conversation about the role of free speech in contemporary society than the tiresome and headline-grabbing free speech debates where so many strut and fret upon the stage, superficially magnified in the media, full of sound and fury, signifying nothing.

In Is Free Speech Racist?, Titley is at his best when describing the stark realities of subjugation and humiliation imposed by racism, which possesses an irrational hostility based on race, usually accompanied by a belief in the superiority or inferiority of certain races. He calls out a few recent examples of racism such as President Donald Trump saying that Representatives Ilhan Omar and Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez should go back and help fix the [] crime-infested places from which they came, singling out two women of color oblivious of the fact that they are actually from the United States. Titley describes the frustration of writers such as Reni Eddo-Lodge, who has suffered the sting of racism to the point of exclaiming, Im no longer engaging with white people on the topic of race because of a lifetime of self-censorship that people of colour have to live. Had Titley written a book developing these themes, exposing the evils of racism, explaining the nature of implicit bias, white privilege, and systemic racism, and outlining concrete steps that societies can take to dismantle racism, he would have contributed significantly to the progress of racial justice.

Yet Titley does very little of that. Instead, he blames free speech for racism, and his antidote is to block, cancel, and eliminate racist speech. It is a flawed and lazy analysis. But before examining its weaknesses in the spirit of free speech lets give his arguments a fair reading.

Titley is deeply concerned that conferring on racist speech the respectable mantle of free speech gives it the same deference and hallowed status that has been bestowed on great and worthy ideas over centuries of classical liberal thought. As a result, free speech no longer serves its neutral role in the storied marketplace of ideas because it elevates, honors, and promotes racism and all of the hatred, oppression, and silencing that it represents. For him, free speech has become weaponized in the service of racism. He sees a tendency of appropriating free speech as a shield against criticism or as a licence [British spelling] to provoke. The central argument of his book is that where racism is dominantly understood in terms of ideology and ideas, invocations of free speech have become fundamental to reshaping how racism is expressed and legitimized in public culture. Consequently, free speech has been adopted as a primary mechanism for validating, amplifying, and reanimating racist ideas and racializing claims.

As Titley sees it, giving a racist a platform on a university campus or community forum to voice hate-filled rhetoric anoints that speaker with the imprimatur of the university or forum. The very idea of public debate, he writes, exudes a glow of democratic potency, one that all too often remains undimmed by any reckoning with the barriers and inequalities to meaningful participation that shape public cultures. He skeptically adopts the question of one observer: How can we balance the core values of preserving freedom while limiting the harmful effects of racism?

Titley argues that the far-right has captured free speech. Racists have replaced hackneyed KKK appeals to White Power with the rhetoric of free speech, converting challenges over the validity of what they say into attacks on their cherished right to say it. Anti-racism is increasingly cast in the role of censor, he writes, granted exceptional powers to silence in a context of abundant, endless communications. By hijacking free speech, Titley argues, racists attract support from a wider swath of society who are more comfortable defending such a universal value but would never be caught dead defending racism or white supremacy itself. In a variation on the Observer Effect, which posits that the very act of observing a phenomenon changes that phenomenon, Titley appears to be suggesting that the very act of treating racist speech as free speech transforms racism into a legitimate subject for public discourse and debate.

Titley, author of several books, including After Charlie Hebdo: Terror, Racism and Free Speech (2017), is rightly skeptical of the marketplace of ideas metaphor. The dominant liberal vision, he writes, has always been shadowed by the constraints it neglects: the forms of material possibility, structured inequality, political power, media access, and communicative capacity that organize the meaningful distribution of expression and attention in racially ordered capitalist societies. Aside from unnecessarily limiting his critique to capitalist societies (Lenin imposed strict controls on the press as soon as he came to power, as regimes across the political and economic spectrum have done and are doing), Titley makes a valid point. There has always been something abstract and pristine about the Holmesian notion that we exchange our ideas in a free and unconstrained market where truth will inevitably emerge from the clash of ideas openly expressed by all sides. The ability to be heard and compete for recognition has never been conducted on a level playing field and has always been subject to market constraints Titley mentions and, one might add more explicitly, severe economic, racial, and gender disparities across society.

But Titley goes much further. He argues that racism and by the end of the book, he includes sexism and homophobia is a categorically false and discredited idea that does not deserve to be treated as free speech, just as the Holocaust, eugenics, or the flat earth theory should no longer be debated. If free speech is based on the pursuit of truth and racism is universally known to be false, then there is nothing further to pursue, and racism is automatically disqualified from its status as free speech. If free speech is based on the power of reason to identify what is good for society, which people and governments should endorse and nurture, then because racism is irrational, invalid, and incoherent, it is not entitled to the protection of free speech.

Titley is explicit and unequivocal on this point. He argues that opposition to far-right speakers is based on a rejection of the idea that racializing discourse should be treated as debatable in societies and contexts where it acts in and on the lives of its targets. He considers it key to his argument that because fascist speech is action oriented toward furthering a violent politics of domination, there is no possibility of democratic debate. Instead, all forms of fascist activity constitute attempts at mobilization which must be defeated before they achieve traction. He endorses an observation in Antifa: The Anti-Fascist Handbook (2017) that [i]nstead of privileging allegedly neutral universal rights, anti-fascists prioritize the political project of destroying fascism and protecting the vulnerable regardless of whether their actions are considered violations of the free speech of fascists or not.

When it comes to racists speaking on campus or at other forums, Titley approves of tactics such as blocking, disruption, and no platforming. Titley awkwardly claims that to block is not to stem the transmission of ideas, but to stymie the cumulative force of ritual, drawing attention to the conditions of reception required for racisms successful reproduction. He argues that to play the roles allotted by the ritual is to refuse the postracial licence increasingly accorded to racializing discourse under the sign of civil debate. He defines the roles allotted by ritual as allowing a speaker to speak without cancellation, interruption, or disruption.

There is no question that Titley presents a consistent and elaborate argument grounded in a compassionate and genuine sympathy for the victims of racism. But his argument is deeply flawed, beginning with the elemental obligation of defining what hes talking about. While everyone, including Titley, has their own working definition of racism, in a book whose essential purpose is to eliminate an entire classification of speech from public discourse, the author has a special responsibility to define what he means by racist speech. He is advancing a very serious project of categorically excluding what he calls racism from the protections afforded to the universal notion of free speech. But what ideas, ideologies, practices, and policies are encompassed within Titleys definition of racism which are sufficiently false, discredited, irrational, and beyond the pale to no longer deserve to be debated? What ideas, ideologies, practices, and policies should be blocked, canceled, or disrupted? Titley never says.

In just a moment of reflection, a number of possibilities come to mind which might or might not qualify to be blocked, canceled, disrupted, or placed beyond the realm of debate in a world controlled by the speech regime Titley recommends: Is it racist to counter Black Lives Matter with a demand that All Lives Matter? Is it racist to call racial sensitivity training divisive anti-American propaganda? Is it racist to label Critical Race Theory cult indoctrination? Is it racist to deny that America is inherently a racist country? Is it racist to complain about multiculturalism, ethnic studies, and identity politics? Is it racist to claim that there is more Black-on-Black crime compared to police shootings of unarmed Black men? Is it racist to argue that affirmative action programs constitute reverse discrimination against whites? Is it racist to object to reparations? Is it racist to prohibit the teaching of the New York Times 1619 Project in public schools? Is it racist to deny the existence of white privilege and white fragility? Is it racist to deny that systemic racism exists in law enforcement? Is it racist to demand that athletes salute the American flag rather than take a knee? Is it racist to oppose the removal of Confederate statues? And so on.

Remember, to deem the expression of any or all of these ideas racist under Titleys free speech regime is to exclude them from any further debate and to allow them to be blocked, canceled, or disrupted when (or even before) they are uttered. This is the essential problem with Titleys book. If after 155 pages he is proposing something else, what is it? A book fails when a careful reading leaves a reader in such a quandary.

And there are other problems with his arguments. Titley bridles at the suggestion that anti-racists are trying to censor racist speech, but his entire argument placing certain speech beyond debate and allowing it to be blocked, canceled, and disrupted validates that very suggestion. Long passages from his book, some of which are quoted in this review, will be Exhibit A the next time Richard Spencer or other alt-right speakers accuse anti-racists of seeking to suppress what they have to say. This only serves to play into the white supremacists hands, further solidifying their claim to the hallowed role of Defenders of Free Speech.

Titley also makes the mistake committed by other proponents of limiting free speech: He never does the heavy lifting of explaining who is going to decide what is debatable and what should be blocked, canceled, or disrupted. He offers a few half-hearted disclaimers that legal or governmental restrictions are beyond the scope of his book. So then what? In the university setting, who will decide what is debatable and what should be blocked, canceled, or disrupted? The administration? Faculty? Students? And regardless of who is on the committee, by what reasonable and objective standards would speech be deemed racist and therefore beyond debate and suitable for blocking, canceling, or disruption? One hundred years of Supreme Court interpretation of the First Amendment, involving thousands of scholars, judges, and advocates, has never been able to devise such a definition that passes constitutional muster bound by requirements of fair notice, due process, and the prohibition on content-based prior restraints.

A related problem that Titley ignores is whether commentary, criticism, and condemnation of racist speech would itself fall victim under his regime. Would the portions of his own book where he quotes racist speech need to be redacted to prevent the spread of these discredited ideas by the very practice of repetition, which he criticizes? Would portions of this book review fall afoul of Titleys proscriptions? And given the subtleties of language and argumentation, how would the committee ever be able to distinguish between condemnation and criticism, not to mention all the shades of opinion in between. Titleys free speech regime would have unintended consequences, especially in classrooms, town halls, political debates, or other forums where the use of devils advocacy is a tried-and-true method of exposing the fallacies of racism.

Titleys book is the biggest advertisement for the classic liberal approach, which he himself belittles more speech, not less developed by Justice Louis Brandeis. The first Jew on the Supreme Court, Brandeis was personally familiar with racist speech, having been subjected to a scurrilously antisemitic confirmation process in the US Senate in 1916. Without harboring any delusions that the opportunities for free speech were equitably and fairly distributed through society, Brandeis nonetheless believed deeply that instead of suppressing hateful or offensive speech, the best remedy was the use of more speech to refute, dismantle, and condemn such speech, thereby exposing and discrediting it and promoting a vision of equality and justice in its place.

Finally, Titley ignores perhaps the greatest threat his regime poses for his ultimate goal of eradicating fascism, racism, sexism, homophobia, and other systems of invidious oppression. Lets imagine Titley succeeds in establishing his regime at college campuses, libraries, city councils, state legislatures, and eventually Congress, installing committees at every level of public and private life to designate certain ideas, ideologies, policies, and practices, beyond debate and therefore subject to blocking, canceling, and disruption. With these standards and procedures solidly in place, ratified and endorsed all the way to the Supreme Court, occupied by justices firmly in Titleys camp, what if the membership of the committees were to change? What if white supremacists took control first at a few universities here and there, then a few libraries here and there, then more and more cities councils and state legislatures, and eventually Congress, the White House, and the Supreme Court? Now in control, they remember only too well the one-sided rules and procedures established under the Titley regime that had systematically suppressed their racist truths. Based on precedent, the new committees promptly declare anti-racist ideas beyond debate and proceed to systematically block, cancel, and disrupt them because they are false and anti-American propaganda. Without the classical liberal First Amendment protections for free speech that we rely on today, the content-based Titley regime would allow anti-racist ideas to be placed beyond debate and subject to blocking, canceling, and disruption.

This is what the famous scene in A Man for All Seasons was all about. When William Roper asks Sir Thomas More if he would give the Devil the benefit of law, More readily replies, Yes! What would you do? Cut a great road through the law to get after the Devil? Roper fires back: Yes, Id cut down every law in England to do that! Without a pause, More declares:

Oh? And when the last law was down, and the Devil turned round on you, where would you hide, Roper, the laws all being flat? This country is planted thick with laws, from coast to coast, Mans laws, not Gods! And if you cut them down, and youre just the man to do it, do you really think you could stand upright in the winds that would blow then? Yes, Id give the Devil benefit of law, for my own safetys sake!

Despite its flaws and inequities, the strength of the classical liberal tradition of free speech lies in its protection for all ideas, no matter how odious or offensive, giving the Devil the benefit of that protection for the sake of protecting ideas with which the rest of us agree.

One of the most compelling refutations to calls to prohibit hate speech was made by Aryeh Neier, former executive director of Human Rights Watch. He was born in Nazi Germany and became a refugee when his family fled in 1939 when he was two years old. He was also national director of the ACLU at the time of the Skokie controversy, when the ACLU defended the right of American Nazis to conduct a nonviolent march in that predominately Jewish community. What he wrote in his book Defending My Enemy: American Nazis, the Skokie Case, and the Risks of Freedom (1979) is worth quoting in full:

Because we Jews are uniquely vulnerable, I believe we can win only brief respite from persecution in a society in which encounters are settled by power. As a Jew, therefore, concerned with my own survival and the survival of the Jews the two being inextricably linked I want restraints placed on power. The restraints that matter most to me are those which ensure that I cannot be squashed by power, unnoticed by the rest of the world. If I am in danger, I want to cry out to my fellow Jews and to all those I may be able to enlist as my allies. I want to appeal to the worlds sense of justice. I want restraints which prohibit those in power from interfering with my right to speak, my right to publish, or my right to gather with others who also feel threatened. Those in power must not be allowed to prevent us from assembling and joining our voices together so we can speak louder and make sure that we are heard. To defend myself, I must restrain power with freedom, even if the temporary beneficiaries are the enemies of freedom.

Neiers powerful and compassionate comments reflect the words of the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals in its decision in Collins v. Smith, upholding the right of the Nazis to march in Skokie:

[O]ur task here is to decide whether the First Amendment protects the activity in which appellees wish to engage, not to render moral judgment on their views or tactics. No authorities need be cited to establish the proposition, which the Village does not dispute, that First Amendment rights are truly precious and fundamental to our national life. Nor is this truth without relevance to the saddening historical images this case inevitably arouses. It is, after all, in part the fact that our constitutional system protects minorities unpopular at a particular time or place from governmental harassment and intimidation, that distinguishes life in this country from life under the Third Reich.

In Confessions of a Free Speech Lawyer, Rodney Smolla takes the accusation that free speech enables racism very personally. That explains his repentant title. He has spent his entire legal career teaching, practicing, and defending the First Amendment. Among many books and scores of articles on free speech, Smolla has been the editor of the legal treatise Smolla and Nimmer on Freedom of Speech since 1996 and the author of the casebook The First Amendment: Freedom of Expression, Regulation of Mass Media, Freedom of Religion since 1999. In 2002, he represented a Ku Klux Klan leader in the case of Virginia v. Black in which the US Supreme Court ruled that a cross-burning statute was unconstitutional. In the aftermath of the violent and deadly Charlottesville Unite the Right rallies three years ago, Smolla was appointed by Virginia Governor Terry McAuliffe as special advisor for First Amendment issues on a task force created to investigate what happened during those bloody confrontations.

Did free speech kill Heather Heyer on August 12, 2017? Smolla is haunted by that question. Blame has been cast on many for her death, starting with James Alex Fields Jr., who drove his car into her and later pled guilty to 29 violations of federal hate crimes, for which he received a sentence of life in prison, plus 419 years and a $480,000 fine. Blame has also been cast on the white supremacists who planned and carried out the violent rallies. Others blame lax and ill-prepared Charlottesville and University of Virginia law enforcement. But Smolla is distraught by those who argue that a piece of the blame should be placed on the First Amendment and the marketplace theory of free speech, which treated hate speech as free speech.

I took this last criticism particularly personally, since I had long been, as both a scholar and a courtroom advocate, a champion of expansive protection for free speech. Was I, in some sense, personally complicit in Heather Heyers death, and in the deaths of thousands of others killed by radicalized extremists who bought into the wild white genocide conspiracy theories that fueled the Unite the Right rally and other episodes of hate and violence around the globe?

To answer that question, Smolla weaves together two important strands in his highly engaging book. He presents an engrossing chronicle of what led up to the horrific Unite the Right rallies of August 11 and 12, 2017, and the soul-searching that took place in their aftermath. Meanwhile, he interlaces an excellent analysis of First Amendment history and case law. Both threads, skillfully woven together, are illuminating and make for a captivating account suitable for laymen and lawyers alike.

Smollas lucid explanation of the two major theories of free speech in the American legal system that have jostled for preeminence for over 220 years should be required reading for anyone who deigns to express an opinion on free speech. He labels them the order and morality theory and the marketplace of ideas theory. Neither is mentioned in the First Amendment, which simply declares, in relevant part, that Congress shall make no law [] abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; [] or the right of the people peaceably to assemble

As Smolla explains it, the order and morality theory, which largely tracks Titleys approach, is grounded in the notion that freedom of speech cannot be elevated above the social compact that binds us as a society. A stable, decent, and just society may call on its citizens to obey certain elemental precepts of order, reflected in admonitions such as thou shall not kill, or thou shall not wage war against the government. Likewise, our society may also call on its citizens to respect certain precepts of morality, exemplified by the principle that thou shall not degrade or debase a person based on the persons racial, religious, or sexual identity. Consequently, the order and morality theory posits that freedom of speech, while important, remains subordinate to values of order and morality, and [s]peech that undermines order and morality may be punished by laws enacted through the democratic process. In short, freedom of speech is not freedom to subvert order and morality.

As Smolla explains it, the marketplace of ideas theory is the very opposite. It is grounded in the notion that democracy is subordinate to free speech, and that the test of truth and morality should be the power of a thought to win in the competition of the marketplace of ideas. This should be an ongoing and unfettered competition, outside the heavy-handed authority of the law. Laws enacted by a majority vote may not suppress expression merely because that expression is deemed an affront to prevailing views of good order and morality, because the government has no authority to declare political truth or orthodoxy.

For over 150 years, the order and morality theory of free speech held sway in the United States, with the courts largely allowing Congress and state legislatures to pass laws without questioning whether they ran afoul of the First Amendment. To be sure, there were dissenting views that began to question whether the government had unchecked power to dictate what people could say, write, or read. Indeed, it was in dissent in a case in 1919 that Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., joined by Justice Brandeis, first introduced the marketplace metaphor. He wrote that

the ultimate good desired is better reached by a free trade in ideas that the best test of truth is the power of the thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the market, and that truth is the only ground upon which their wishes safely can be carried out. That at any rate is the theory of our Constitution. It is an experiment, as all life is an experiment.

The shift away from the order and morality model toward the marketplace of ideas model began to develop in earnest in cases such as West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette in 1943, in which Justice Robert Jackson wrote, If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion, or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein. In the subsequent 75 years, the Supreme Court has repeatedly adopted a broad reading of the First Amendment, protecting a wide array of controversial, offensive, and hateful speech from government censorship.

Smolla recounts that as a young free speech lawyer and litigator, I was once an unabashed and unapologetic zealot for the marketplace theory. But quoting Joni Mitchells Ive looked at life from both sides now, he admits that he now sees the battle of ideas as excruciatingly close, and for me the Charlottesville events made the choice even more excruciating. I am sure I am not alone.

Smolla introduces us to Leslie Kendrick, who is Jewish and a distinguished First Amendment scholar. She is the vice dean and a professor of law at the University of Virginia Law School and lives in Charlottesville. According to Smolla, in the aftermath of the Unite the Right rallies in her hometown, Kendrick took a hard look at her traditional defense of free speech. Skeptical of the marketplace rational, she questioned whether suppressing or protecting extremist speech strengthens or weakens such speech. Ultimately, Kendrick comes down in favor of the modern protection of hate speech, as better than any plausible alternative. He summarizes her conclusion this way:

Preventing government from deciding what speech is worthy of protection and what speech is not poses major problems of legitimacy, and the nation has a less than stellar track record in that regard. Modern marketplace of ideas principles exist to shelter unpopular views from the power of majorities. As Kendrick points out, this is true whether the unpopular belief in question is white supremacy in 2017 Charlottesville or equality in 1964 Birmingham.

Lest it be assumed that over time the marketplace theory has only been used to protect racist and hateful speech, Smolla shows how it has been employed to protect various progressive ideas, such as opposition to the Vietnam War and protests against Ronald Reagan. In 1971, the Supreme Court overturned the conviction of a California man who had been convicted of tumultuous and offensive conduct for wearing a jacket bearing the phrase Fuck the Draft in the corridor of a Los Angeles courthouse with women and children present. In an opinion by Justice John Marshall Harlan, Smolla explains, the Supreme Court rejected Californias claim that it could use the law to preserve decency and decorum in society by banning public vulgarity and sheltering citizens from offensive language. And in 1989, the Supreme Court overturned the conviction of Gregory Lee Johnson who had been convicted of burning the American flag at a rally in front of the Republican National Convention in Dallas, Texas, protesting Reagan, the military, nuclear war, and corporate America. Speaking for the court, Justice William Brennan declared that the Government may not prohibit the expression of an idea simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or disagreeable.

At the conclusion of his book, Smolla returns to the questions that have haunted him from the start: Is the contemporary First Amendment principle that hate speech is free speech to blame for the violence and death in Charlottesville three years ago, and do free speech lawyers like himself share that blame? There is no doubt that Charlottesville has prompted Smolla to engage in serious soul-searching. He is now convinced by those events that the marketplace theory cannot be defended on the nave faith that allowing free speech to remain unfettered leads to the triumph of truth in the marketplace. Sometimes it does, and sometimes it doesnt. Often, as in the case of the irrational and hate-filled conspiracy theories of the far right, Smolla writes, freedom of speech leads to the proliferation of death and destruction.

Nevertheless, Smolla comes to the conclusion that the marketplace theory is the best of the bad options. First, it does not result in protection for any and all speech because the Supreme Court has consistently held that the First Amendment is not absolute. It protects speech that is only hateful, but it does not protect hateful speech that is also a true threat, an incitement, or part of a conspiracy to engage in either threats or incitement. Indeed, on July 9, 2018, US District Judge Norman Moon held that the First Amendment did not prevent 11 plaintiffs injured in the 2017 Unite the Right rallies from proceeding to trial against several individuals and organizations accused of conspiring to commit violence in Charlottesville in violation of the federal Ku Klux Klan Act.

Consequently, according to Smolla, despite all its shortcomings, the marketplace theory largely works. It protects evil abstract advocacy, as it is designed to do without placing society in a straitjacket. When proof of actual conspiracy to incite violence and intimidate exists, Smolla writes, the rules of the marketplace theory permit accountability.

As Smolla sees it, the Achilles heel of the order and morality theory is that it can only work if the government is empowered to decide when societys norms of order and morality have been transgressed. This inevitably means that we must trust the government to make these decisions wisely. In the end, the defense of the marketplace theory is that government cannot and should not be trusted with the power.

With Titley arguing that certain ideas, ideologies, practices, and policies are so false, discredited, irrational, and beyond the pale that they deserve to be blocked, canceled, or disrupted, and Smolla holding fast to the principle that short of true threats, incitement, or conspiracy, the First Amendment protects racist, sexist, homophobic, and other hateful and offensive speech, is society left powerless to deal with the toxically polluted public discourse that these authors agree exists?

Into this breach Suzanne Nossel offers us a path forward in her innovative book, Dare to Speak: Defending Free Speech for All. Nossel is deeply concerned that the state of discourse in America today raises a troubling question of whether the principle of free speech can survive intact in our diverse, digitized, and divided culture. She shares Titleys concerns that talking about free speech is hard because the speech that gives rise to such conversations is unpopular, offensive, dangerous, or otherwise contestable. She hopes that her book will help people, when confronted by free speech issues, not to follow the crowd, nod along with outraged friends, or change the subject. Instead, Nossel wants people to enter into dialogue about why free speech matters and how it can be protected without running roughshod over values of equality. Nossel accepts Titleys premise that free speech enables the spread of racism and other objectionable ideas, but she proposes remedies which are far different from his.

Dare to Speak is actually a practical handbook that offers 20 specific principles to help everyone rise to the defense of free speech in ways that avoid simply fueling controversy and instead help rally others to the cause. Fortunately, Nossel pulls this off in a very engaging fashion, looking at the responsibilities we bear living in a diverse society when we speak, when we listen, when we debate, and when we address laws, regulations, and social media company practices. Nossel is convinced that public support for free speech will increase as people feel that their own speech is respected and public discourse is characterized by greater civility.

While her 20 principles could have read like platitudes, Nossel is adept at exploring them more deeply and illustrating them with spot-on examples. She develops the adage watch your language into a more sophisticated call for linguistic conscientiousness. She encourages speakers to understand that the meaning of words and phrases is not universally shared; we must strive to keep abreast of how language and usage are changing, and we should assume our audience encompasses a wide range of experience and viewpoints. She also cautions that all speakers have a duty of care to do their homework first to understand how what they say may be heard differently by different audiences and not to assume their speech is private, especially when using email and social media. She suggests that by keeping an open mind, you can make space in your information diet for alternative viewpoints and sources, and you can develop the strength when appropriate to offer a prompt, sincere, self-reflective apology that does not deflect blame or make excuses. Nossel emphasizes that these norms this linguistic conscientiousness does not mean self-censorship but in fact enables us not only to express strongly held ideas and opinions but also to improve our chances of persuading others to more readily consider what we have to say, and, in many cases, come to agree with us.

Nossel also counsels that we need to become better listeners by delaying a response until we have seriously considered the intent and context surrounding what has been said or written. If there is ambiguity, we should offer the speaker the benefit of the doubt and investigate before responding; consider the culture and the setting in which something is said; and resist applying strict liability, recognizing that something that appears offensive at first blush, may not have been intended in that way.

Nossel explains that there are times to call in (with a private reproval) and times to call out (with a public response). She recommends calling in when the offense appears inadvertent or unintended, the speaker is open to correction, the potential harm can be prevented or ameliorated, and when there is a trusted relationship with the speaker. Calling out is justified when behind-the-scenes efforts have failed, the speaker has a track record of deliberate provocation, the offense is highly public and therefore demands a public response, the speaker intends to cause harm or has already caused harm, and a shared taboo has been breached and warrants reinforcement. In all this, one bears a special responsibility as a classroom teacher, a panel moderator, or someone in a position of higher authority.

When it comes to the attempted regulation of hate speech, Nossel has been paying close attention to the debate exemplified by the competing views of Titley and Smolla. To have doubts about new government restrictions on hate speech, she writes, does not imply callousness toward loathsome invective. Those who are legitimately anguished over the rise of hateful speech need to be persuaded that free speech is not their enemy, while those who oppose censorship need to be persuaded that active, effective resistance to hateful speech and crimes is essential. To fend off new curbs on speech, Nossel argues that it is essential to demonstrate that there exist viable, constitutional measures to combat hateful speech and prevent hate crimes.

Nossel distinguishes hate crimes from hate speech. According to the FBI, a hate crime is a traditional offense like murder, arson, or vandalism with an added element of bias motivated in whole or in part by an offenders bias against a race, religion, disability, sexual orientation, ethnicity, gender, or gender identity. Hate speech is the expression of any form of bias not accompanied by a crime motivated by such bias. Hate crimes can involve speech tied to a clear-cut criminal act such as an assault or vandalism or where the speech crosses the line into action, such as a death threat or harassment. To emphasize the difference, the FBI notes that [h]ate itself is not a crime and the FBI is mindful of protecting freedom of speech and other civil liberties.

Nossel is very clear, and indeed even more descriptive than Titley, that hate speech slurs, insults, stereotypes, bigoted symbols causes real harm, including engendering feelings of fear, scapegoating, intimidation, inferiority, and stigma, and wider social effects, including stimulating, legitimizing, and provoking violent or criminal actions, as well as stoking divisions and undercutting the security and well-being of the larger community. She cites several studies documenting these harms, culminating in a meta-study conducted by the University of California San Francisco Medical Center which found that [t]he mental and physical health consequences of perceiving and experiencing discrimination or bias due to some aspect of the self that can be negatively judged appears to be persistent and pervasive. Nossels discussion on the harms of hate speech thoroughly refute the schoolyard retort that sticks and stones may break my bones but words can never hurt me.

Yet Nossel cautions against going in the other direction, exaggerating claims of harm by speculating, inflating, conflating, or projecting onto others. She also is highly critical of a surprising number of influential voices [who] seem ready to treat ugly speech as akin to physical violence. Speech is never the same as physical violence, nor a justifiable provocation for it. As Nossel sees it, Collapsing the time-honored distinction between speech and action would erode the rule of law, chill speech, upend long-held legal and social arrangements, and invite violence in response to verbal provocation.

The core of Nossels project is to offer tools and tactics under the general rubric of counterspeech to undermine, diminish, and eliminate the hate in hate speech, first because its the right thing to do and then because it relieves pressure to enact government controls on speech. She discusses a wide array of methods, including pointing out facts to dispute misstatements and misperceptions; spotlighting hypocrisy and contradictions; warning about the consequences of speech; relating personally to the speaker or the target; opposing the speech rather than the speaker; using humor, empathy, or sometimes denunciation; deleting and not forwarding; eliciting supportive counterspeech from bystanders; and more.

Nossel recommends the work of the Dangerous Speech Project (DSP), an organization focused on mobilizing more effective responses to the most menacing speech. In a 2016 study, DSP found that the use of the foregoing tactics, though hardly foolproof, can in the best of circumstances lead to golden conversations, in which extended exchanges (usually between two people) bring about lasting changes in beliefs. More commonly, counterspeech succeeds incrementally especially where it comes from persons in authority for whom speakers have respect or who are respected within the speakers community or circle of influencers. In those situations, the counterspeech is effective because it authoritatively refutes invidious claims; conveys that toxic messages are rejected writ large; isolates and stigmatizes the speaker; offers a unifying rallying cry for those who oppose the message; and supports those who feel targeted. In its work, DSP supports free speech because it is a fundamental human right and also because silencing people can make them more likely to resort to violence, if they have no peaceful way of expressing and resolving their grievance. This has been called the safety valve benefit of free speech letting off steam to prevent an explosion.

In the long run, Nossel recommends that the best solution to hatred is to root it out through education, dialogue, and exposure to diverse groups and populations. She points to comprehensive anti-bias programs in schools, including curricula, staff and faculty professional development, student leadership training, community forums, and forceful response to bias incidents. In addition, direct human encounters replace stereotypes, including [i]nterracial dialogues, interfaith efforts, LGBT-straight alliances, and a range of other formats.

Nossel also recommends stronger hate crime reporting and law enforcement. She cites a 2019 report of the International Association of Chiefs of Police and the Lawyers Committee for Civil Rights Under Law which recommended beefed-up training for law enforcement and community activists, more rigorous data collection and analysis, and augmented collaboration among police, prosecutors, and community organizations.

Nossel believes that opponents of racism and other forms of bigotry should engage in more effective acts of protest which do not silence, ban, disrupt, or cancel their opponents, including walking out; turning your back; displaying signs, banners, silent gestures, satirical costumes and images; posing tough questions; and protesting outside a venue loudly, boisterously, and nonviolently.

Nossel is alarmed that several recent surveys indicate that just as millennials (born between 1981 and 1997) and members of so-called Generation Z (born between 1995 and 2010) are becoming more liberal and progressive and more supportive of racial and gender diversity and inclusion, they are more willing to accept government regulation of speech. Generally, they place far lower priority on free expression relative to social justice concerns, seeing these values in conflict with one another rather than being allied in the struggle for a just and equal society. Her concerns are worth considering at length:

If younger Americans come to believe that the First Amendment is a tool of white, male-dominant culture, long-standing protections for speech may give way over time. In the long run, those who have the greatest to lose from a withering of free speech norms are those most vulnerable to government suppression of speech, or to being shouted down by the mob, namely the powerless and voices of dissent. It would be ironic for those whose voices are in greatest danger of being silenced to lead the charge to dismantle the norms and principles intended to guarantee them their say.

She quotes President Barack Obama in a 2016 commencement address at Rutgers University where he criticized the universitys decision to give in to student protestors and cancel the planned graduation speech by former secretary of state in the Bush administration Condoleezza Rice. If you disagree with somebody, Obama said,

bring them in and ask them tough questions. Hold their feet to the fire. Make them defend their positions. If somebody has got a bad or offensive idea, prove it wrong. Engage it. Debate it. Stand up for what you believe in. Dont be scared to take somebody on. Dont feel you got to shut your ears off.

Nossel is very clear that free speech concerns should neither be allowed to distract from questions of racial equality nor take a deferential backseat to them. The challenge of realizing a society dedicated to both is to articulate how they interact and can reinforce one another. Speaking directly to Titley, Nossel writes that while free speech can be invoked cynically, it is not the wellspring of bigotry or racism. Those evils derive from history, belief systems, socialization, power structures, fear and other sources. While free speech principles sometimes safeguard bigots from certain forms of reprisal, Nossel firmly believes that to blame free speech for social and racial inequality, or suggest that curtailing free speech will somehow redress these ills, is a red herring. In fact, Nossel argues that free speech is essential to enable the bracing and confrontational protests, demands, and debates that have historically been the engine of equality.

Nossel balances her strong defense of free speech with a refreshing critique of the marketplace theory. Free speech defenders, she writes, must consider what it would take to create a marketplace for speech in which everyone is an equal participant. Citing Ibram Kendis seminal 2019 book How to Be an Antiracist, she identifies the educational, cultural, historic, and other forces that dictate who enjoys important outlets for speech publishing contracts, newsroom jobs, public speaking slots, plum jobs, and opportunities to make art or films, as well as the myriad forms of mentorship, recognition, and acclaim with the power to raise visibility and propel expressive careers. Access to these advantages is shaped by the forces of inclusion and exclusion that pervade society at large, including racism, sexism, and other forms of discrimination and inequity. Kendi argues that it is not enough to be nonracist; individuals and institutions must be explicitly anti-racist, meaning that they are working assiduously to dismantle, reverse, and reinvent the forces of racism that pervade society.

Nossel challenges her free speech allies to insist on, and work for, the eradication of constraints, biases, and inequities that make speech freer for some than others. If free speech is premised on robust give-and-take, she insists that exclusion and underrepresentation in such debates impoverish the deliberation and compromise the result. Finally, when free speech is seen as benefiting only the powerful, it becomes discredited as a tool of privilege. Instead, free speech and its defenders need to be seen as allies in the struggle to eliminate racism, sexism, homophobia, antireligious bias, and prejudice.

To that end, Nossel presents a program to spend more effort enabling the speech of those who have been silenced and marginalized together with the traditional work of constraining limits on speech. On a personal level, she recommends a range of methods to welcome participation at the Thanksgiving table, a business meeting, or a classroom discussion, making space for those who are too shy or intimidated to speak, or using progressive stacking which prioritizes excluded groups who are all too often drowned out by traditionally male-dominated settings.

Another idea is centering and decentering. The notion is that white voices, ideas, and institutions have long occupied center stage in American society, and that it is important to now center people of color and their narratives as a way to upend traditional hierarchies that impair equality. Some of these hierarchies are so entrenched we easily overlook them. The prevalence of all-male panels in academia, business, and civic society led some to label them manels prompting intentional efforts to diversify such gatherings.

As an example of what is being done on a more institutional level, Nossel identifies five literary organizations that are expanding opportunities for expression, including Cave Canem (African American poetry), Kundiman (Asian American creative writing), Lambda Literary (LGBTQ writers), Vida Women in Literary Arts (women reviewing books and essays), and Asian-American Writers Workshop (supporting writers and curating events).

Nossel concludes her book by tackling the quarrelsome issue of online free speech. The size of the digital public square is immense. Seventy-two percent of American adults use some form of social media, and 68 percent rely on social media as a main source for news. Among young adults, the proportions are even higher. Five billion videos are viewed on YouTube and 500 million tweets are posted every day every day! The public increasingly demands that these platforms monitor all this content. Consequently, Facebook, YouTube, and Twitter have established Community Guidelines that provide standards of what the platforms permit and forbid when it comes to nudity, violence, hate speech, and other contentious content. Social media sites rely on tens of thousands of content moderators who are usually low-wage individuals employed by outside contractors, poring over endless streams of explicit, violent, and disturbing messages in depressing work conditions. They often suffer from panic attacks and even post-traumatic stress disorder, and some, after prolonged exposure, even eventually embrace the very fringe views they are monitoring.

Compounding the problem, the standards used to monitor content are labyrinthine and illogical, confirming the fears of free speech defenders who complain about the unintended consequences once someone in authority assumes the power of restricting speech. At one stage, Facebooks official policy protected white men from hate speech (since both race and gender are protected characteristics) but not black children (since age is not a protected trait). A post by US representative Clay Higgins calling for the murder of radicalized Muslims was allowed to remain online, while a post by a poet and Black Lives Matter activist saying, All white people are racist was removed. A 2016 study found that Islamic State accounts on Twitter were subjected to frequent disabling and removal, while white nationalist accounts were allowed to post with little disruption. YouTube removed a video channel tied to California State University San Bernardinos Center for the Study of Hate and Extremism a channel educating users about bigotry, not promoting it. YouTube also pulled a series of videos depicting fighting dinosaur robots because they showed deliberate infliction of animal suffering or the forcing of animals to fight. This is all a baffling laboratory experiment exposing the problems that would confront any state or federal government agency, university, or other speech control committee that assumed the power to block or cancel free speech.

Another serious problem Nossel identifies is that profit-driven market considerations influence content decisions. In 2018, Twitter earned $3 billion, Facebook $56 billion, and Alphabet (Google) $137 billion. To attract and keep users and increase engagement, ad dollars, and transaction revenues, the platforms favor gripping content, including surprising, shocking, up-to-the minute posts with the potential to go viral. According to Nossel, a major 2018 study conducted by the Massachusetts Institute of Technology found that on Twitter, falsehoods consistently travel farther and wider than truthful posts, undercutting the incentive for traffic-hungry content czars to crack down on misleading information.

In the face of these daunting problems with social media, Nossel suggests both institutional and personal responses. She recommends a multipronged, multiyear effort based on increased transparency; meaningful accountability for malfeasance and negligence; respect for international human rights law and norms; adequate redress for individuals who are harmed, including through the unwarranted suppression of their speech; and credible and empowered external oversight.

She also endorses the Santa Clara Principles developed by open-expression advocates in 2018 to expand disclosures and enable greater public accountability, including calling on companies to reveal how many posts are removed, provide notice and an explanation if content is taken down or an account is suspended, and to create an accessible appeals process.

On an individual level, Nossel recommends a variety of steps users can take to be responsible online citizens, including following reliable news reports on platforms products, operations, and terms of service; expressing oneself publicly and within ones circle of influence on issues that matter; asking questions about how the platforms work; voicing outrage when user trust and expectations are breached; reporting content that is unlawful or inconsistent with a companys standards; not sharing dubious content; and voting with clicks i.e., rejecting platforms that betray their responsibilities to society.

And one could add: Not believing everything you read online. Many of us were brought up not to trust everything we read in the newspaper. Proponents of imposing restrictions of free speech assume that the public needs a Big Brother to decide what they can see and read because if left to its own devices the public cant be trusted to make its own decisions. We need to teach and practice critical thinking. We need to consider the source and remain skeptical about what we read.

Titley makes the case why hate speech undermines the struggle for equality and should be curtailed. Smolla makes the case why hate speech, short of threats and incitement, deserves First Amendment protection. Nossel makes the case that if defenders of free speech put time and energy into creating opportunities to give voice to those who have been marginalized, society would see that free speech and equality are friends, not foes.

Nossel reminds us that free speech is the foundation for all other rights. If we did not enjoy the freedom to write, speak, publish, assemble, and protest, she writes, the great movements for reproductive freedom, racial justice, environmental accountability, immigrants rights, and other essential causes would be hamstrung. Every major manifestation of social progress, including passage of civil rights laws, womens suffrage, environmental protection, gay marriage, and countless other examples has been driven forward by the exercise of protected speech: people who voiced ideas that were novel and debatable and used their powers of persuasion to win gradual support.

Justice Brandeis gets the last word. Writing over 100 years ago, he warned that the greatest menace to freedom is an inert people; that public discussion is a political duty, and that this should be a fundamental principle of the American government. Titley, Smolla, and Nossel have done their duty venturing into this controversial public discussion about free speech. Its up to the rest of us to sustain that vital discussion, not merely by defending the right to speak, but by ensuring the widest opportunities for those who historically have been silenced.

Stephen Rohde is a retired constitutional lawyer, lecturer, writer, and political activist.

View post:
Free Speech and the Question of Race - Los Angeles Review of Books - lareviewofbooks - lareviewofbooks

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Free Speech and the Question of Race – Los Angeles Review of Books – lareviewofbooks – lareviewofbooks

Free speech and the responsibilities of social media companies: When should political speech lose its protection? – ABC News

Posted: at 11:33 am

Soon after the anti-democratic mob violence which occurred recently at the US Capitol, I wrote an opinion piece for these pages arguing that much of the debate in the Australian media covering the decision by Twitter to suspend Donald Trumps account permanently was seriously missing the point. Media coverage, including that of the ABC, had covered the views of some Coalition MPs including Deputy Prime Minister Michael McCormack, Treasurer Josh Frydenberg, and backbenchers Dave Sharma, George Christensen, and Craig Kelly. They had expressed concern over what they described as censorship, said that everyone should be entitled to express their views even if they differ, and cited free speech principles as the basis for these views.

I argued that, to the contrary, there was no free speech defence to the speech that Donald Trump gave in Washington, DC on 6 January. This was because of the key issue of the incitement of violence. No coherent free speech argument has ever suggested that its protections extend to the incitement of violence. There is no free speech protection for speech that is imminently and causally connected to the incitement of a mob to violent lawlessness. This is because such speech is evidently, immediately, and virulently harmful. We saw this with the loss of five lives at Capitol Hill that day. There have been subsequent reports that improvised explosive devices were left in the building, and suggestions that some of the insurrectionists had planned (including by bringing along equipment) to take hostages and to execute them.

The idea that the incitement of violence is not protected free speech is not new. In the nineteenth century, John Stuart Mill, the founder of liberalisms ideal of free speech, gave an example of protected free speech writing in a newspaper that corn dealers were robbing the poor. But he stressed that there was a limit on free speech, which is harm to others. He gave as his example the incitement of a mob to violence outside the house of that same corn dealer. In January, Donald Trump incited a mob outside the United States house of democracy, spurring them on to engage in violence against individuals inside the building, and against democratic institutions of governance. There is no free speech defence to this kind of speech.

Want the best of Religion & Ethics delivered to your mailbox? Sign up for our weekly newsletter.

Your information is being handled in accordance with theABC Privacy Collection Statement.

But there are other, very significant free speech concerns that the event raises. With the benefit of the peaceful transition behind us, it is important to pay attention to them.

The first of these is the sheer power of social media to determine what people may, and may not, say. Social media is privately owned. Their highly profitable business model has relied to a large extent on eschewing the responsibilities that inhere in their power to facilitate speech. They have, by and large, profited enormously from facilitating speech while simultaneously avoiding the responsibilities of responding to harmful speech.

Their platforms facilitate harms in new ways, and with a new scope. One need only think of doxing (publicly revealing personal documents online for the purposes of harming someone), revenge porn (publicly revealing intimate photographs online without their consent for the purposes of harming someone), cyberstalking, and disinformation (the deliberate purveying of misinformation for the purposes of harming people or democratic institutions) to understand that online speech facilitates new types of harm, and facilitates a larger scope for old types of harm, such as hate speech.

Platforms are coming under increasing pressure to respond to these, and other, harms and to take action in transparent and consistent ways. This has resulted in the publication of community standards, and of regular reports on the material that is removed by the platforms in violation of those standards. Facebook has even created a new, independent, Oversight Board for the purposes of adjudicating disputes over material that it has taken down.

But there is a long way to go. Just a few points among many make this clear. First, the platforms goal is an international standard that can be applied consistently in any country across the globe. This is a forlorn hope. One of the reasons the platforms get their content moderation wrong is that they do not understand the local contexts that ultimately determine the meaning and force of speech online. Those contexts matter. Second, the platforms are too large to do this work meaningfully they need to be broken up into smaller components that are more easily regulable and can respond to the local contexts that matter. Third, they need to invest much more in, and significantly improve, the training they give their content moderators, with input from the communities and community managers who know how to do this work well.

And fourth, they need to take advice and implement that advice from scholars and practitioners who understand that free speech is not one-sided. Like any human right, free speech carries with it commensurate responsibilities. The responsibility that inheres in freedom of speech is the responsibility not to harm others with ones speech. Everyone is entitled to hold their own views. But when they express these views in public discourse, they have a responsibility to do so in a way that does not harm others. This lesson appears to have been entirely forgotten by those who use the mantra of free speech in increasingly meaningless, or selective, ways.

Another important question raised by the Trump ban is that of the importance of political speech. Trump was given a lot more leeway by social media platforms than ordinary citizens are, during his term of office. There is a good rationale for this. Political speech is at the core of speech that ought to be protected speech in a democracy. Although it is notoriously difficult to define, it includes the speech that is vital to citizens ability to self-govern. This is much broader than just the decision of whom to vote for it includes what to believe, and decisions on how to live a good life.

The speech of the president of the United States is inherently political, and therefore warrants a very high degree of protection. Nevertheless, what we saw in January was the recognition that even political speech is not limitless. Where political speech crosses the line into harming others in this case through the incitement of lawless violence it may lose its special protection. It is my hope that the severity of what we saw on 6 January gives pause to those who seek to establish a limitless understanding of free speech, who view all expressions as simply one persons opinion, who view all opinions as just alternative views of the facts.

There are lines that, when crossed, cannot be defended on free speech grounds. Free speech is not unlimited. Free speech carries with it commensurate responsibilities. When we treat all claims to free speech as having equal merit, we lose sight of the meaning of this fundamental, core freedom and instead of understanding it as a human right, we see it used as a weapon to enable harm.

Professor Katharine Gelber is the Head of the School of Political Science and International Studies at the University of Queensland. You can hear her discuss the limits of free speech and the nature of harmful speech with Waleed Aly and Scott Stephens this week on The Minefield.

Original post:
Free speech and the responsibilities of social media companies: When should political speech lose its protection? - ABC News

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Free speech and the responsibilities of social media companies: When should political speech lose its protection? – ABC News

Does Freedom of Speech Exist in Cryptocurrency Communities? – hackernoon.com

Posted: at 11:33 am

"A statement may be both true and dangerous. The previous sentence is such a statement." - David Friedman

Freedom of speech is a topic that many internet communities have struggled with over the last two decades. Cryptocurrency and blockchain communities, a major part of their raison d'etre being censorship resistance, are especially poised to value free speech very highly, and yet, over the last few years, the extremely rapid growth of these communities and the very high financial and social stakes involved have repeatedly tested the application and the limits of the concept.

In this post, I aim to disentangle some of the contradictions, and make a case what the norm of "free speech" really stands for.

A common, and in my own view frustrating, argument that I often hear is that "freedom of speech" is exclusively a legal restriction on what governments can act against, and has nothing to say regarding the actions of private entities such as corporations, privately-owned platforms, internet forums and conferences.

One of the larger examples of "private censorship" in cryptocurrency communities was the decision of Theymos, the moderator of the /r/bitcoin subreddit, to start heavily moderating the subreddit, forbidding arguments in favor of increasing the Bitcoin blockchain's transaction capacity via a hard fork.

Here is a timeline of the censorship as catalogued by John Blocke: https://medium.com/johnblocke/a-brief-and-incomplete-history-of-censorship-in-r-bitcoin-c85a290fe43

Here is Theymos's post defending his policies: https://www.reddit.com/r/Bitcoin/comments/3h9cq4/its_time_for_a_break_about_the_recent_mess/, including the now infamous line "If 90% of /r/Bitcoin users find these policies to be intolerable, then I want these 90% of /r/Bitcoin users to leave".

A common strategy used by defenders of Theymos's censorship was to say that heavy-handed moderation is okay because /r/bitcoin is "a private forum" owned by Theymos, and so he has the right to do whatever he wants in it; those who dislike it should move to other forums:

And it's true that Theymos has not broken any laws by moderating his forum in this way. But to most people, it's clear that there is still some kind of free speech violation going on. So what gives? First of all, it's crucially important to recognize that freedom of speech is not just a law in some countries. It's also a social principle.

And the underlying goal of the social principle is the same as the underlying goal of the law: to foster an environment where the ideas that win are ideas that are good, rather than just ideas that happen to be favored by people in a position of power. And governmental power is not the only kind of power that we need to protect from; there is also a corporation's power to fire someone, an internet forum moderator's power to delete almost every post in a discussion thread, and many other kinds of power hard and soft.

So what is the underlying social principle here? Quoting Eliezer Yudkowsky:

Slatestarcodex elaborates:

That said, sometimes there is a rationale for "safe spaces" where people who, for whatever reason, just don't want to deal with arguments of a particular type, can congregate and where those arguments actually do get silenced. Perhaps the most innocuous of all is spaces like ethresear.ch where posts get silenced just for being "off topic" to keep the discussion focused. But there's also a dark side to the concept of "safe spaces"; as Ken White writes:

Aha. So making your own safe space off in a corner is totally fine, but there is also this concept of a "public space", and trying to turn a public space into a safe space for one particular special interest is wrong. So what is a "public space"? It's definitely clear that a public space is not just "a space owned and/or run by a government"; the concept of privately owned public spaces is a well-established one.

This is true even informally: it's a common moral intuition, for example, that it's less bad for a private individual to commit violations such as discriminating against races and genders than it is for, say, a shopping mall to do the same. In the case or the /r/bitcoin subreddit, one can make the case, regardless of who technically owns the top moderator position in the subreddit, that the subreddit very much is a public space. A few arguments particularly stand out:

If, instead, Theymos had created a subreddit called /r/bitcoinsmallblockers, and explicitly said that it was a curated space for small block proponents and attempting to instigate controversial hard forks was not welcome, then it seems likely that very few people would have seen anything wrong about this.

They would have opposed his ideology, but few (at least in blockchain communities) would try to claim that it's improper for people with ideologies opposed to their own to have spaces for internal discussion. But back in reality, Theymos tried to "annex a public space and demand that people within the space confirm to his private norms", and so we have the Bitcoin community block size schism, a highly acrimonious fork and chain split, and now a cold peace between Bitcoin and Bitcoin Cash.

About a year ago at Deconomy I publicly shouted down Craig Wright, a scammer claiming to be Satoshi Nakamoto, finishing my explanation of why the things he says make no sense with the question "why is this fraud allowed to speak at this conference?"

Of course, Craig Wright's partisans replied back with.... accusations of censorship:

Did I try to "silence" Craig Wright? I would argue, no. One could argue that this is because "Deconomy is not a public space", but I think the much better argument is that a conference is fundamentally different from an internet forum.

An internet forum can actually try to be a fully neutral medium for discussion where anything goes; a conference, on the other hand, is by its very nature a highly curated list of presentations, allocating a limited number of speaking slots and actively channeling a large amount of attention to those lucky enough to get a chance to speak. A conference is an editorial act by the organizers, saying "here are some ideas and views that we think people really should be exposed to and hear".

Every conference "censors" almost every viewpoint because there's not enough space to give them all a chance to speak, and this is inherent to the format; so raising an objection to a conference's judgement in making its selections is absolutely a legitimate act.

This extends to other kinds of selective platforms. Online platforms such as Facebook, Twitter and Youtube already engage in active selection through algorithms that influence what people are more likely to be recommended. Typically, they do this for selfish reasons, setting up their algorithms to maximize "engagement" with their platform, often with unintended byproducts like promoting flat earth conspiracy theories.

So given that these platforms are already engaging in (automated) selective presentation, it seems eminently reasonable to criticize them for not directing these same levers toward more pro-social objectives, or at the least pro-social objectives that all major reasonable political tribes agree on (eg. quality intellectual discourse).

Additionally, the "censorship" doesn't seriously block anyone's ability to learn Craig Wright's side of the story; you can just go visit their website, here you go: https://coingeek.com/. If someone is already operating a platform that makes editorial decisions, asking them to make such decisions with the same magnitude but with more pro-social criteria seems like a very reasonable thing to do.

A more recent example of this principle at work is the #DelistBSV ampaign, where some cryptocurrency exchanges, most famously Binance, removed support for trading BSV (the Bitcoin fork promoted by Craig Weight). Once again, many people, even reasonable people, accused this campaign of being an exercise in censorship, raising parallels to credit card companies blocking Wikileaks:

I personally have been a critic of the power wielded by centralized exchanges. Should I oppose #DelistBSV on free speech grounds? I would argue no, it's ok to support it, but this is definitely a much closer call.

Many #DelistBSV participants like Kraken are definitely not "anything-goes" platforms; they already make many editorial decisions about which currencies they accept and refuse. Kraken only accepts about a dozen currencies, so they are passively "censoring" almost everyone. Shapeshift supports more currencies but it does not support SPANK, or even KNC. So in these two cases, delisting BSV is more like reallocation of a scarce resource (attention/legitimacy) than it is censorship.

Binance is a bit different; it does accept a very large array of cryptocurrencies, adopting a philosophy much closer to anything-goes, and it does have a unique position as market leader with a lot of liquidity.

That said, one can argue two things in Binance's favor. First of all, censorship is retaliating against a truly malicious exercise of censorship on the part of core BSV community members when they threatened critics like Peter McCormack with legal letters (see Peter's response); in "anarchic" environments with large disagreements on what the norms are, "an eye for an eye" in-kind retaliation is one of the better social norms to have because it ensures that people only face punishments that they in some sense have through their own actions demonstrated they believe are legitimate.

Furthermore, the delistings won't make it that hard for people to buy or sell BSV; Coinex has said that they will not delist (and I would actually oppose second-tier "anything-goes" exchanges delisting). But the delistings do send a strong message of social condemnation of BSV, which is useful and needed. So there's a case to support all delistings so far, though on reflection, Binance refusing to delist "because freedom" would have also been not as unreasonable as it seems at first glance.

It's in general absolutely potentially reasonable to oppose the existence of a concentration of power, but support that concentration of power being used for purposes that you consider prosocial as long as that concentration exists; see Bryan Caplan's exposition on reconciling supporting open borders and also supporting anti-ebola restrictions for an example in a different field.

Opposing concentrations of power only requires that one believe those concentrations of power to be on balance harmful and abusive; it does not mean that one must oppose all things that those concentrations of power do.

If someone manages to make a completely permissionless cross-chain decentralized exchange that facilitates trade between any asset and any other asset, then being "listed" on the exchange would not send a social signal, because everyone is listed; and I would support such an exchange existing even if it supports trading BSV. The thing that I do support is BSV being removed from already exclusive positions that confer higher tiers of legitimacy than simple existence.

So to conclude: censorship in public spaces bad, even if the public spaces are non-governmental; censorship in genuinely private spaces (especially spaces that are not "defaults" for a broader community) can be okay; ostracizing projects with the goal and effect of denying access to them, bad; ostracizing projects with the goal and effect of denying them scarce legitimacy can be okay.

Originally published as On Free Speech with the WTFPL license

Create your free account to unlock your custom reading experience.

Read this article:
Does Freedom of Speech Exist in Cryptocurrency Communities? - hackernoon.com

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Does Freedom of Speech Exist in Cryptocurrency Communities? – hackernoon.com

Complaints about Trump Twitter ban aside, there is no absolute right to free speech – The Fayetteville Observer

Posted: at 11:33 am

Richard A.S. Hall| The Fayetteville Observer

Some have argued that Trumps recent inflammatory speech inciting an insurrection is Constitutionally protected by the First Amendment an argument that might resurface when Trumps impeachment by the House goes to the Senate for trial) but it is not. Still others have claimed that Facebooks and Twitters closing Trumps accounts infringes his right to free speech it does not.

Let me explain.

The right of freedom of speech is unquestionably the sine qua non for a flourishing academy and democracy and thus highly prized by any civilized society. It is inscribed in the First Amendment as, Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press.

More: Letter: I supported Trump, but now is a time to unite

However, free speech is not an unqualified right. There are certain kinds of speech proscribed by law and justifiably so. These include libel, perjury, blackmail, incitement to riot and other such threats to public order and security. The right of free speech is justified by its political value in preserving a democratic polity and by its intellectual value in advancing the cause of truth to which, for example, the scientific community is devoted.

What, then, justifies restrictions on free speech such as the laws forbidding libel and incitements to riot? It is that it actually or potentially harms others. This justification, then, is now known as the harm principle.

Thomas Jefferson anticipated it in his advocacy of the right of freedom of religion: The legitimate powers of government extend to such acts only as are injurious to others. It does me no injury for my neighbor to say there are twenty gods or no god. It neither picks my pocket nor breaks my leg.

More: Authentic religion does not call for churches reopening in a pandemic

John Stuart Mill articulated it more fully in his classic On Liberty (a magisterial defense of free speech that should be required reading for Americans): the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.

Back now to the two cases with which I began, namely, Trumps incendiary speech igniting an insurrection, and Facebooks suspension and Twitters cancellation of his accounts with them. With respect to the first: Trumps speech incited a riot worse, an insurrectionary riot.

Incitement to riot violates the harm principle and U.S. federal law, and is thereby indictable. Hence, his speech is not Constitutionally protected free speech. As to the second case: If Trumps statements on Facebook and Twitter pose a threat to public order and security in the form of riots, in violation of the harm principle and federal law, then they are not protected by the First Amendment. If Facebook and Twitter were to allow him to voice his threats to the public peace, they would be complicit in his malfeasance. Their decisions to close Trumps accounts are not an infringement of his right of free speech.

More: Myron B. Pitts: 8 times Biden, Obama and others condemned Black Lives Matter violence

Let me conclude by strongly affirming my own commitment to the maximization of free speech as an indefeasible human right. However, when its exercise conflicts with other such rights, namely the publics right to safety and security, then it should give way to the latter.

Lest anyone complain that restrictions on their harmful speech violates their First Amendment Right, let them ask themselves this question: Does my speech advance the cause of justice and truth? If they cannot answer affirmatively, then they have no grounds for complaint.

According to the late nineteenth-century English philosopher, Thomas H. Green, the true index of a societys freedom is the extent to which its citizens have the ability and opportunity to realize the best in themselves and others: When we measure the progress of a society by its growth in freedom, we measure it by the increasing development and exercise on the whole of these powers of contributing to social good with which we believe the members of the society to be endowed; in short, by the greater power on the part of the citizens as a body to make the most and best of themselves.

Nothing less than this is the very freedom that speech should promote, thereby justifying its own status as an indefeasible right.

Richard A. S. Hall is a professor of philosophy at Fayetteville State University.

Support local journalism with a subscription to The Fayetteville Observer. Click the subscribe link at the top of this article.

Continued here:
Complaints about Trump Twitter ban aside, there is no absolute right to free speech - The Fayetteville Observer

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Complaints about Trump Twitter ban aside, there is no absolute right to free speech – The Fayetteville Observer

Absolute Freedom to Tweet? Employers (and the NLRA) May Have Something to Say About It – Lexology

Posted: at 11:33 am

Do you need a social media policy or are the legal obstacles just too much? Now more than ever, people are exercising their First Amendment right to free speech, which, not surprisingly, can cause heartburn at the workplace. In times of contention, stress, and uncertainty, speech often multiplies, and, in an era where someones speech is accessible to the world with just a few clicks, an employees online speech is often cast as the speech or opinions of the employer. Additionally, the National Labor Rights Act (NLRA) presents another hurdle, as it protects employees rights to discuss the terms and conditions of their employment. What can and should a responsible employer do?

Many employers implement social media policies, addressing employees actions on social media to enforce their policies and protect their brand. Although important, an employees right to free speech or NLRA protection is not without limits. How do you balance the First Amendment and employees NLRA protections on the one hand and your business interests on the other? Below are some considerations to keep in mind.

The First Amendment May Not Apply: Public vs. Private Employers

The First Amendment says that Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech. Then came the 14th Amendment, which applied the First Amendment to state governments and their divisions. All of that to say, the First Amendment prohibits public entities, and therefore public employers, from infringing on their employees constitutionally protected rights to free speech. However, even public employers have some ability to control employee speech, such as when the speech is illegal, riot-inducing, or made as part of their official duties. For example, in Garcetti v. Ceballos, the U.S. Supreme Court held that the City of Los Angeles did not violate a public officials First Amendment rights by taking action against him for a speech made in his official duties, even though it addressed a matter of public concern. Speech not made as part of an official duty and that addresses a matter of public concern is protected by the First Amendment. For example, in Marquardt v. Carlton, the Sixth Circuit Court of Appeals held that the city may have violated an employees First Amendment rights when it terminated him for social media posts of his opinions on a recent police shooting, because it was a matter of public concern.

Dont Forget the NLRA (Even if You Dont Have a Union)

While private employers do not have to navigate First Amendment issues, they are not totally off the hook. The NLRA protects employees rights to engage in concerted activities for the purpose of . . . mutual aid or protection. Importantly, this has been interpreted to mean that employees have a right to discuss the terms and conditions of their employment, such as pay rates. For example, in Quicken Loans, Inc. v. National Labor Relations Board, the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals sided with the NLRB and affirmed that an employers policy forbidding employees from discussing non-public employment information infringed on their rights to discuss terms and conditions of employment.

Even though the NLRA is typically associated with unionized workers, employees have this right whether they are unionized or not. Thus, private employers beware: Although the First Amendment may not keep you from controlling employee speech, the NLRA does . . . but only to an extent.

Unpacking the NLRA

The NLRA protects an employees right to engage in concerted activity by discussing the terms and conditions of his or her employment. These are commonly referred to as Section 7 rights. Lets unpack this:

Social Media Policies: What Does the NLRB Recommend?

Social media policies generally restrict, or attempt to control, what employees say online. When do these policies go too far and restrict employees Section 7 rights? The NLRB has published some reports summarizing its decisions on what social media policies and practices infringe on employees Section 7 rights to discuss the terms and conditions of their employment.

The NLRBs guiding rule: A social media policy is unlawful if a reasonable employee would interpret it as prohibiting the exercise of Section 7 rights. This almost always depends on the context surrounding the provisions. However, heres a list of some common provisions that the NLRB deemed overly broad:

Often, if a social media policys provision includes examples of prohibited behavior, which do not implicate Section 7 rights, or if it limits prohibited conduct to certain circumstances, such as speaking with the press, the NLRA will deem that an employee could not reasonably interpret it as infringing on their Section 7 rights.

It is important to note that, in some instances, the NLRB has held that, even though the social media policy was overbroad, the employer nonetheless lawfully disciplined an employee for his or her actions on social media (e.g., the employees speech was unrelated to employment, not concerted with other employees, or harassing). Thus, keep in mind that an overbroad policy alone is not the determinant of whether an action against an employee violated the NLRA; what is important is whether the action taken was because of or restricted a conversation between employees about the terms and conditions of their employment.

Takeaways

If you want to implement a social media policy, consider the First Amendment and the NLRA. Policies are good ideas and can give your employees some valuable guidance about what they should or shouldnt do. However, remember that the First Amendment applies if you are a public employer. If you are a private employer and want to discipline an employee pursuant to a social media policy, take a deep breath and think about NLRA Section 7 rights (and maybe call your legal counsel).

Read more:
Absolute Freedom to Tweet? Employers (and the NLRA) May Have Something to Say About It - Lexology

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Absolute Freedom to Tweet? Employers (and the NLRA) May Have Something to Say About It – Lexology

Students quit free speech campaign over role of Toby Young-founded group – The Guardian

Posted: January 9, 2021 at 3:18 pm

When a group of student activists were recruited to create a freedom of expression campaign, they were optimistic that their wide-ranging views could be part of its mission to get all young people enthusiastic about free speech.

The reality of the Free Speech Youth Advisory Board, they say, was rather different.

Instead of finding a forum for their hopes of opposing repressive regimes and helping minority voices to get heard, they claim that they were censured if they disagreed with the groups right-of-centre orthodoxy. And they say they were dismayed to realise that the supposedly grassroots project appeared to be an astroturfed front for Toby Youngs controversial pressure group, the Free Speech Union (FSU).

We have been used by Toby Young to legitimise this project, said Harry Walker, president of the Bristol Free Speech Society, who emphasised that he spoke in a personal capacity. Organisations like the FSU are just perpetuating a culture war.

Maya Thomas, an Oxford University student and founder of the Oxford Society for Free Discourse, claimed: They said very clearly this is a grassroots movement. They purposely hushed the FSUs involvement down.

Days ahead of a planned launch of the Free Speech Champions arm of the FSU, the Guardian has learned that at least six of the founding 16 participants have withdrawn from the campaign.

An email to organisers claimed that this project seems to have been in the works for months, originating effectively as an FSU youth wing rather than the independent grassroots movement it was pitched to us as.

Inaya Folarin Iman, a director of FSU who led work on the project, told the Guardian: This is my initiative, but I am a founding member of the board of the Free Speech Union and I have always been very open about the FSUs involvement and sponsorship No doubt the students who have contacted you see themselves as supporting free speech, but the Free Speech Champions project is unequivocal that it is an indivisible right and a fundamental civic virtue. Young did not respond to a request for comment.

The resignations, which highlight a seething debate over the definition of free speech on campuses, may come as a blow to Youngs plans to influence university cancel culture debates through the FSU. Since he founded the group in February last year, it has largely intervened in cases of interest to the libertarian right, embroiling itself in identity politics, anti-trans activism and lockdown scepticism.

Despite those apparent focuses, Young whose supporters include the historian David Starkey and the journalists Allison Pearson and Julia Hartley-Brewer insisted last year that he wanted the FSU to appeal across the political and demographic spectrum, saying the organisation isnt just for male, pale and stale conservatives like me.

More than 80% of the 85 directors, staff and advisers listed on the FSU website are male and more than 90% of those whose ethnicity could be determined are white.

Walker and Thomas were both approached to join the group. They and a recent Portsmouth graduate, Charlotte Nrnberg, told the Guardian that they found the promise of an open forum to be empty. The group started with quite diverse viewpoints, said Nrnberg, an activist and committee member of her university debating society until she graduated. But very quickly that got shut down.

In two emails to organisers explaining their departure, the trio, along with another member of Bristols Free Speech Society, Ben Sewell, claimed that the reality of the FSUs involvement had been deliberately withheld when they signed up.

We were led to believe that [the group] was independent from external organisations, particularly the one that most of us are concerned about, the FSU, they wrote. A number of us would not have joined had we known the true extent of the FSUs influence.

A subsequent email to Iman confirming their departure added: some of us even asked specifically about FSU involvement and were told that it was negligible.

Emails and social media messages seen by the Guardian suggest that during the recruitment process which sought branding help with name ideas, edgy marketing tactics, things which youd find cool students were led to believe that a separate group led by Iman, the Equiano Project, was behind the plans.

An online application form and introductory email both mention the Equiano Project but not the FSU. Jan Macvarish, a sociologist and education director at the FSU who was present at the first meeting, was introduced as an observer but swiftly took on a major role in shaping the discussion, they said. Macvarish did not respond to a request for comment.

Jan and Inaya dictated the ideological dogma of the group, one of the students who left the group said. This is correct free speech, this is wishy-washy free speech.

While some on the left of the group sought to make the case that it should seek to win support by emphasising the universality of free speech and raising concerns about repressive regimes silencing protest, Macvarish told them in a WhatsApp chat: The degree to which citizens of China or Hungary have fs [freedom of speech], I would argue, isnt of paramount importance to this project.

Instead, WhatsApp discussions were largely dominated by discussions of such figures as the self-styled professor against political correctness Jordan Peterson and anti-trans activists.

As time went on, the role of the FSU became more explicit, the disaffected group say, with Young himself appearing at one of the Zoom sessions. They claim that those who disagreed with the FSUs worldview were portrayed as not committed to free speech.

After Walker said in one discussion that he would punch a Nazi, saw Peterson as a peddler of bought speech and felt that marginalised groups were often denied true freedom of speech, Iman emailed him about a few things that you mentioned on the call that I wanted to pick up with you for clarification.

She added: A level of synthesis is important for the project to demonstrate coherence I aim for this free speech project to move away from an identity politics-based framework. Walker said he viewed those comments as a way of implying that he was not welcome to express his views.

The controversy caps an awkward week for the FSU and its supporters which began with Pearson, a Daily Telegraph columnist and member of the groups Media/PR advisory council, appearing to contradict its opposition to cancel culture by threatening to sue someone who she said had defamed her on Twitter, warning that she would contact his boss, and adding: Youre finished. She subsequently accepted an apology.

On Wednesday, Young was asked on Newsnight why he had written in June that the virus has all but disappeared and said hands up, I got that wrong before continuing his argument against lockdowns.

With the dangers of the wokerati often in the news, Young and the FSU which costs between 25 and 250 a year for membership have frequently found themselves on the frontline of a culture war and celebrating victories wherever they can find them.

After a judge dismissed the groups attempt to win a judicial review of Ofcoms role in regulating misinformation about coronavirus and called it not properly arguable, premised on a misinterpretation, and untenable, the FSU Twitter account posted: Thanks to us, @ofcom has stopped censoring Covid dissidents. The price of freedom is eternal vigilance. In fact, the price of the case was the 16,732 the FSU was ordered to pay to cover Ofcoms costs.

Original post:
Students quit free speech campaign over role of Toby Young-founded group - The Guardian

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Students quit free speech campaign over role of Toby Young-founded group – The Guardian

Houston congressman confronted while flying back from D.C. – KHOU.com

Posted: at 3:18 pm

A video posted to Twitter shows several people yelling at the Houston Democrat as he exits the flight in Tennessee to change planes.

HOUSTON Congressman Al Greensays he was harassed by people identifying themselves as Trump supporters on the way home from Washington.

The Houston Democrat said issues started at the airport in D.C.

Upon getting on the plane, someone recognized me, said Rep Green. At some point, someone said Mr. Impeachment is on the plane.

The Congressman said he heard another voice behind him.

Someone said, somethings gonna happen.

A video posted to Twitter shows several people yelling at the Houston Democrat as he exits the flight in Tennessee to change planes.

On the 21-second clip, voices can be heard saying four more years," youre a disgrace to this country," youre a dirtbag, and youre a traitor."

Rep. Green said people made comments accusing him of not honoring the Constitution, the Presidents freedom of speech, and about how people were being denied their rights.

The people became very rambunctious in the airport, said Rep. Green. They started closing in, and the young man who was helping me had to take me into a room off to the side and call police, call for some security.

He later added, Literally I had to be escorted some 50 feet, maybe, by two peace officers and a Southwest employee.

Rep. Green said the group helped him get on the flight and had a pilot sitting next to him.

The congressman said problems started again when he was about to deplane at Hobby Airport in Houston

Fortunately, I had HPD officers to meet me, he said. Im not sure how it would have ended but for having police officers to assist me.

Republican Sen. Mitt Romney was also confronted at the Salt Lake City airport and heckled while flying to D.C. on Tuesday.

Rep. Green says everyone has the right to free speech but believes protests in airports could lead to violence and disrupt travel and commerce.

He worries protests on planes could be especially dangerous.

You cant protest in a courtroom, you cant yell fire in a theater, and you ought not be able to protest in an airplane 35,000 feet in the air because you dont know what the protest will lead to, he said.

Its an issue the congressman says hell raise once he flies back to Capitol Hill.

Read the original here:
Houston congressman confronted while flying back from D.C. - KHOU.com

Posted in Freedom of Speech | Comments Off on Houston congressman confronted while flying back from D.C. – KHOU.com

Page 34«..1020..33343536..4050..»