The Prometheus League
Breaking News and Updates
- Abolition Of Work
- Ai
- Alt-right
- Alternative Medicine
- Antifa
- Artificial General Intelligence
- Artificial Intelligence
- Artificial Super Intelligence
- Ascension
- Astronomy
- Atheism
- Atheist
- Atlas Shrugged
- Automation
- Ayn Rand
- Bahamas
- Bankruptcy
- Basic Income Guarantee
- Big Tech
- Bitcoin
- Black Lives Matter
- Blackjack
- Boca Chica Texas
- Brexit
- Caribbean
- Casino
- Casino Affiliate
- Cbd Oil
- Censorship
- Cf
- Chess Engines
- Childfree
- Cloning
- Cloud Computing
- Conscious Evolution
- Corona Virus
- Cosmic Heaven
- Covid-19
- Cryonics
- Cryptocurrency
- Cyberpunk
- Darwinism
- Democrat
- Designer Babies
- DNA
- Donald Trump
- Eczema
- Elon Musk
- Entheogens
- Ethical Egoism
- Eugenic Concepts
- Eugenics
- Euthanasia
- Evolution
- Extropian
- Extropianism
- Extropy
- Fake News
- Federalism
- Federalist
- Fifth Amendment
- Fifth Amendment
- Financial Independence
- First Amendment
- Fiscal Freedom
- Food Supplements
- Fourth Amendment
- Fourth Amendment
- Free Speech
- Freedom
- Freedom of Speech
- Futurism
- Futurist
- Gambling
- Gene Medicine
- Genetic Engineering
- Genome
- Germ Warfare
- Golden Rule
- Government Oppression
- Hedonism
- High Seas
- History
- Hubble Telescope
- Human Genetic Engineering
- Human Genetics
- Human Immortality
- Human Longevity
- Illuminati
- Immortality
- Immortality Medicine
- Intentional Communities
- Jacinda Ardern
- Jitsi
- Jordan Peterson
- Las Vegas
- Liberal
- Libertarian
- Libertarianism
- Liberty
- Life Extension
- Macau
- Marie Byrd Land
- Mars
- Mars Colonization
- Mars Colony
- Memetics
- Micronations
- Mind Uploading
- Minerva Reefs
- Modern Satanism
- Moon Colonization
- Nanotech
- National Vanguard
- NATO
- Neo-eugenics
- Neurohacking
- Neurotechnology
- New Utopia
- New Zealand
- Nihilism
- Nootropics
- NSA
- Oceania
- Offshore
- Olympics
- Online Casino
- Online Gambling
- Pantheism
- Personal Empowerment
- Poker
- Political Correctness
- Politically Incorrect
- Polygamy
- Populism
- Post Human
- Post Humanism
- Posthuman
- Posthumanism
- Private Islands
- Progress
- Proud Boys
- Psoriasis
- Psychedelics
- Putin
- Quantum Computing
- Quantum Physics
- Rationalism
- Republican
- Resource Based Economy
- Robotics
- Rockall
- Ron Paul
- Roulette
- Russia
- Sealand
- Seasteading
- Second Amendment
- Second Amendment
- Seychelles
- Singularitarianism
- Singularity
- Socio-economic Collapse
- Space Exploration
- Space Station
- Space Travel
- Spacex
- Sports Betting
- Sportsbook
- Superintelligence
- Survivalism
- Talmud
- Technology
- Teilhard De Charden
- Terraforming Mars
- The Singularity
- Tms
- Tor Browser
- Trance
- Transhuman
- Transhuman News
- Transhumanism
- Transhumanist
- Transtopian
- Transtopianism
- Ukraine
- Uncategorized
- Vaping
- Victimless Crimes
- Virtual Reality
- Wage Slavery
- War On Drugs
- Waveland
- Ww3
- Yahoo
- Zeitgeist Movement
-
Prometheism
-
Forbidden Fruit
-
The Evolutionary Perspective
Daily Archives: January 6, 2023
Benedict XVIs Most Powerful Influence on the Catholic Church Came Before He Was Pope – The New Yorker
Posted: January 6, 2023 at 3:32 pm
Benedict XVIs Most Powerful Influence on the Catholic Church Came Before He Was Pope The New Yorker
See the article here:
Posted in Alt-right
Comments Off on Benedict XVIs Most Powerful Influence on the Catholic Church Came Before He Was Pope – The New Yorker
Women and the Drug War | Drug Policy Alliance
Posted: at 3:30 pm
More than 61% of women doing time in federal prison are behind bars for nonviolent drug offenses.
Women are now a fast growing segment of the U.S. prison population, largely because of draconian drug laws. More than 61% of women doing time in federal prison are behind bars for nonviolent drug offenses.
Women, and particularly women of color, are disproportionately affected by social stigma, by a plea bargaining system that punishes those unable or unwilling to inform on others, by regulations that bar people with a drug conviction from obtaining (or that require a drug test to receive) public assistance, and by a drug treatment system designed for men.
Black women are almost twice as likely and Latinas are 20% more likely to be incarcerated than white women. Native American women are incarcerated six times the rate of their white counterparts.
Drug use occurs at similar rates across racial and ethnic groups, but racialized women are far more likely to be criminalized for drug law violations than white women. Black people are no more likely than white people to use illicit drugs during pregnancy, but they are far more likely to be reported to child welfare services for drug use. Learn more about pregnancy and the drug war.
Roughly 60% of women in state and federal prisons are mothers of minor children, many of them sole caregivers. Removing a parent (perhaps the only parent) from a household is immediately destabilizing, and over the long-term, its devastating. Children with a parent in prison are several times more likely than other children to end up in foster care, to drop out of school and to become involved in the criminal legal system themselves.
Parents, once released from prison, may be barred from public assistance and housing and face significantly reduced employment opportunities. Even women who do not use drugs may be required to submit to invasive and embarrassing monitored drug testing in order to obtain public assistance.
Under the drug war logic that has infiltrated our child welfare system, any drug use is equivalent to child abuse, regardless of context and whether or not there is actual harm to the child. This has resulted in formalized policies that demonize parents, testing them for drugs (often without their consent), relentlessly investigating them, and routinely removing their children without any reason other than supposed drug use.
Learn more about how the drug war breaks up families at UprootingTheDrugWar.org.
Conspiracy charges represent one of the most egregious examples of the drug wars inequitable treatment of women. Although conspiracy laws were designed to target high-level members of illicit drug organizations, they have swept up many women for being guilty of nothing more than living with or not cooperating as an informant against a partner or family member involved in some level of drug sales.
Harsh mandatory minimum sentencing may keep them behind bars for 20 years, 30 years, or life, even if they were never directly involved in drug sales or distribution.
Susan Burton is the founder and executive director of A New Way of Life, an organization that provides support and resources for women recently released from prison. After her son was killed by the Los Angeles Police Department, Susan medicated her grief with alcohol and drugs. Instead of receiving the support and services she needed, she cycled in and out of the criminal legal system for nearly fifteen years.
In 1998, Susan gained her freedom and sobriety and founded A New Way of Life Reentry Project, which has served over 800 women and is a national leader in the struggle to break the cycle of addiction and incarceration.
The Drug Policy Alliance is working to reduce the devastating effects of the drug war on women, particularly women of color. We advocate for:
The rest is here:
Posted in War On Drugs
Comments Off on Women and the Drug War | Drug Policy Alliance
The War on Drugs as Structural Racism – Penn LDI
Posted: at 3:30 pm
A University of Pennsylvania seminar looks at the contrast between the War on Drugs, which devastated Black and Latino communities through mass incarceration, and todays public health approach to opioids in white communities.
A University of Pennsylvania seminar on Racial Justice in National Drug Policy opened with a nod to Michelle Alexander, JD, author of the book The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness,and a quote about racialized drug policy attributed to John Ehrlichman, former White House Counsel and Assistant to the President for Domestic Affairs in the Nixon Administration.
As she opened the panel discussion, moderator Eugenia South, MD, MSHP, LDI Senior Fellow, and Faculty Director of the Penn Urban Health Lab, explained: When we think about what fueled mass incarceration, what laws and policies were created that led to both the ballooning of the prison population and the racial disproportionality of who is there, the War on Drugs is really front and center.
South then read the controversial Ehrlichman quote that appeared in the April2016 issue of Harpers magazine in an article about the failure of the War on Drugs originally launched by President Nixon in 1971:
The Nixon campaign in 1968, and the Nixon White House after that, had two enemies: the antiwar left and Black people,Ehrlichman said. You understand what Im saying? We knew we couldnt make it illegal to be either against the war or Black, but by getting the public to associate the hippies with marijuana and Blacks with heroin, and then criminalizing both heavily, we could disrupt those communities. We could arrest their leaders, raid their homes, break up their meetings, and vilify them night after night on the evening news. Did we know we were lying about the drugs? Of course we did.
Leading up to the first question to a panelist, South emphasized: In this discussion, I really want to explicitly name mass incarceration and the War on Drugs for what it is: a stark example of structural racism.
The event was co-hosted by the Leonard Davis Institute of Health Economics (LDI) and Bold Solutions, a Penn initiative aimed at addressing the effects of interpersonal, structural, and institutional racism on health, and co-sponsored by the Urban Health Lab.
The three panelists were Michael Botticelli, MEd, former Director of the Office of National Drug Control Policy (ONDCP) during the Obama Administration; Kassandra Frederique, MSW, Executive Director of the Drug Policy Alliance; and Helena Hansen, MD, PhD, Professor and Chair, Research Theme in Translational Social Science and Health Equity, and Associate Director of the Center for Social Medicine at the UCLA David Geffen School of Medicine.
A major theme throughout the discussion was how the issues of equity and anti-racism were, or were not, part of the federal governments drug policies in the 1980s and 90s versus the todays raging opioid epidemic. The panelagreed that the earlier War on Drugs criminalized drug use for Black and Latino communities while the current opioid epidemic policy has veered dramatically toward a public health approach to the problem.
Panelist Helena Hansen, who has been studying racialized aspects of U.S. drug policy for a decade, noted that the opioid crisis came to be seen as white.
The popular press and politicians have been circulating images of Black, brown and even Asian people as addicted and dangerous for over 100years and these racialized images built political support for prohibitionist criminalizing drug policies, Hansen continued. Back in 1914, newspapers like the New York Times were reporting that cocaine-crazed Negroes were attacking their white supervisors and raping white women. A couple of decades later in the 1930s, newspapers had stories of Mexican marijuana madness and Mexican workers sleeping on the job under the influence of marijuana. These images led to more and more stringent narcotics laws and enforcement policies in Black and Brown communities which live with us even today.
All the while, middle-class white people throughout the past century have enjoyed full access to medical narcotics prescribed by private doctors in such large volumes that, by the 1940s and 50s, white Americans were dying from barbiturate overdose rates that rival todays opioid overdose rates, said Hansen.
In the 1990s, corporate marketing campaigns flooded Oxycodone and other prescription opioids through the health care system, addicting large numbers of white middle-class people in suburbia and rural regions. When new controls such as drug monitoring laws, tightened prescribing, and tamper-resistant drug formulations were put in place, white drug userswere cut off from their prescription pharmaceuticals and began turning to street heroin as a substituteand overdosing in ever-larger numbers, creating the current crisis.
This put heroin in a really unprecedented position, said Hansen. It was not a popular political response to criminalize white, middle-class opioid users. The surprising new face of addiction was reported in the media with lots of humanizing stories of college athletes, housewives, and schoolteachers who were unwittingly addicted to pills, and ultimately heroin. This publicity built support for local decriminalization of heroin and other opioids in white, largely affluent neighborhoods whose empowered residents collaborate with local law enforcement and district attorneys to divert people arrested on low-level drug charges to sentencing in treatment and, in some cases, peer support.
So, Hansen continued, we get Good Samaritan laws protecting people who call 911 in case of an overdose. Out of this moment of selective racialized decriminalization, we get bipartisan national support for the medicalization of heroin as well as opioid addiction by clinically maintaining patients on the opioid Buprenorphine. White patients with opioid use disorder are three to four times as likely as Black patients with opioid use disorder to get Buprenorphine. And those white patients who get it are most likely to pay out of pocket for very expensive patented medication or with private insurance.
Were talking about a middle-class and affluent market for Buprenorphine and, therefore, middle-class, white, and affluent constituency for selective medicalization of addiction, said Hansen. None of this disparity was accidental in any way. It was deliberate. The medicalized alternative response to an emerging white heroin problem was crafted to handle the anomaly of the racial crossover of heroin and the image of heroin after a century of drug policy that separated illegal Black and Brown drug useand drug use from legal white medications.
Michael Botticelli pointed to the difference between policies related to methadone and buprenorphine. One of the things that came out of the Nixon administration was a tremendous expansion in the use of methadone, he said. In keeping with those policies, its no surprise that methadone is probably one of the most highly restricted medications to ever exist. Its highly regulated and highly stigmatized. Many, including myself, have talked about the racial underpinnings of those methadone regulations. And I think at the federal level, its one of the things we could really focus on. Methadone regulations havent been updated in close to 60 years and its really a time for an overhaul of those regulations, because it could have an immediate impact.
Kassandra Frederique, who has been with the Drug Policy Alliance (DPA) for 11years, works to create coalitions focused on changing various drug policies. But a big issue in the current opioid epidemic is that communities of color have difficulty engaging in drug policy discussions or getting their issues recognized.
Lets be really clear, said Frederique, the overdose crisis is being exacerbated by structural issues of economic immobility and other barriers. Theres a lot of unlearning that has to happen when were doing advocacy around policymaking and the opioid crisis. Some people who are impacted now are saying, look, what happened in the past is hard and terrible but were here now. Lets move forward. Theyre coming with their pain and their trauma. But communities of color are asked to to come in as if were in an equitable placebut were not. Whats being ignored is that we have that long trauma.
A major rising issue in drug policy is the class-action court settlements with opioid manufacturers, distributors, and pharmacies that will sendmoney into the states for uses related to drug addiction and treatment.
I am often in places where people are talking about the opioid settlement, and the advocacy around it is white, said Frederique. The conversation is that the communities with the most need are white ones. They say, opioid impacted us most, we are the ones most hurt and we deserve the money. So, were in this moment when some think that only white families lost people to overdoses. At the same time, because of the historical inaccuracies and stigma, it makes it hard for families of color to say but I lost my kids to overdose, too because they dont get the same compassion back. Its a different level of scrutiny on that family of color than on white, upper middle-class suburban families.
Hansen pointed out: The current opioid class action lawsuits really do use a logic of reparation. Predominantly white, suburban and rural residents were hard hit early on in the opioid epidemic, but we know the demographics are changing. We know Black people have the fastest rising overdose rate in the country right now. And there are several states actually in which they have a higher absolute overdose rate than white Americans.
Nevertheless, the impression that the opioid overdose crisis was a white one continues to lead to a logic of reparations for white communities, Hansen said. And thats what flows out of the discourse around Depths of Despairthe fact that people are overdosing because they are largely in white communities that have been abandoned by manufacturing, mining companies, and other industries. Left out of that logicare Black and Brown people who have long suffered from all kinds of repressive narcotics policies, and so I do think if were going to take on a logic of reparations, we actually have to look at the history of who has been very much harmed by drug policies as well as pharmaceutical marketing, and apply that logic in a way thats very conscious of racial justice. That is exactly what has been missing from that discourse in the class action opioid lawsuits: a racial justice frame. We would have to insert that and look at investing not only in classical treatment and medications, but actually in all of the social structural drivers of overdose and the individual and community harms of opioid and narcotics use.
Another major focus for Frederiqueand the DPA, a non-profit that works to ground national drug policy around evidence, compassion, justice, and health, is the decriminalization of drug use and an end to using prisons and jails as major addiction treatment facilities.
The change we need to move forward, Frederiquesaid, is to reduce the role of criminalization when it comes to issues of health, Frederique said. We are pushing back on the concept that the criminal justice system is an appropriate vector for health care. Some of the largest facilities for either mental health or drugs are local jails and prisons. That is a failure, not an innovation.
Providing a historical inside-policymaking view, former ONDCP Director Botticelli remembered that the Obama administration effort was to move away from a War on Drugs approach and really focus on drug policy as a health-related issue and not as a criminal justice issue. It really was the implementation of the Affordable Care Act and its mandate to include substance use disorder treatment as an essential benefit, where we really saw, and even tried to approximate, parity between demand-reduction approaches, public health strategies, and law enforcement supply-reduction strategies.
Botticelli said he also recently went back and looked through our drug control strategies to see if there was particular mention in terms of equity-based or anti-racist strategy and there wasnt. Certainly, there was an acknowledgement of policies that had a disproportionate impact on people of color. But really, unfortunately, it didnt include specific goals and specific strategies that dealt squarely with this issue. Thats regrettable for me.
See original here:
Posted in War On Drugs
Comments Off on The War on Drugs as Structural Racism – Penn LDI
The Phony War on Drugs – The New York Times
Posted: at 3:30 pm
He is comfortable telling precartel narco anecdotes that he uncovered in dusty archives, but he skims over some messy details of recent atrocities. For instance, he does not identify Cardinal Posadas by name but refers to the shooting of the popes representative in Mexico, apparently confusing the cardinal with Geronimo Prigione, the papal nuncio whom Posadas was reportedly meeting the day he was killed.
Smith makes a strong case that the awful escalation of violence is not so much in the DNA of trading in narcotics as in the DNA of prohibiting the trade. For decades, Mexican authorities treated narcotics as a source of revenue. As early as 1915, Esteban Cant, the appointed governor of Baja California, collected a 3.5 peso tax on every kilogram of opium imported from China and demanded a share of protection racket payments, using the money to build roads, parks and a functioning postal service.
Such a morally questionable approach was considered justifiable because, until recently, Mexico had no drug-addiction problem of its own. So long as the drugs went north, what was the harm? In the 1940s, freethinkers got the Mexican government to experiment with legalizing marijuana and permitting dispensaries to give addicts morphine, until the United States quickly forced a reversal.
But as profits increased, competition for protection schemes intensified and eventually engulfed the federal government. The corruption and violence described in the books final section, Into the Abyss, 1990-2020, is apocalyptic. By early 1997, even the Mexican Army general in charge of the nations war on drugs was taking payments to protect the cartels.
It didnt stop there. The biggest drug lords now run their own rackets, unleashing their armed wings against opposing gangs that try to muscle in on their territories. Mexicos murder rate more than doubled during the tough-on-drugs presidency of Felipe Caldern. The cartels spread their infection to car theft rings, kidnappers and illegal loggers, and then demanded protection payments from legitimate businesses. They even stalked Mexican elective politics. Just this past June, 35 candidates for local office were killed as cartels ensured that their own candidates won.
Smith ends not with policy recommendations but with the bleakest of predictions: A century and counting, the Mexican drug trade shows no signs of slowing.
Continue reading here:
Posted in War On Drugs
Comments Off on The Phony War on Drugs – The New York Times
Timeline: 50 Years of Spaceflight | Space
Posted: at 3:17 pm
On Oct. 4, 2007, the Space Age celebrated the 50th anniversary of the historic launch of Sputnik, the first artificial satellite, by the former Soviet Union.
The space shot also launched the Space Race to the moon between the United States and the Soviet Union. But despite that turbulent beginning, the initial launch has led to five decades of triumphs and tragedies in space science and exploration.
Below is a timeline by Space News and SPACE.com chronicling the first 50 years of spaceflight. You are invited to walk through the half century of space exploration and click related links for more in depth information:
Sometime in the 11th century: China combines sulfur, charcoal and saltpeter (potassium nitrate) to make gunpowder, the first fuel used to propel early rockets in Chinese warfare.
July 4, 1054: Chinese astronomers observe the supernova in Taurus that formed the Crab Nebula.
Mid-1700s: Hyder Ali, the Sultan of Mysome in India, begins manufacturing rockets sheathed in iron, not cardboard or paper, to improve their range and stability.
March 16, 1926: Robert Goddard, sometimes referred to as the "Father of Modern Rocketry," launches the first successful liquid-fueled rocket.
July 17, 1929: Robert Goddard launches a rocket that carries with it the first set of scientific tools a barometer and a camera in Auburn, Mass. The launch was Goddard's fourth.
Feb. 18, 1930: The dwarf planet Pluto is discovered by American astronomer Clyde Tombaugh at Lowell Observatory in Flagstaff, Ariz.
Oct. 3, 1942: Germany successfully test launches the first ballistic missile, the A4, more commonly known as the V-2, and later uses it near the end of European combat in World War II.
Sep. 29, 1945: Wernher von Braun arrives at Ft. Bliss, Texas, with six other German rocket specialists.
Oct. 14, 1947: American test pilot Chuck Yeager breaks the sound barrier for the first time in the X-1, also known as Glamorous Glennis.
Oct. 4, 1957: A modified R-7 two-stage ICBM launches the satellite Sputnik 1 from Tyuratam. The Space Race between the Soviet Union and the United States begins.
Nov. 3, 1957: The Soviet Union launches Sputnik 2 with the first living passenger, the dog Laika, aboard.
Dec. 6, 1957: A Vanguard TV-3 carrying a grapefruit-sized satellite explodes at launch; a failed response to the Sputnik launch by the United States.
Jan. 31, 1958: Explorer 1, the first satellite with an onboard telemetry system, is launched by the United States into orbit aboard a Juno rocket and returns data from space.
Oct. 7, 1958: NASA Administrator T. Keith Glennan publicly announces NASA's manned spaceflight program along with the formation of the Space Task Group, a panel of scientist and engineers from space-policy organizations absorbed by NASA. The announcement came just six days after NASA was founded.
Jan. 2, 1959: The U.S.S.R. launches Luna 1, which misses the moon but becomes the first artificial object to leave Earth orbit.
Jan. 12, 1959: NASA awards McDonnell Corp. the contract to manufacture the Mercury capsules.
Feb. 28, 1959: NASA launches Discover 1, the U.S. first spy satellite, but it is not until the Aug. 11, 1960, launch of Discover 13 that film is recovered successfully.
May 28, 1959: The United States launches the first primates in space, Able and Baker, on a suborbital flight.
Aug. 7, 1959: NASA's Explorer 6 launches and provides the first photographs of the Earth from space.
Sept. 12, 1959: The Soviet Union's Luna 2 is launched and two days later is intentionally crashed into the Moon.
Sept. 17, 1959: NASA's X-15 hypersonic research plane, capable of speeds to Mach 6.7, makes its first powered flight.
Oct. 24, 1960: To rush the launch of a Mars probe before the Nov. 7 anniversary of the Bolshevik Revolution, Field Marshall Mitrofan Nedelin ignored several safety protocols and 126 people are killed when the R-16 ICBM explodes at the Baikonur Cosmodrome during launch preparations.
Feb. 12, 1961: The Soviet Union launches Venera to Venus, but the probe stops responding after a week.
April 12, 1961: Yuri Gagarin becomes the first man in space with a 108-minute flight on Vostok 1 in which he completed one orbit.
May 5, 1961: Mercury Freedom 7 launches on a Redstone rocket for a 15-minute suborbital flight, making Alan Shepard the first American in space.
May 25, 1961: In a speech before Congress, President John Kennedy announces that an American will land on the moon and be returned safely to Earth before the end of the decade.
Oct. 27, 1961: Saturn 1, the rocket for the initial Apollo missions, is tested for the first time.
Feb. 20, 1962: John Glenn makes the first U.S. manned orbital flight aboard Mercury 6.
June 7, 1962: Wernher von Braun backs the idea of a Lunar Orbit Rendezvous mission.
July 10, 1962: The United States launches Telstar 1, which enables the trans-Atlantic transmission of television signals.
June 14, 1962: Agreements are signed establishing the European Space Research Organisation and the European Launcher Development Organisation. Both eventually were dissolved.
July 28, 1962: The U.S.S.R launches its first successful spy satellite, designated Cosmos 7.
Aug. 27, 1962: Mariner 2 launches and eventually performs the first successful interplanetary flyby when it passes by Venus.
Sept. 29, 1962: Canada's Alouette 1 launches aboard a NASA Thor-Agena B rocket, becoming the first satellite from a country other than the United States or Soviet Union.
June 16, 1963: Valentina Tereshkova becomes the first woman to fly into space.
July 28, 1964: Ranger 7 launches and is the Ranger series' first success, taking photographs of the moon until it crashes into its surface four days later.
April 8, 1964: Gemini 1, a two-seat spacecraft system, launches in an unmanned flight.
Aug. 19, 1964: NASA's Syncom 3 launches aboard a Thor-Delta rocket, becoming the first geostationary telecommunications satellite.
Oct. 12, 1964: The Soviet Union launches Voskhod 1, a modified Vostok orbiter with a three-person crew.
March 18, 1965: Soviet cosmonaut Alexei Leonov makes the first spacewalk from the Voskhod 2 orbiter.
March 23, 1965: Gemini 3, the first of the manned Gemini missions, launches with a two-person crew on a Titan 2 rocket, making astronaut Gus Grissom the first man to travel in space twice.
June 3, 1965: Ed White, during the Gemini 4 mission, becomes the first American to walk in space.
July 14, 1965: Mariner 4 executes the first successful Mars flyby.
Aug. 21, 1965: Gemini 5 launches on an eight-day mission.
Dec. 15, 1965: Gemini 6 launches and performs a rendezvous with Gemini 7.
Jan. 14, 1966: The Soviet Union's chief designer, Sergei Korolev, dies from complications stemming from routine surgery, leaving the Soviet space program without its most influential leader of the preceding 20 years.
Feb. 3, 1966: The unmanned Soviet spacecraft Luna 9 makes the first soft landing on the Moon.
March 1, 1966: The Soviet Union's Venera 3 probe becomes the first spacecraft to land on the planetVenus, but its communications system failed before data could be returned.
March 16, 1966: Gemini 8 launches on a Titan 2 rocket and later docks with a previously launched Agena rocket the first docking between two orbiting spacecraft.
April 3, 1966: The Soviet Luna 10 space probe enters lunar orbit, becoming the first spacecraft to orbit the Moon.
June 2, 1966: Surveyor 1, a lunar lander, performs the first successful U.S. soft landing on the Moon.
Jan. 27, 1967: All three astronauts for NASA's Apollo 1 mission suffocate from smoke inhalationin a cabin fire during a launch pad test.
April 5, 1967: A review board delivers a damning report to NASA Administrator James Webb about problem areas in the Apollo spacecraft. The recommended modifications are completed by Oct. 9, 1968.
April 23, 1967: Soyuz 1 launches but myriad problems surface. The solar panels do not unfold, there are stability problems and the parachute fails to open on descent causing the death of Soviet cosmonaut Vladimir Komarov.
Oct. 11, 1968: Apollo 7, the first manned Apollo mission, launches on a Saturn 1 for an 11-day mission in Earth orbit. The mission also featured the first live TV broadcast of humans in space.
Dec. 21, 1968: Apollo 8 launches on a Saturn V and becomes the first manned mission to orbit the moon.
Jan. 16, 1969: Soyuz 4 and Soyuz 5 rendezvous and dock and perform the first in-orbit crew transfer.
March 3, 1969: Apollo 9 launches. During the mission, tests of the lunar module are conducted in Earth orbit.
May 22, 1969: Apollo 10's Lunar Module Snoopy comes within 8.6 miles (14 kilometers) of the moon's surface.
July 20, 1969: Six years after U.S. President John F. Kennedy's assassination, the Apollo 11 crew lands on the Moon, fulfilling his promise to put an American there by the end of the decade and return him safely to Earth.
Nov. 26, 1965: France launches its first satellite, Astrix, on a Diamant A rocket, becoming the third nation to do so.
Feb. 11, 1970: Japan's Lambda 4 rocket launches a Japanese test satellite, Ohsumi into orbit.
April 13, 1970: An explosion ruptures thecommand module of Apollo 13, days after launch and within reach of the moon. Abandoning the mission to save their lives, the astronauts climb into the Lunar Module and slingshot around the Moon to speed their return back to Earth.
April 24, 1970: The People's Republic of China launches its first satellite, Dong Fang Hong-1, on a Long March 1 rocket, becoming the fifth nation capable of launching its own satellites into space.
Sept. 12: 1970: The Soviet Union launches Luna 16, the first successful automated lunar sample retrieval mission.
April 19, 1971: A Proton rocket launches thefirst space station, Salyut 1, from Baikonur.
June 6, 1971: Soyuz 11 launches successfully, docking with Salyut 1. The three cosmonauts are killed during re-entry from a pressure leak in the cabin.
July 26, 1971: Apollo 15 launches with a Boeing-built Lunar Roving Vehicle and better life-support equipment to explore the Moon.
Oct. 28, 1971: The United Kingdom successfully launches its Prospero satellite into orbit on a Black Arrow rocket, becoming the sixth nation capable of launching its own satellites into space.
Nov. 13, 1971: Mariner 9 becomes the first spacecraft to orbit Mars and provides the first complete map of the planet's surface.
Jan. 5, 1972: U.S. President Richard Nixon announces that NASA is developing a reusable launch vehicle, the space shuttle.
March 3, 1972: Pioneer 10, the first spacecraft to leave the solar system, launches from Cape Kennedy, Fla.
Dec. 19, 1972: Apollo 17, the last mission to the moon, returns to Earth.
May 14, 1973: A Saturn V rocket launches Skylab, the United States' first space station.
March 29, 1974: Mariner 10 becomes the first spacecraft to fly by Mercury.
April 19, 1975: The Soviet Union launches India's first satellite, Aryabhata.
May 31, 1975: The European Space Agency is formed.
July 17 1975: Soyuz-19 and Apollo 18 dock.
Aug. 9, 1975: ESA launches its first satellite, Cos-B, aboard a Thor-Delta rocket.
Sept. 9, 1975: Viking 2, composed of a lander and an orbiter, launches for Mars.
July 20, 1976: The U.S. Viking 1 lands on Mars, becoming the first successful Mars lander.
Aug. 20, 1977: Voyager 2 is launched on a course toward Uranus and Neptune.
Sept. 5, 1977: Voyager 1 is launched to perform flybys of Jupiter and Saturn.
Sept. 29, 1977: Salyut 6 reaches orbit. It is the first space station equipped with docking stations on either end, which allow for two vehicles to dock at once, including the Progress supply ship.
Feb. 22, 1978: The first GPS satellite, Navstar 1, launches aboard an Atlas F rocket.
July 11, 1979: Skylab, the first American space station, crashes back to Earth in the sparsely populated grasslands of western Australia.
Sept. 1, 1979: Pioneer 11 becomes the first spacecraft to fly past Saturn.
Dec. 24, 1979: The French-built Ariane rocket, Europe's first launch vehicle, launches successfully.
July 18 1980: India launches its Rohini 1 satellite. By using its domestically developed SLV-3 rocket, India becomes the seventh nation capable of sending objects into space by itself.
April 12, 1981: Space Shuttle Columbia lifts off from Cape Canaveral, beginning the first space mission for NASA's new astronaut transportation system.
June 24, 1982: French air force test pilot Jean-Loup Chrtien launches to the Soviet Union's Salyut 7 aboard Soyuz T-6.
Nov. 11, 1982: Shuttle Columbia launches. During its mission, it deploys two commercial communications satellites.
June 18, 1983: Sally Ride aboard the Space Shuttle Challenger becomes the first American woman in space.
Feb. 7, 1984: Astronauts Bruce McCandless and Robert Stewart maneuver as many as 328 feet (100 meters) from the Space Shuttle Challenger using the Manned Maneuvering Unit, which contains small thrusters, in the first ever untethered spacewalks.
April 8, 1984: Challenger crew repairs the Solar Max satellite during a spacewalk.
Sept. 11: 1985: The International Cometary Explorer, launched by NASAin 1978, performs the first comet flyby.
Jan. 24, 1986: Voyager 2 completes the first and only spacecraft flyby of Uranus.
View original post here:
Posted in Space Travel
Comments Off on Timeline: 50 Years of Spaceflight | Space
Scientists Propose New, Faster Method of Interstellar Space Travel
Posted: at 3:17 pm
JWST's first deep field image. Image:Xinhua News Agency/Contributor via Getty Images
ABSTRACT breaks down mind-bending scientific research, future tech, new discoveries, and major breakthroughs.
Scientists have proposed a dazzling new mission to travel to the stars that is inspired by the elegant flights of seabirds, such as albatrosses, reports a new study. The interstellar concept mission would harness shifting winds generated by the Sun in order to accelerate a spacecraft to as much as 2 percent the speed of light within two years, allowing it to soar into the vast expanse beyond our solar system.
Humans have dreamed about leaving the solar system for thousands of years, but the mind-boggling distances between stars present major challenges to this goal. NASAs Voyager spacecraft, which were launched in 1977, are the first probes to enter interstellar space, but it will still take them tens of thousands of years to reach another star system.
Now, scientists led by Mathias Larrouturou, a spaceflight researcher at McGill University, have envisioned a much faster spacecraft that would mimic the dynamic soaring maneuvers of seabirds by gaining momentum from the solar wind, which is a stream of charged particles emitted by the Sun that creates a bubble around the solar system called the heliosphere.
The team found that their new concept for spacecraft propulsion that invokes dynamic soaring appears feasible for a vehicle to achieve velocities approaching 2 percent of [the speed of light] after a year and a half or 0.5 percent of [the speed of light] after 1 month, depending on its trajectory through the solar system, according to a recent study published in Frontiers of Space Technologies.
Inspired by the dynamic soaring maneuvers performed by seabirds and gliders in which differences in wind speed are exploited to gain velocity, in the proposed technique a lift-generating spacecraft circles between regions of the heliosphere that have different wind speeds, gaining energy in the process without the use of propellant and only modest onboard power requirements, Larrouturou and his colleagues said in the study.
The technique may comprise the first stage for a multistage mission to achieve true interstellar flight to other solar systems, the researchers added.
Many interstellar concept missions have been proposed over the years, from tiny chips that use high-powered lasers to propel them to the stars, to hulking generation ships that carry humans across the galaxy. Larrouturou and his colleagues imagine a different kind of architecture centered around a magnetohydrodynamic wing, which is an invisible structure made of magnetic fields that is somewhat analogous to the physical wing of a bird or plane, according to the study.
This spectral wing could theoretically be produced by two plasma magnets placed along an antenna measuring several feet in length. In the right parts of the solar system, the field created by the magnets could interact with solar wind flows in different directions in much the same way that birds exploit wind turbulence to create lift.
The result is a type of lift-generating wing, but without a physical structure, the team explained in the study. In dynamic soaring as practiced terrestrially, a lift-generating vehicle executes a maneuver that exploits the difference in wind speeds between two different regions of air, for example, the wind blowing over a hilltop and the quiescent air on the leeward side of the hill.
If a probe of this kind was placed at the heliopause, the tumultuous boundary to the heliosphere, it could leverage these mixed wind flows to accelerate to speeds of around 3,720 miles per second in a matter of years. In other parts of the solar system, the spacecraft could reach a quarter of that speed in only a month, according to the teams calculations.
A mission that hit the gas in this way could reach Jupiter in months, not years, and could potentially reach other stars in a matter of centuries. While this is still well beyond a human lifetime, it is a substantial improvement over the multi-millennia trips of slower spacecraft, like the Voyagers.
To that end, Larrouturou and his colleagues conclude their study with a technology roadmap for plasma magnet technology in practice. The team highlights two other concept missions, the Jupiter Observing Velocity Experiment (JOVE) and the Wind Rider Pathfinder Mission, as potential trailblazers of this novel approach to spaceflight.
These groundbreaking missions would provide validation that meaningful propulsive power could be extracted from the solar wind, providing a foundation for the more advanced concept of extracting electrical power from the wind for lift-generation, the researchers said.
The ability to generate large values of lift-to-drag ratio via interaction with the flow of interplanetary and interstellar medium over a spacecraft is found to be feasible, at least from the perspective of the physical principles involved, they concluded.
Original post:
Scientists Propose New, Faster Method of Interstellar Space Travel
Posted in Space Travel
Comments Off on Scientists Propose New, Faster Method of Interstellar Space Travel
Nietzsche, Friedrich | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Posted: at 3:16 pm
Nietzsche was a German philosopher, essayist, and cultural critic. His writings on truth, morality, language, aesthetics, cultural theory, history, nihilism, power, consciousness, and the meaning of existence have exerted an enormous influence on Western philosophy and intellectual history.
Nietzsche spoke of the death of God, and foresaw the dissolution of traditional religion and metaphysics. Some interpreters of Nietzsche believe he embraced nihilism, rejected philosophical reasoning, and promoted a literary exploration of the human condition, while not being concerned with gaining truth and knowledge in the traditional sense of those terms. However, other interpreters of Nietzsche say that in attempting to counteract the predicted rise of nihilism, he was engaged in a positive program to reaffirm life, and so he called for a radical, naturalistic rethinking of the nature of human existence, knowledge, and morality. On either interpretation, it is agreed that he suggested a plan for becoming what one is through the cultivation of instincts and various cognitive faculties, a plan that requires constant struggle with ones psychological and intellectual inheritances.
Nietzsche claimed the exemplary human being must craft his/her own identity through self-realization and do so without relying on anything transcending that lifesuch as God or a soul. This way of living should be affirmed even were one to adopt, most problematically, a radical vision of eternity, one suggesting the eternal recurrence of all events. According to some commentators, Nietzsche advanced a cosmological theory of will to power. But others interpret him as not being overly concerned with working out a general cosmology. Questions regarding the coherence of Nietzsches viewsquestions such as whether these views could all be taken together without contradiction, whether readers should discredit any particular view if proven incoherent or incompatible with others, and the likecontinue to draw the attention of contemporary intellectual historians and philosophers.
Because much of Nietzsches philosophical work has to do with the creation of selfor to put it in Nietzschean terms, becoming what one is some scholars exhibit uncommon interest in the biographical anecdotes of Nietzsches life. Taking this approach, however, risks confusing aspects of the Nietzsche legend with what is important in his philosophical work, and many commentators are rightly skeptical of readings derived primarily from biographical anecdotes.
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche was born October 15, 1844, the son of Karl Ludwig and Franziska Nietzsche. Karl Ludwig Nietzsche was a Lutheran Minister in the small Prussian town of Rcken, near Leipzig. When young Friedrich was not quite five, his father died of a brain hemorrhage, leaving Franziska, Friedrich, a three-year old daughter, Elisabeth, and an infant son. Friedrichs brother died unexpectedly shortly thereafter (reportedly, the legend says, fulfilling Friedrichs dream foretelling of the tragedy). These events left young Friedrich the only male in a household that included his mother, sister, paternal grandmother and an aunt, although Friedrich drew upon the paternal guidance of Franziskas father. Young Friedrich also enjoyed the camaraderie of a few male playmates.
Upon the loss of Karl Ludwig, the family took up residence in the relatively urban setting of Naumburg, Saxony. Friedrich gained admittance to the prestigious Schulpforta, where he received Prussias finest preparatory education in the Humanities, Theology, and Classical Languages. Outside school, Nietzsche founded a literary and creative society with classmates including Paul Deussen (who was later to become a prominent scholar of Sanskrit and Indic Studies). In addition, Nietzsche played piano, composed music, and read the works of Emerson and the poet Friedrich Hlderlin, who was relatively unknown at the time.
In 1864 Nietzsche entered the University of Bonn, spending the better part of that first year unproductively, joining a fraternity and socializing with old and new acquaintances, most of whom would fall out of his life once he regained his intellectual focus. By this time he had also given up Theology, dashing his mothers hopes of a career in the ministry for him. Instead, he choose the more humanistic study of classical languages and a career in Philology. In 1865 he followed his major professor, Friedrich Ritschl, from Bonn to the University of Leipzig and dedicated himself to the studious life, establishing an extracurricular society there devoted to the study of ancient texts. Nietzsches first contribution to this group was an essay on the Greek poet, Theognis, and it drew the attention of Professor Ritschl, who was so impressed that he published the essay in his academic journal, Rheinisches Museum. Other published writings by Nietzsche soon followed, and by 1868 (after a year of obligatory service in the Prussian military), young Friedrich was being promoted as something of a phenomenon in classical scholarship by Ritschl, whose esteem and praise landed Nietzsche a position as Professor of Greek Language and Literature at the University of Basel in Switzerland, even though the candidate had not yet begun writing his doctoral dissertation. The year was 1869 and Friedrich Nietzsche was 24 years old.
At this point in his life, however, Nietzsche was a far cry from the original thinker he would later become, since neither he nor his work had matured. Swayed by public opinion and youthful exuberance, he briefly interrupted teaching in 1870 to join the Prussian military, serving as a medical orderly at the outbreak of the Franco-Prussian War. His service was cut short, however, by severe bouts of dysentery and diphtheria. Back in Basel, his teaching responsibilities at the University and a nearby Gymnasium consumed much of his intellectual and physical energy. He became acquainted with the prominent cultural historian, Jacob Burkhardt, a well-established member of the university faculty. But, the person exerting the most influence on Nietzsche at this point was the artist, Richard Wagner, whom Nietzsche had met while studying in Leipzig. During the first half of the decade, Wagner and his companion, Cosima von Blow, frequently entertained Nietzsche at Triebschen, their residence near Lake Lucerne, and then later at Bayreuth.
It is commonplace to say that at one time Nietzsche looked to Wagner with the admiration of a dutiful son. This interpretation of their relationship is supported by the fact that Wagner would have been the same age as Karl Ludwig, had the elder Nietzsche been alive. It is also commonplace to note that Nietzsche was in awe of the artists excessive displays of a fiery temperament, bravado, ambition, egoism, and loftiness typical qualities demonstrating genius in the nineteenth century. In short, Nietzsche was overwhelmed by Wagners personality. A more mature Nietzsche would later look back on this relationship with some regret, although he never denied the significance of Wagners influence on his emotional and intellectual path, Nietzsches estimation of Wagners work would alter considerably over the course of his life. Nonetheless, in light of this relationship, one can easily detect Wagners presence in much of Nietzsches early writings, particularly in the latter chapters of The Birth of Tragedy and in the first and fourth essays of 1874s Untimely Meditations. Also, Wagners supervision exerted considerable editorial control over Nietzsches intellectual projects, leading him to abandon, for example, 1873s Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, which Wagner scorned because of its apparent irrelevance to his own work. Such pressures continued to bridle Nietzsche throughout the so-called early period. He broke free of Wagners dominance once and for all in 1877, after a series of emotionally charged episodes. Nietzsches fallout with Wagner, who had moved to Bayreuth by this time, led to the publication of 1878s Human, All-Too Human, one of Nietzsches most pragmatic and un-romantic textsthe original title page included a dedication to Voltaire and a quote from Descartes. If Nietzsche intended to use this text as a way of alienating himself from the Wagnerian circle, he surely succeeded. Upon its arrival in Bayreuth, the text ended this personal relationship with Wagner.
It would be an exaggeration to say that Nietzsche was not developing intellectually during the period, prior to 1877. In fact, figures other than Wagner drew Nietzsches interest and admiration. In addition to attending Burkhardts lectures at Basel, Nietzsche studied Greek thought from the Pre-Socratics to Plato, and he learned much about the history of philosophy from Friedrich Albert Langes massive History of Materialism, which Nietzsche once called a treasure trove of historical and philosophical names, dates, and currents of thought. In addition, Nietzsche was taken by the persona of the philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer, which Nietzsche claimed to have culled from close readings of the two-volume magnum opus, The World as Will and Representation.
Nietzsche discovered Schopenhauer while studying in Leipzig. Because his training at Schulpforta had elevated him far above most of his classmates, he frequently skipped lectures at Leipzig in order to devote time to [CE1] Schopenhauers philosophy. For Nietzsche, the most important aspect of this philosophy was the figure from which it emanated, representing for him the heroic ideal of a man in the life of thought: a near-contemporary thinker participating in that great and noble republic of genius, spanning the centuries of free thinking sages and creative personalities. That Nietzsche could not countenance Schopenhauers ethical pessimism and its negation of the will was recognized by the young man quite early during this encounter. Yet, even in Nietzsches attempts to construct a counter-posed pessimism of strength affirming the will, much of Schopenhauers thought remained embedded in Nietzsches philosophy, particularly during the early period. Nietzsches philosophical reliance on genius, his cultural-political visions of rank and order through merit, and his self-described (and later self-rebuked) metaphysics of art all had Schopenhauerian underpinnings. Also, Birth of Tragedys well-known dualism between the cosmological/aesthetic principles of Dionysus and Apollo, contesting and complimenting each other in the tragic play of chaos and order, confusion and individuation, strikes a familiar chord to readers acquainted with Schopenhauers description of the world as will and representation.
Despite these similarities, Nietzsches philosophical break with Schopenhauerian pessimism was as real as his break with Wagners domineering presence was painful. Ultimately, however, such triumphs were necessary to the development and liberation of Nietzsche as thinker, and they proved to be instructive as Nietzsche later thematized the importance of self-overcoming for the project of cultivating a free spirit.
The middle and latter part of the 1870s was a time of great upheaval in Nietzsches personal life. In addition to the turmoil with Wagner and related troubles with friends in the artists circle of admirers, Nietzsche suffered digestive problems, declining eyesight, migraines, and a variety of physical aliments, rendering him unable to fulfill responsibilities at Basel for months at a time. After publication of Birth of Tragedy, and despite its perceived success in Wagnerian circles for trumpeting the masters vision for Das Kunstwerk der Zukunft (The Art Work of the Future) Nietzsches academic reputation as a philologist was effectively destroyed due in large part to the works apparent disregard for scholarly expectations characteristic of nineteenth-century philology. Birth of Tragedy was mocked as Zukunfts-Philologie (Future Philology) by Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, an up-and-coming peer destined for an illustrious career in Classicism, and even Ritschl characterized it as a work of megalomania. For these reasons, Nietzsche had difficulty attracting students. Even before the publication of Birth of Tragedy, he had attempted to re-position himself at Basel in the department of philosophy, but the University apparently never took such an endeavor seriously. By 1878, his circumstances at Basel deteriorated to the point that neither the University nor Nietzsche was very much interested in seeing him continue as a professor there, so both agreed that he should retire with a modest pension [CE2] . He was 34 years old and now apparently liberated, not only from his teaching duties and the professional discipline he grew to despise, but also from the emotional and intellectual ties that dominated him during his youth. His physical woes, however, would continue to plague him for the remainder of his life.
After leaving Basel, Nietzsche enjoyed a period of great productivity. And, during this time, he was never to stay in one place for long, moving with the seasons, in search of relief for his ailments, solitude for his work, and reasonable living conditions, given his very modest budget. He often spent summers in the Swiss Alps in Sils Maria, near St. Moritz, and winters in Genoa, Nice, or Rappollo on the Mediterranean coast. Occasionally, he would visit family and friends in Naumburg or Basel, and he spent a great deal of time in social discourse, exchanging letters with friends and associates.
In the latter part of the 1880s, Nietzsches health worsened, and in the midst of an amazing flourish of intellectual activity which produced On the Genealogy of Morality, Twilight of the Idols, The Anti-Christ, and several other works (including preparation for what was intended to be his magnum opus, a work that editors later titled Will to Power) Nietzsche suffered a complete mental and physical breakdown. The famed moment at which Nietzsche is said to have succumbed irrevocably to his ailments occurred January 3, 1889 in Turin (Torino) Italy, reportedly outside Nietzsches apartment in the Piazza Carlos Alberto while embracing a horse being flogged by its owner.
After spending time in psychiatric clinics in Basel and Jena, Nietzsche was first placed in the care of his mother, and then later his sister (who had spent the latter half of the 1880s attempting to establish a racially pure German colony in Paraguay with her husband, the anti-Semitic political opportunist Bernhard Foerster). By the early 1890s, Elisabeth had seized control of Nietzsches literary remains, which included a vast amount of unpublished writings. She quickly began shaping his image and the reception of his work, which by this time had already gained momentum among academics such as Georg Brandes. Soon the Nietzsche legend would grow in spectacular fashion among popular readers. From Villa Silberblick, the Nietzsche home in Weimar, Elisabeth and her associates managed Friedrichs estate, editing his works in accordance with her taste for a populist decorum and occasionally with an ominous political intent that (later researchers agree) corrupted the original thought[CE3] . Unfortunately, Friedrich experienced little of his fame, having never recovered from the breakdown of late 1888 and early 1889. His final years were spent at Villa Silberblick in grim mental and physical deterioration, ending mercifully August 25, 1900. He was buried in Rcken, near Leipzig. Elisabeth spent one last year in Paraguay in 1892-93 before returning to Germany, where she continued to exert influence over the perception of Nietzsches work and reputation, particularly among general readers, until her death in 1935. Villa Silberblick stands today as a monument, of sorts, to Friedrich and Elisabeth, while the bulk of Nietzsches literary remains is held in the Goethe-Schiller Archiv, also in Weimar.
Nietzsche scholars commonly divide his work into periods, usually with the implication that discernable shifts in Nietzsches circumstances and intellectual development justify some form of periodization in the corpus. The following division is typical:
(i.) before 1869the juvenilia
Cautious Nietzsche biographers work to separate the facts of Nietzsches life from myth, and while a major part of the Nietzsche legend holds that Friedrich was a precocious child, writings from his youth bear witness to that part of the story. During this time Nietzsche was admitted into the prestigious Gymnasium Schulpforta; he composed music, wrote poetry and plays, and in 1863 produced an autobiography (at the age of 19). He also produced more serious and accomplished works on themes related to philology, literature, and philosophy. By 1866 he had begun contributing articles to a major philological journal, Rheinisches Museum, edited by Nietzsches esteemed professor at Bonn and Leipzig, Friedrich Ritschl. With Ritschls recommendation, Nietzsche was appointed professor of Greek Language and Literature at the University of Basel in January 1869.
(ii.) 1869-1876the early period
Nietzsches writings during this time reflect interests in philology, cultural criticism, and aesthetics. His inaugural public lecture at Basel in May 1869, Homer and Classical Philology brought out aesthetic and scientific aspects of his discipline, portending Nietzsches attitudes towards science, art, philology and philosophy. He was influenced intellectually by the philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer and emotionally by the artist Richard Wagner. Nietzsches first published book, The Birth of Tragedy, appropriated Schopenhaurian categories of individuation and chaos in an elucidation of primordial aesthetic drives represented by the Greek gods Apollo and Dionysus. This text also included a Wagnerian precept for cultural flourishing: society must cultivate and promote its most elevated and creative typesthe artistic genius. In the Preface to a later edition of this work, Nietzsche expresses regret for having attempted to elaborate a metaphysics of art. In addition to these themes, Nietzsches interest during this period extended to Greek philosophy, intellectual history, and the natural sciences, all of which were significant to the development of his mature thought. Nietzsches second book-length project, The Untimely Meditations, contains four essays written from 1873-1876. It is a work of acerbic cultural criticism, encomia to Schopenhauer and Wagner, and an unexpectedly idiosyncratic analysis of the newly developing historical consciousness. A fifth meditation on the discipline of philology is prepared but left unpublished. Plagued by poor health, Nietzsche is released from teaching duties in February 1876 (his affiliation with the university officially ends in 1878 and he is granted a small pension).
(iii.) 1877-1882the middle period
During this time Nietzsche liberated himself from the emotional grip of Wagner and the artists circle of admirers, as well as from those ideas which (as he claims in Ecce Homo) did not belong to him in his nature (Human All Too Human: With Two Supplements 1). Reworking earlier themes such as tragedy in philosophy, art and truth, and the human exemplar, Nietzsches thinking now comes into sharper focus, and he sets out on a philosophical path to be followed the remainder of his productive life. In this periods three published works Human, All-Too Human (1878-79), Dawn (1881), and The Gay Science (1882), Nietzsche takes up writing in an aphoristic style, which permits exploration of a variety of themes. Most importantly, Nietzsche lays out a plan for becoming what one is through the cultivation of instincts and various cognitive faculties, a plan that requires constant struggle with ones psychological and intellectual inheritances. Nietzsche discovers that one thing is needful for the exemplary human being: to craft an identity from otherwise dissociated events bringing forth the horizons of ones existence. Self-realization, as it is conceived in these texts, demands the radicalization of critical inquiry with a historical consciousness and then a retrograde step back (Human aphorism 20) from what is revealed in such examinations, insofar as these revelations threaten to dissolve all metaphysical realities and leave nothing but the abysmal comedy of existence. A peculiar kind of meaningfulness is thus gained by the retrograde step: it yields a purpose for existence, but in an ironic form, perhaps esoterically and without ground; it is transparently nihilistic to the man with insight, but suitable for most; susceptible to all sorts of suspicion, it is nonetheless necessary and for that reason enforced by institutional powers. Nietzsche calls the one who teaches the purpose of existence a tragic hero (GS 1), and the one who understands the logic of the retrograde step a free spirit. Nietzsches account of this struggle for self-realization and meaning leads him to consider problems related to metaphysics, religion, knowledge, aesthetics, and morality.
(iv.) Post-1882the later period
Nietzsche transitions into a new period with the conclusion of The Gay Science (Book IV) and his next published work, the novel Thus Spoke Zarathustra, produced in four parts between 1883 and 1885. Also in 1885 he returns to philosophical writing with Beyond Good and Evil. In 1886 he attempts to consolidate his inquiries through self-criticism in Prefaces written for the earlier published works, and he writes a fifth book for The Gay Science. In 1887 he writes On the Genealogy of Morality. In 1888, with failing health, he produces several texts, including The Twilight of the Idols, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, and two works concerning his prior relationship with Wagner. During this period, as with the earlier ones, Nietzsche produces an abundance of materials not published during his lifetime. These works constitute what is referred to as Nietzsches Nachlass. (For years this material has been published piecemeal in Germany and translated to English in various collections.) Philosophically, during this period, Nietzsche continues his explorations on morality, truth, aesthetics, history, power, language and identity. For some readers, he appears to be broadening the scope of his ideas to work out a cosmology involving the all encompassing will to power and the curiously related and enigmatic eternal recurrence of the same. Prior claims regarding the retrograde step are re-thought, apparently in favor of seeking some sort of breakthrough into the abyss of light (Zarathustras Before Sunrise) or in an encounter with decadence (Expeditions of a Untimely Man 43, in Twilight of the Idols). The intent here seems to be an overcoming or dissolution of metaphysics. These developments are matters of contention, however, as some commentators maintain that statements regarding Nietzsches cosmological vision are exaggerated. And, some will even deny that he achieves (nor even attempts) the overcoming described above. Despite such complaints, interpreters of Nietzsche continue to reference these ineffable concepts.
Nietzsches work in the beginning was heavily influenced, either positively or negatively, by the events of his young life. His early and on-going interest in the Greeks, for example, can be attributed in part to his Classical education at Schulpforta, for which he was well-prepared as a result of his familys attempts to steer him into the ministry. Nietzsches intense association with Wagner no doubt enhanced his orientation towards the philosophy of Schopenhauer, and it probably promoted his work in aesthetics and cultural criticism. These biographical elements came to bear on Nietzsches first major works, while the middle period amounts to a confrontation with many of these influences. In Nietzsches later writings we find the development of concepts that seem less tangibly related to the biographical events of his life.
Lets outline four of these concepts, but not before adding a word of caution regarding how this outline should be received. Nietzsche asserts in the opening section of Twilight of the Idols that he mistrusts systematizers (Maxims and Arrows 26), which is taken by some readers to be a declaration of his fundamental stance towards philosophical systems, with the additional inference that nothing resembling such a system must be permitted to stand in interpretations of his thought. Although it would not be illogical to say that Nietzsche mistrusted philosophical systems, while nevertheless building one of his own, some commentators point out two important qualifications. First, the meaning of Nietzsches stated mistrust in this brief aphorism can and should be treated with caution. In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche claims that philosophers today, after millennia of dogmatizing about absolutes, now have a duty to mistrust philosophys dogmatizing tendencies (BGE 34). Yet, earlier in that same text, Nietzsche claimed that all philosophical interpretations of nature are acts of will power (BGE 9) and that his interpretations are subject to the same critique (BGE 22). In Thus Spoke Zarathustras Of Involuntary Bliss we find Zarathustra speaking of his own mistrust, when he describes the happiness that has come to him in the blissful hour of the third part of that book. Zarathustra attempts to chase away this bliss while waiting for the arrival of his unhappiness, but his happiness draws nearer and nearer to him, because he does not chase after it. In the next scene we find Zarathustra dwelling in the light abyss of the pure open sky, before sunrise. What then is the meaning of this mistrust? At the very least, we can say that Nietzsche does not intend it to establish a strong and unmovable absolute, a negative-system, from which dogma may be drawn. Nor, possibly, is Nietzsches mistrust of systematizers absolutely clear. Perhaps it is a discredit to Nietzsche as a philosopher that he did not elaborate his position more carefully within this tension; or, perhaps such uncertainty has its own ground. Commentators such as Mueller-Lauter have noticed ambivalence in Nietzsches work on this very issue, and it seems plausible that Nietzsche mistrusted systems while nevertheless constructing something like a system countenancing this mistrust. He says something akin to this, after all, in Beyond Good and Evil, where it is claimed that even sciences truths are matters of interpretation, while admitting that this bold claim is also an interpretation and so much the better (aphorism 22). For a second cautionary note, many commentators will argue along with Richard Schacht that, instead of building a system, Nietzsche is concerned only with the exploration of problems, and that his kind of philosophy is limited to the interpretation and evaluation of cultural inheritances (1995). Other commentators will attempt to complement this sort of interpretation and, like Lwith, presume that the ground for Nietzsches explorations may also be examined. Lwith and others argue that this ground concerns Nietzsches encounter with historical nihilism. The following outline should be received, then, with the understanding that Nietzsches own iconoclastic nature, his perspectivism, and his life-long projects of genealogical critique and the revaluation of values, lend credence to those anti-foundational readings which seek to emphasize only those exploratory aspects of Nietzsches work while refuting even implicit submissions to an orthodox interpretation of the one Nietzsche and his one system of thought. With this caution, the following outline is offered as one way of grounding Nietzsches various explorations.
The four major concepts presented in this outline are:
Although Michael Gillespie makes a strong case that Nietzsche misunderstood nihilism, and in any event Nietzsches Dionysianism would be a better place to look for an anti-metaphysical breakthrough in Nietzsches corpus (1995, 178), commentators as varied in philosophical orientation as Heidegger and Danto have argued that nihilism is a central theme in Nietzsches philosophy. Why is this so? The constellation of Nietzsches fundamental concepts moves within his general understanding of modernitys historical situation in the late nineteenth century. In this respect, Nietzsches thought carries out the Kantian project of critique by applying the nineteenth centurys developing historical awareness to problems concerning the possibilities of knowledge, truth, and human consciousness. Unlike Kants critiques, Nietzsches examinations find no transcendental ego, given that even the categories of experience are historically situated and likewise determined. Unlike Hegels notion of historical consciousness, however, history for Nietzsche has no inherent teleology. All beginnings and ends, for Nietzsche, are thus lost in a flood of indeterminacy. As early as 1873, Nietzsche was arguing that human reason is only one of many peculiar developments in the ebb and flow of time, and when there are no more rational animals nothing of absolute value will have transpired (On truth and lies in a non-moral sense). Some commentators would prefer to consider these sorts of remarks as belonging to Nietzsches juvenilia. Nevertheless, as late as 1888s Reason in Philosophy from Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche derides philosophers who would make a fetish out of reason and retreat into the illusion of a de-historicized world. Such a philosopher is decadent, symptomatic of a declining life. Opposed to this type, Nietzsche valorizes the Dionysian artist whose sense of history affirms all that is questionable and terrible in existence.
Nietzsches philosophy contemplates the meaning of values and their significance to human existence. Given that no absolute values exist, in Nietzsches worldview, the evolution of values on earth must be measured by some other means. How then shall they be understood? The existence of a value presupposes a value-positing perspective, and values are created by human beings (and perhaps other value-positing agents) as aids for survival and growth. Because values are important for the well being of the human animal, because belief in them is essential to our existence, we oftentimes prefer to forget that values are our own creations and to live through them as if they were absolute. For these reasons, social institutions enforcing adherence to inherited values are permitted to create self-serving economies of power, so long as individuals living through them are thereby made more secure and their possibilities for life enhanced. Nevertheless, from time to time the values we inherit are deemed no longer suitable and the continued enforcement of them no longer stands in the service of life. To maintain allegiance to such values, even when they no longer seem practicable, turns what once served the advantage to individuals to a disadvantage, and what was once the prudent deployment of values into a life denying abuse of power. When this happens the human being must reactivate its creative, value-positing capacities and construct new values.
Commentators will differ on the question of whether nihilism for Nietzsche refers specifically to a state of affairs characterizing specific historical moments, in which inherited values have been exposed as superstition and have thus become outdated, or whether Nietzsche means something more than this. It is, at the very least, accurate to say that for Nietzsche nihilism has become a problem by the nineteenth century. The scientific, technological, and political revolutions of the previous two hundred years put an enormous amount of pressure on the old world order. In this environment, old value systems were being dismantled under the weight of newly discovered grounds for doubt. The possibility arises, then, that nihilism for Nietzsche is merely a temporary stage in the refinement of true belief. This view has the advantage of making Nietzsches remarks on truth and morality seem coherent from a pragmatic standpoint, in that with this view the problem of nihilism is met when false beliefs have been identified and corrected. Reason is not a value, in this reading, but rather the means by which human beings examine their metaphysical presuppositions and explore new avenues to truth.
Yet, another view will have it that by nihilism Nietzsche is pointing out something even more unruly at work, systemically, in the Western worlds axiomatic orientation. Heidegger, for example, claims that with the problem of nihilism Nietzsche is showing us the essence of Western metaphysics and its system of values (The Word of Nietzsche: God is dead). According to this view, Nietzsches philosophy of value, with its emphasis on the value-positing gesture, implies that even the concept of truth in the Western worldview leads to arbitrary determinations of value and political order and that this worldview is disintegrating under the weight of its own internal logic (or perhaps illogic). In this reading, the history of truth in the occidental world is the history of an error (Twilight of the Idols), harboring profoundly disruptive antinomies which lead, ultimately, to the undoing of the Western philosophical framework. This kind of systemic flaw is exposed by the historical consciousness of the nineteenth century, which makes the problem of nihilism seem all the more acutely related to Nietzsches historical situation. But to relegate nihilism to that situation, according to Heidegger, leaves our thinking of it incomplete.
Heidegger makes this stronger claim with the aid of Nietzsches Nachlass. Near the beginning of the aphorisms collected under the title, Will To Power (aphorism 2), we find this note from 1887: What does nihilism mean? That the highest values devalue themselves.The aim is lacking; Why? finds no answer. Here, Nietzsches answer regarding the meaning of nihilism has three parts.
(i) The first part makes a claim about the logic of values: ultimately, given the immense breadth of time, even the highest values devalue themselves. What does this mean? According to Nietzsche, the conceptual framework known as Western metaphysics was first articulated by Plato, who had pieced together remnants of a declining worldview, borrowing elements from predecessors such as Anaximander, Parmenides, and especially Socrates, in order to overturn a cosmology that had been in play from the days of Homer and which found its fullest and last expression in the thought of Heraclitus. Platos framework was popularized by Christianity, which added egalitarian elements along with the virtue of pity. The maturation of Western metaphysics occurs during modernitys scientific and political revolutions, wherein the effects of its inconsistencies, malfunctions, and mal-development become acute. At this point, according to Nietzsche, the highest values devalue themselves, as modernitys striving for honesty, probity, and courage in the search for truth, those all-important virtues inhabiting the core of scientific progress, strike a fatal blow against the foundational idea of absolutes. Values most responsible for the scientific revolution, however, are also crucial to the metaphysical system that modern science is destroying. Such values are threatening, then, to bring about the destruction of their own foundations. Thus, the highest values are devaluing themselves at the core. Most importantly, the values of honesty, probity, and courage in the search for truth no longer seem compatible with the guarantee, the bestowal, and the bestowing agent of an absolute value. Even the truth of truth now falls prey to the workings of nihilism, given that Western metaphysics now appears groundless in this logic.
For some commentators, this line of interpretation leaves Nietzsches revaluation of values lost in contradiction. What philosophical ground, after all, could support revaluation if this interpretation were accurate? For this reason, readers such as Clark work to establish a coherent theory of truth in Nietzsches philosophy, which can apparently be done by emphasizing various parts of the corpus to the exclusion of others. If, indeed, a workable epistemology may be derived from reading specific passages, and good reasons can be given for prioritizing those passages, then consistent grounds may exist for Nietzsche having leveled a critique of morality. Such readings, however, seem incompatible with Nietzsches encounter with historical nihilism, unless nihilism is taken to represent merely a temporary stage in the refinement of Western humanitys acquisition of knowledge.
With the stronger claim, however, Nietzsches critique of the modern situation implies that the highest values [necessarily] devalue themselves. Western metaphysics brings about its own disintegration, in working out the implications of its inner logic. Nietzsches name for this great and terrible event, capturing popular imagination with horror and disgust, is the death of God. Nietzsche acknowledges that a widespread understanding of this event, the great noon at which all shadows of God will be washed out, is still to come. In Nietzsches day, the God of the old metaphysics is still worshiped, of course, and would be worshiped, he predicted, for years to come. But, Nietzsche insisted, in an intellectual climate that demands honesty in the search for truth and proof as a condition for belief, the absence of foundations has already been laid bare. The dawn of a new day had broken, and shadows now cast, though long, were receding by the minute.
(ii) The second part of the answer to the question concerning nihilism states that the aim is lacking. What does this mean? In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche claims that the logic of an existence lacking inherent meaning demands, from an organizational standpoint, a value-creating response, however weak this response might initially be in comparison to how its values are then taken when enforced by social institutions (aphorisms 20-23). Surveys of various cultures show that humanitys most indispensable creation, the affirmation of meaning and purpose, lies at the heart of all fundamental values. Nihilism stands not only for that apparently inevitable process by which the highest values devalue themselves. It also stands for that moment of recognition in which human existence appears, ultimately, to be in vain. Nietzsches surveys of cultures and their values, his cultural anthropologies, are typically reductive in the extreme, attempting to reach the most important sociopolitical questions as neatly and quickly as possible. Thus, when examining so-called Jewish, Oriental, Roman, or Medieval European cultures Nietzsche asks, how was meaning and purpose proffered and secured here? How, and for how long, did the values here serve the living? What form of redemption was sought here, and was this form indicative of a healthy life? What may one learn about the creation of values by surveying such cultures? This version of nihilism then means that absolute aims are lacking and that cultures naturally attempt to compensate for this absence with the creation of goals.
(iii) The third part of the answer to the question concerning nihilism states that why? finds no answer. Who is posing the question here? Emphasis is laid on the one who faces the problem of nihilism. The problem of value-positing concerns the one who posits values, and this one must be examined, along with a corresponding evaluation of relative strengths and weaknesses. When, indeed, why? finds no answer, nihilism is complete. The danger here is that the value-positing agent might become paralyzed, leaving the call of lifes most dreadful question unanswered. In regards to this danger, Nietzsches most important cultural anthropologies examined the Greeks from Homer to the age of tragedy and the pre-Platonic philosophers. Here was evidence, Nietzsche believed, that humanity could face the dreadful truth of existence without becoming paralyzed. At every turn, the moment in which the Greek worlds highest values devalued themselves, when an absolute aim was shown to be lacking, the question why? nevertheless called forth an answer. The strength of Greek culture is evident in the gods, the tragic art, and the philosophical concepts and personalities created by the Greeks themselves. Comparing the creativity of the Greeks to the intellectual work of modernity, the tragic, affirmative thought of Heraclitus to the pessimism of Schopenhauer, Nietzsche highlights a number of qualitative differences. Both types are marked by the appearance of nihilism, having been drawn into the inevitable logic of value-positing and what it would seem to indicate. The Greek type nevertheless demonstrates the characteristics of strength by activating and re-intensifying the capacity to create, by overcoming paralysis, by willing a new truth, and by affirming the will. The other type displays a pessimism of weakness, passivity, and wearinesstraits typified by Schopenhauers life-denying ethics of the will turning against itself. In Nietzsches 1888 retrospection on the Birth of Tragedy in Ecce Homo, we read that Hellenism and Pessimism would have made a more precise title for the first work, because Nietzsche claims to have attempted to demonstrate how
the Greeks got rid of pessimismwith what they overcame it.Precisely tragedy is the proof that the Greeks were no pessimists: Schopenhauer blundered in this as he blundered in everything (The Birth of Tragedy in Ecce Homo section 1).
From Twilight of the Idols, also penned during that sublime year of 1888, Nietzsche writes that tragedy has to be considered the decisive repudiation of pessimism as Schopenhauer understood it:
affirmation of life, even in its strangest and sternest problems, the will to life rejoicing in its own inexhaustibility through the sacrifice of its highest typesthat is what I called Dionysian.beyond [Aristotelian] pity and terror, to realize in oneself the eternal joy of becomingthat joy which also encompasses joy in destruction (What I Owe the Ancients 5).
Nietzsche concludes the above passage by claiming to be the last disciple of the philosopher Dionysus (which by this time in Nietzsches thought came to encompass the whole of that movement which formerly distinguished between Apollo and Dionysus). Simultaneously, Nietzsche declares himself, with great emphasis, to be the teacher of the eternal recurrence.
The work to overcome pessimism is tragic in a two-fold sense: it maintains a feeling for the absence of ground, while responding to this absence with the creation of something meaningful. This work is also unmodern, according to Nietzsche, since modernity either has yet to ask the question why?, in any profound sense or, in those cases where the question has been posed, it has yet to come up with a response. Hence, a pessimism of weakness and an incomplete form of nihilism prevail in the modern epoch. Redemption in this life is denied, while an uncompleted form of nihilism remains the fundamental condition of humanity. Although the logic of nihilism seems inevitable, given the absence of absolute purpose and meaning, actively confronting nihilism and completing our historical encounter with it will be a sign of good health and the increased power of the spirit (Will to Power aphorism 22). Thus far, however, modernitys attempts to escape nihilism (in turning away) have only served to make the problem more acute (aphorism 28). Why, then, this failure? What does modernity lack?
How and why do nihilism and the pessimism of weakness prevail in modernity? Again, from the notebook of 1887 (Will to Power, aphorism 27), we find two conditions for this situation:
1. the higher species is lacking, i.e., those whose inexhaustible fertility and power keep up the faith in man.[and] 2. the lower species (herd, mass, society,) unlearns modesty and blows up its needs into cosmic and metaphysical values. In this way the whole of existence is vulgarized: insofar as the mass is dominant it bullies the exceptions, so they lose their faith in themselves and become nihilists.
With the fulfillment of European nihilism (which is no doubt, for Nietzsche, endemic throughout the Western world and anyplace touched by modernity), and the death of otherworldly hopes for redemption, Nietzsche imagines two possible responses: the easy response, the way of the herd and the last man, or the difficult response, the way of the exception, and the bermensch.
Ancillary to any discussion of the exception, per se, the compatibility of the bermensch concept with other movements in Nietzsches thought, and even the significance that Nietzsche himself placed upon it, has been the subject of intense debate among Nietzsche scholars. The terms appearance in Nietzsches corpus is limited primarily to Thus Spoke Zarathustra and works directly related to this text. Even here, moreover, the bermensch is only briefly and very early announced in the narrative, albeit with a tremendous amount of fanfare, before fading from explicit consideration. In addition to these problems, there are debates concerning the basic nature of the bermensch itself, whether ber- refers to a transitional movement or a transmogrified state of being, and whether Nietzsche envisioned the possibility of a community of bermenschen, as opposed to a solitary figure among lesser types. So, what should be made of Nietzsches so-called overman (or even superman) called upon to arrive after the death of God?
Whatever else may be said about the bermensch, Nietzsche clearly had in mind an exemplary figure and an exception among humans, one whose inexhaustible fertility and power keep up the faith in man. For some commentators, Nietzsches distinction between overman and the last man has political ramifications. The hope for an overman figure to appear would seem to be permissible for one individual, many, or even a social ideal, depending on the culture within which it appears. Modernity, in Nietzsches view, is in such a state of decadence that it would be fortunate, indeed, to see the emergence of even one such type, given that modern sociopolitical arrangements are more conducive to creating the egalitarian last man who blinks at expectations for rank, self-overcoming, and striving for greatness. The last men are the most harmful to the species because they preserve their existence as much at the expense of the truth as at the expense of the future (Why I am a Destiny in Ecce Homo 1). Although Nietzsche never lays out a precise political program from these ideas, it is at least clear that theoretical justifications for complacency or passivity are antithetical to his philosophy. What, then, may be said about Nietzsche as political thinker? Nietzsches political sympathies are definitely not democratic in any ordinary way of thinking about that sort of arrangement. Nor are they socialist or Marxist.
Nietzsches political sympathies have been called aristocratic, which is accurate enough only if one does not confuse the term with European royalty, landed gentry, old money or the like and if one keeps in mind the original Greek meaning of the term, aristos, which meant the good man, the man with power. A certain ambiguity exists, for Nietzsche, in the term good man. On the one hand, the modern, egalitarian good man, the last man, expresses hostility for those types willing to impose measures of rank and who would dare to want greatness and to strive for it. Such hostilities are born out of ressentiment and inherited from Judeo-Christian moral value systems. (Beyond Good and Evil 257-260 and On the Genealogy of Morals essay 1). Good in this sense is opposed to evil, and the good man is the one whose values support the herd and whose condemnations are directed at those whose thoughts and actions might disrupt the complacent normalcy of modern life. On the other hand, the kind of good man who might overcome the weak pessimism of herd morality, the man of strength, a man to confront nihilism, and thus a true benefactor to humanity, would be decidedly unmodern and out of season. Only such a figure would keep up the faith in man. For these reasons, some commentators have found in Nietzsche an existentialist program for the heroic individual dissociated in varying degrees from political considerations. Such readings however ignore or discount Nietzsches interest in historical processes and the unavoidable inference that although Nietzsches anti-egalitarianism might lead to questionably unmodern political conclusions, hierarchy nevertheless implies association.
The distinction between the good man of active power and the other type also points to ambiguity in the concept of freedom. For the hopeless, human freedom is conceived negatively in the freedom from restraints, from higher expectations, measures of rank, and the striving for greatness. While the higher type, on the other hand, understands freedom positively in the freedom for achievement, for revaluations of values, overcoming nihilism, and self-mastery.
Nietzsche frequently points to such exceptions as they have appeared throughout historyNapoleon is one of his favorite examples. In modernity, the emergence of such figures seems possible only as an isolated event, as a flash of lightening from the dark cloud of humanity. Was there ever a culture, in contrast to modernity, which saw these sorts of higher types emerge in congress as a matter of expectation and design? Nietzsches early philological studies on the Greeks, such as Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, The Pre-Platonic Philosophers, Homer on Competition, and The Greek State, concur that, indeed, the ancient world before Plato produced many exemplary human beings, coming forth independently of each other but hewn from the same stone, made possible by the fertile cultural milieu, the social expectation of greatness, and opportunities to prove individual merit in various competitive arenas. Indeed, Greek athletic contests, festivals of music and tragedy, and political life reflected, in Nietzsches view, a general appreciation for competition, rank, ingenuity, and the dynamic variation of formal structures of all sorts. Such institutions thereby promoted the elevation of human exemplars. Again, the point must be stressed here that the historical accuracy of Nietzsches interpretation of the Greeks is no more relevant to his philosophical schemata than, for example, the actual signing of a material document is to a contractarian political theory. What is important for Nietzsche, throughout his career, is the quick evaluation of social order and heirarchies, made possible for the first time in the nineteenth century by the newly developed historical sense (BGE 224) through which Nietzsche draws sweeping conclusions regarding, for example, the characteristics of various moral and religious epochs (BGE 32 and 55), which are themselves pre-conditioned by the material origins of consciousness, from which a pre-human animal acquires the capacity (even the right) to make promises and develops into the sovereign individual who then bears responsibility for his or her actions and thoughts (GM II.2).
Like these rather ambitious conclusions, Nietzsches valorization of the Greeks is partly derived from empirical evidence and partly confected in myth, a methodological concoction that Nietzsche draws from his philological training. If the Greeks, as a different interpretation would have them, bear little resemblance to Nietzsches reading, such a difference would have little relevance to Nietzsches fundamental thoughts. Later Nietzsche is also clear that his descriptions of the Greeks should not be taken programmatically as a political vision for the future (see for example GS 340).
The Greeks are one of Nietzsches best exemplars of hope against a meaningless existence, hence his emphasis on the Greek worlds response to the wisdom of Silenus in Birth of Tragedy. (ch. 5). If the sovereign individual represents historys ripest fruit, the most recent millennia have created, through rituals of revenge and punishment, a bad conscience. The human animal thereby internalizes material forces into feelings of guilt and duty, while externalizing a spirit thus created with hostility towards existence itself (GM II.21). Compared to this typically Christian manner of forming human experiences, the Greeks deified the animal in man and thereby kept bad conscience at bay (GM II.23).
In addition to exemplifying the Greeks in the early works, Nietzsche lionizes the artist-genius and the sage; during the middle period he writes confidently, at first, and then longingly about the scientist, the philosopher of the future, and the free spirit; Zarathustras decidedly sententious oratory heralds the coming of the bermensch; the periods in which revaluation comes to the fore finds value in the destructive influences of the madman, the immoralist, the buffoon, and even the criminal. Finally, Nietzsches last works reflect upon his own image, as the breaker of human history into two, upon Mr. Nietzsche, the anti-Christian, the self-anointed clever writer of great books, the creator of Zarathustra, the embodiment of human destiny and humanitys greatest benefactor: only after me, Nietzsche claims in Ecce Homo, is it possible to hope again (Why I am a Destiny 1). It should be cautioned that important differences exist in the way Nietzsche conceives of each of these various figures, differences that reflect the development of Nietzsches philosophical work throughout the periods of his life. For this reason, none of these exemplars should be confused for the others. The bombastic Mr. Nietzsche of Ecce Homo is no more the bermensch of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, for example, than the Zarathustra character is a pre-Platonic philosopher or the alienated, cool, sober, and contemptuous scientist is a tragic artist, although these figures will frequently share characteristics. Yet, a survey of these exceptions shows that Nietzsches philosophy, in his own estimation, needs the apotheosis of a human exemplar, perhaps to keep the search for meaning and redemption from abdicating the earth in metaphysical retreat, perhaps to avert the exhaustion of human creativity, to reawaken the instincts, to inspire the striving for greatness, to remind us that this has happened once and is therefore a possibility, or perhaps simply to bestow the honey offering of a very useful piece of folly. This need explains the meaning of the parodic fourth book of Zarathustra, which opens with the title character reflecting on the whole of his teachings: I am hewho once bade himself, and not in vain: Become what you are! The subtitle of Nietzsches autobiographical Ecce Homo, How One Becomes What One Is, strikes a similar chord.
The exemplar expresses hope not granted from metaphysical illusions. After sharpening the critique of art and genius during the positivistic period, Nietzsche seems more cautious about heaping praise upon specific historical figures and types, but even when he could no longer find an ideal exception, he nevertheless deemed it requisite to fabricate one in myth. Whereas exceptional humans of the past belong to an exalted republic of genius, those of the future, those belonging to human destiny, embody humanitys highest hopes. As a result of this development, some commentators will emphasize the philosophy of the future as one of Nietzsches most important ideas. Work pursued in service of the future constitutes for Nietzsche an earthly form of redemption. Yet, exemplars of type, whether in the form of isolated individuals like Napoleon, or of whole cultures like the Greeks, are not caught up in petty historical politics or similar mundane endeavors. According to Nietzsche in Twilight of the Idols, their regenerative powers are necessary for the work of interpreting the meaning and sequence of historical facts.
My Conception of the geniusGreat men, like great epochs, are explosive material in whom tremendous energy has been accumulated; their prerequisite has always been, historically and psychologically, that a protracted assembling, accumulating, economizing and preserving has preceded themthat there has been no explosion for a long time. If the tension in the mass has grown too great the merest accidental stimulus suffices to call the genius, the deed, the great destiny, into the world. Of what account then are circumstances, the epoch, the Zeitgeist, public opinion!Great human beings are necessary, the epoch in which they appear is accidental (Expeditions of an Untimely Man, 44).
It is with this understanding of the great man that Nietzsche, in Ecce Homo, proclaims even himself a great man, dynamite,breaking the history of humanity in two (Why I am a Destiny 1 and 8). A human exemplar, interpreted affirmatively in service of a hopeful future, is a great event denoting qualitative differences amidst the play of historical determinations. Thus, it belongs, in this reading, to Nietzsches cosmological vision of an indifferent nature marked occasionally by the boundary-stones of noble and sometimes violent uprisings.
To what extent is Nietzsche entitled to such a vision? Unlike nihilism, pessimism, and the death of God, which are historically, scientifically, and sometimes logically derived, Nietzsches yes-saying concepts seem to be derived from intuition, although Nietzsche will frequently support even these great hopes with bits of inductive reasoning. Nietzsche attempts to describe the logical structure of great events, as if a critical understanding of them pertains to their recurrence in modernity: great men have a historical and psychological prerequisite. Historically, there must be a time of waiting and gathering energy, as we find, for example, in the opening scene of Zarathustra. The great man and the great deed belong to a human destiny, one that emerges in situations of crisis and severe want. Psychologically, they are the effects of human energy stored and kept dormant for long periods of time in dark clouds of indifference. Primal energy gathers to a point before a cataclysmic event, like a chemical reaction with an electrical charge, unleashes some decisive, episodic force on all humanity. From here, the logic unfolds categorically: all great events, having occurred, are possibilities. All possibilities become necessities, given an infinite amount of time. Perhaps understanding this logic marks a qualitative difference in the way existence is understood. Perhaps this qualitative difference will spark the revaluation of values. When a momentous event takes place, the exception bolts from the cloud of normalcy as a point of extreme difference. In such ways, using this difference as a reference, as a boundary-stone on the river of eternal becoming, the meaning of the past is once again determined and the course of the future is set for a while, at least until a coming epoch unleashes the next great transvaluative event. Conditions for the occurrence of such events, and for the event of grasping this logic itself, are conceptualized, cosmologically in this reading, under the appellation will to power.
Before developing this reading further, it should be noted some commentators argue that the cosmological interpretation of will to power makes too strong a claim and that the extent of will to powers domain ought to be limited to what the idea might explain as a theory of moral psychology, as the principle of an anthropology regarding the natural history of morals, or as a response to evolutionary theories placed in the service of utility. Such commentators will maintain that Nietzsche either in no way intends to construct a new meta-theory, or if he does then such intentions are mistaken and in conflict with his more prescient insights. Indeed, much evidence exists to support each of these positions. As an enthusiastic reader of the French Moralists of the eighteenth century, Nietzsche held the view that all human actions are motivated by the desire to increase the feeling of power (GS 13). This view seems to make Nietzsches insights regarding moral psychology akin to psychological egoism and would thus make doubtful the popular notion that Nietzsche advocated something like an egoistic ethic. Nevertheless, with this bit of moral psychology, a debate exists among commentators concerning whether Nietzsche intends to make dubious morality per se or whether he merely endeavors to expose those life-denying ways of moralizing inherited from the beginning of Western thought. Nietzsche, at the very least, is not concerned with divining origins. He is interested, rather, in measuring the value of what is taken as true, if such a thing can be measured. For Nietzsche, a long, murky, and thereby misunderstood history has conditioned the human animal in response to physical, psychological, and social necessities (GM II) and in ways that have created additional needs, including primarily the need to believe in a purpose for its very existence (GS 1). This ultimate need may be uncritically engaged, as happens with the incomplete nihilism of those who wish to remain in the shadow of metaphysics and with the laisser aller of the last man who overcomes dogmatism by making humanity impotent (BGE 188). On the other hand, a critical engagement with history is attempted in Nietzsches genealogies, which may enlighten the historical consciousness with a sort of transparency regarding the drive for truth and its consequences for determining the human condition. In the more critical engagement, Nietzsche attempts to transform the need for truth and reconstitute the truth drive in ways that are already incredulous towards the dogmatizing tendency of philosophy and thus able to withstand the new suspicions (BGE 22 and 34). Thus, the philosophical exemplar of the future stands in contrast, once again, to the uncritical man of the nineteenth century whose hidden metaphysical principles of utility and comfort fail to complete the overcoming of nihilism (Ecce Homo, Why I am a Destiny 4). The question of whether Nietzsches transformation of physical and psychological need with a doctrine of the will to power, in making an affirmative principle out of one that has dissolved the highest principles hitherto, simply replaces one metaphysical doctrine with another, or even expresses completely all that has been implicit in metaphysics per se since its inception continues to draw the interest of Nietzsche commentators today. Perhaps the radicalization of will to power in this way amounts to no more than an account of this world to the exclusion of any other. At any rate, the exemplary type, the philosophy of the future, and will to power comprise aspects of Nietzsches affirmative thinking. When the egoists I will becomes transparent to itself a new beginning is thereby made possible. Nietzsche thus attempts to bring forward precisely that kind of affirmation which exists in and through its own essence, insofar as will to power as a principle of affirmation is made possible by its own destructive modalities which pulls back the curtain on metaphysical illusions and dogma founded on them.
The historical situation that conditions Nietzsches will to power involves not only the death of God and the reappearance of pessimism, but also the nineteenth centurys increased historical awareness, and with it the return of the ancient philosophical problem of emergence. How does the exceptional, for example, begin to take shape in the ordinary, or truth in untruth, reason in un-reason, social order and law in violence, a being in becoming? The variation and formal emergence of each of these states must, according to Nietzsche, be understood as a possibility only within a presumed sphere of associated events. One could thus also speak of the emergence, as part of this sphere, of a given forms disintegration. Indeed, the new cosmology must account for such a fate. Most importantly, the new cosmology must grant meaning to this eternal recurrence of emergence and disintegration without, however, taking vengeance upon it. This is to say that in the teaching of such a worldview, the innocence of becoming must be restored. The problem of emergence attracted Nietzsches interest in the earliest writings, but he apparently began to conceptualize it in published texts during the middle period, when his work freed itself from the early periods metaphysics of aesthetics. The opening passage from 1878s Human, All Too Human gives some indication of how Nietzsches thinking on this ancient problem begins to take shape:
Chemistry of concepts and feelings. In almost all respects, philosophical problems today are again formulated as they were two thousand years ago: how can something arise from its opposite.? Until now, metaphysical philosophy has overcome this difficulty by denying the origin of the one from the other, and by assuming for the more highly valued things some miraculous origin. Historical philosophy, on the other hand, the very youngest of all philosophical methods, which can no longer be even conceived of as separate from the natural sciences, has determined in isolated cases (and will probably conclude in all of them) that they are not opposites, only exaggerated to be so by the metaphysical view.As historical philosophy explains it, there exists, strictly considered, neither a selfless act nor a completely disinterested observation: both are merely sublimations. In them the basic element appears to be virtually dispersed and proves to be present only to the most careful observer. (Human, All Too Human, 1)
It is telling that Human begins by alluding to the problem of emergence as it is brought to light again by the historical philosophical method. A decidedly un-scientific metaphysical view, by comparison, looks rather for miraculous origins in support of the highest values. Next, in an unexpected move, Nietzsche relates the general problem of emergence to two specific issues, one concerning morals (selfless acts) and the other, knowledgewhich is taken to include judgment (disinterested observations): in them the basic element appears to be virtually dispersed and discernable only to the most careful observer.
The logical structure of emergence, here, appears to have been borrowed from Hegel and, to be sure, one could point to many Hegelian traces in Nietzsches thought. But previously in 1874s On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life, from Untimely Meditations, Nietzsche had steadfastly refuted the dialectical logic of a world historical process, the Absolute Idea, and cunning reason. What, then, is the basic element, dispersed in morals and knowledge? How is it dispersed so that only the careful observer can detect it? The most decisive moment in Nietzsches development of a cosmology seems to have occurred when Nietzsche plumbed the surface of his early studies on the pathos and social construction of truth to discover a more prevalent feeling, one animating all socially relevant acts. In Book One of the The Gay Science (certainly one of the greatest works in whole corpus) Nietzsche, in the role of careful observer, identifies, with a bit of moral psychology, the one motive spurring all such acts:
On the doctrine of the feeling of power. Benefiting and hurting others are ways of exercising ones power upon others: that is all one desires in such cases. Whether benefiting or hurting others involves sacrifices for us does not affect the ultimate value of our actions. Even if we offer our lives, as martyrs do for their church, this is a sacrifice that is offered for our desire for power or for the purpose of preserving our feeling of power. Those who feel I possess Truthhow many possessions would they not abandon in order to save this feeling!Certainly the state in which we hurt others is rarely as agreeable, in an unadulterated way, as that in which we benefit others; it is a sign that we are still lacking power, or it shows a sense of frustration in the face of this poverty.(aphorism 13).
The ultimate value of our actions, even concerning those intended to pursue or preserve truth, are not measured by the goodness we bring others, notwithstanding the fact that intentionally harmful acts will be indicative of a desperate want of power. Nietzsche, here, asserts the significance of enhancing the feeling of power, and with this aphorism from 1882 we are on the way to seeing how the feeling of power will replace, for Nietzsche, otherworldly measures of value, as we read in finalized form in the second aphorism of 1888s The Anti-Christ:
What is good?All that heightens the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself in man. What is bad?All that proceeds from weakness. What is happiness?The feeling that power increasesthat a resistance is overcome.
No otherworldly measures exist, for Nietzsche. Yet, one should not conclude from this absence of a transcendental measure that all expressions of power are qualitatively the same. Certainly, the possession of a Machiavellian virt will find many natural advantages in this world, but Nietzsche locates the most important aspect of overcoming resistance in self-mastery and self-commanding. In Zarathustras chapter, Of Self-Overcoming, all living creatures are said to be obeying something, while he who cannot obey himself will be commanded. That is the nature of living creatures. It is important to note the disjunction: one may obey oneself or one may not. Either way, one will be commanded, but the difference is qualitative. Moreover, commanding is more difficult than obeying (BGE 188 repeats this theme). Hence, one will take the easier path, if unable to command, choosing instead to obey the directions of another. The exception, however, will command and obey the healthy and self-mastering demands of a willing self. But why, we might ask, are all living things beholden to such commanding and obeying? Where is the proof of necessity here? Zarathustra answers:
Listen to my teaching, you wisest men! Test in earnest whether I have crept into the heart of life itself and down to the roots of its heart! Where I found a living creature, there I found will to power; and even in the will of the servant, I found the will to be master (Z Of the Self-Overcoming).
Here, apparently, Nietzsches doctrine of the feeling of power has become more than an observation on the natural history and psychology of morals. The teaching reaches into the heart of life, and it says something absolute about obeying and commanding. But what is being obeyed, on the cosmological level, and what is being commanded? At this point, Zarathustra passes on a secret told to him by life itself: behold [life says], I am that which must overcome itself again and againAnd you too, enlightened man, are only a path and a footstep of my will: truly, my will to power walks with the feet of your will to truth. We see here that a principle, will to power, is embodied by the human beings will to truth, and we may imagine it taking other forms as well. Reflecting on this insight, for example, Zarathustra claims to have solved the riddle of the hearts of the creator of values: you exert power with your values and doctrines of good and evil, you assessors of values.but a mightier power and a new overcoming grow from out of your values That mightier power growing in and through the embodiment and expression of human values is will to power.
It is important not to disassociate will to power, as a cosmology, from the human beings drive to create values. To be sure, Nietzsche is still saying that the creation of values expresses a desire for power, and the first essay of 1887s On the Genealogy of Morality returns to this simple formula. Here, Nietzsche appropriates a well-known element of Hegels Phenomenology, the structural movement of thought between basic types called masters and slaves. This appropriation has the affect of emphasizing the difference between Nietzsches own historical genealogies and that of Hegels dialectic (as is worked out in Deleuzes study of Nietzsche). Master and slave moralities, the truths of which are confirmed independently by feelings that power has been increased, are expressions of the human beings will to power in qualitatively different states of health. The former is a consequence of strength, cheerful optimism and naivet, while the latter stems from impotency, pessimism, cunning and, most famously, ressentiment, the creative reaction of a bad conscience coming to form as it turns against itself in hatred. The venom of slave morality is thus directed outwardly in ressentiment and inwardly in bad conscience. Differing concepts of good, moreover, belong to master and slave value systems. Master morality complements its good with the designation, bad, understood to be associated with the one who is inferior, weak, and cowardly. For slave morality, on the other hand, the designation, good is itself the complement of evil, the primary understanding of value in this scheme, associated with the one possessing superior strength. Thus, the good man in the unalloyed form of master morality will be the evil man, the man against whom ressentiment is directed, in the purest form of slave morality. Nietzsche is careful to add, at least in Beyond Good and Evil, that all modern value systems are constituted by compounding, in varying degrees, these two basic elements. Only a genealogical study of how these modern systems came to form will uncover the qualitative strengths and weaknesses of any normative judgment.
The language and method of The Genealogy hearken back to The Gay Sciences doctrine of the feeling of power. But, as we have seen, in the period between 1882 and 1887, and from out of the psychological-historical description of morality, truth, and the feeling of power, Nietzsche has given agency to the willing as such that lives in and through the embrace of power, and he generalizes the willing agent in order to include life and the world and the principle therein by which entities emerge embodied. The ancient philosophical problem of emergence is resolved, in part, with the cosmology of a creative, self-grounding, self-generating, sustaining and enhancing will to power. Such willing, most importantly, commands, which at the same time is an obeying: difference emerges from out of indifference and overcomes it, at least for a while. Life, in this view, is essentially self-overcoming, a self-empowering power accomplishing more power to no other end. In a notebook entry from 1885, Will to Powers aphorism 1067, Nietzsches cosmological intuitions take flight:
And do you know what the world is to me? Shall I show it to you in my mirror? This world: a monster of energy, without beginning, without endas force throughout, as a play of forces and waves of forcesa sea of forces flowing and rushing together, eternally changing and eternally flooding back with tremendous years of recurrenceout of the play of contradictions back to the joy of concord, still blessing itself as that which must return eternally, as a becoming that knows no satiety, no disgust, no weariness; this my Dionysian world of the eternally self-creating, the eternally self-destroying, this mystery world of the two-fold voluptuous delight, my beyond good and evil, without goal, unless the joy of the circle is itself a goal.This world is the will to powerand nothing besides! And you yourselves are also this will to powerand nothing besides!
Nietzsche discovers, here, the words to articulate one of his most ambitious concepts. The will to power is now described in terms of eternal and world-encompassing creativity and destructiveness, thought over the expanse of tremendous years and in terms of recurrence, what Foucault has described as the play of domination (1971). In some respects Nietzsche has indeed rediscovered the temporal structure of Heraclitus child at play, arranging toys in fanciful constructions of what merely seems like everything great and noble, before tearing down this structure and building again on the precipice of a new mishap. To live in this manner, according to Nietzsche in The Gay Science, to affirm this kind of cosmology and its form of eternity, is to live dangerously and to love fate (amor fati).
In spite of the positivistic methodology of The Genealogy, beneath the surface of this natural history of morals, will to power pumps life into the heart of both master and slave conceptual frameworks. Moreover, will to power stands as a necessary condition for all value judgments. How, one might ask, are these cosmological intuitions derived? How is knowledge of both will to power and its eternally recurring play of creation and destruction grounded? If they are to be understood poetically, then the question why?is misplaced (Zarathustra, Of Poets). Logically, with respect to knowledge, Nietzsche insists that principles of perception and judgment evolve co-dependently with consciousness, in response to physical necessities. The self is organized and brought to stand within the body and by the stimuli received there. This means that all principles are transformations of stimuli and interpretations thereupon: truth is a mobile army of metaphors which the body forms before the mind begins to grasp. Let us beware, Nietzsche cautions, of saying that the world possesses any sort of order or coherence without these interpretations (GS 109), even to the extent that Nietzsche himself conceives will to power as the way of all things. If all principles are interpretive gestures, by the logic of Nietzsches new cosmology, the will to power must also be interpretive (BGE 22). One aspect of the absence of absolute order is that interpretive gestures are necessarily called-forth for the establishment of meaning. A critical requirement of this interpretive gesture becoming transparent is that the new interpretation must knowingly affirm that all principles are grounded in interpretation. According to Nietzsche, such reflexivity does not discredit his cosmology: so much the better, since will to power, through Nietzsches articulation, emerges as the thought that now dances playfully and lingers for a while in the midst of what Vattimo might call a weakened (and weakening) ontology of indifference. The human being is thereby an experimental animal (GM II). Its truths have the seductive power of the feminine (BGE 1); while Nietzsches grandest visions are oriented by the experimental or tempter god, the one later Nietzsche comes to identify with the name Dionysus (BGE 295).
The philosopher of the future will posses a level of critical awareness hitherto unimagined, given that his interpretive gestures will be recognized as such. Yet, a flourishing life will still demand, one might imagine, being able to suspend, hide, or forgetat the right momentsthe creation of values, especially the highest values. Perhaps the cartoonish, bombastic language of The Genealogys master and slave morality, to point to an example, which was much more soberly discussed in the previous years Beyond Good and Evil, is employed esoterically by Nietzsche for the rhetorical effect of producing a grand and spectacular diversion, hiding the all-important creative gesture that brought forth the new cosmology as a supreme value: This world is the will to power and nothing besides!And you yourselves are also this will to powerand nothing besides! With this teaching, Nietzsche leaves underdeveloped many obvious themes, such as how the worlds non-animate matter may (or may not) be involved with will to power or whether non-human life-forms take part fully and equally in the worlds movement of forces. To have a perspective, for Nietzsche, seems sufficient for participating in will to power, but does this mean that non-human animals, which certainly seem to have perspectives, and without question participate in the living of life, have the human beings capacity (or any capacity for that matter) to command themselves? Or, do trees and other forms of vegetation? Apparently, they do not. Such problems involve, again, the question of freedom, which interests Nietzsche primarily in the positive form. Of more importance to Nietzsche is that which pertains solely to the human beings marshalling of forces but, even here (or perhaps especially here), a hierarchy of differences may be discerned. Some human forms of participation in will to power are noble, others ignoble. But, concerning these sorts of activities, Nietzsche stresses in Beyond Good and Evil (aphorism 9) the difference between his own cosmology, which at times seems to re-establish the place of nobility in nature, and the stoic view, which asserts the oneness of humanity with divine nature:
According to nature you want to live? Oh you noble Stoics, what deceptive words these are! Imagine a being like nature, wasteful beyond measure, indifferent beyond measure, without purposes and consideration, without mercy and justice, fertile and desolate and uncertain at the same time; imagine indifference itself as a powerhow could you live according to this indifference? Livingis that not precisely wanting to be other than this nature? Is not livingestimating, preferring, being unjust, being limited, wanting to be different? .But this is an ancient, eternal story: what formerly happened with the Stoics still happens today, too, as soon as any philosophy begins to believe in itself. It always creates the world in its own image; it cannot do otherwise. Philosophy is this tyrannical drive itself; the most spiritual will to power, to the creation of the world, to the causa prima.
Strauss claims that here Nietzsche is replacing divine nature and its egalitarian coherence with noble nature and its expression of hierarchies, the condition for which is difference, per se, emerging in nature from indifference (1983). Other commentators have suggested that Nietzsche, here, betrays all of philosophy, lacking any sense of decency with this daring exposethat what is left after the expression of such a forbidden truth is no recourse to meaning.
The most generalized form of the philosophical problem of emergence and disintegration, of the living, valuing, wanting to be different, willing power, is described here in terms of the difference-creating gesture embodied by the human beings essential work, its creation of the world and first causes. Within nature, one might say, energy disperses and accumulates in various force-points: natures power to create these force-points is radically indifferent, and this indifference towards what has been created also characterizes its power. Periodically, something exceptional is thrust out from its opposite, given that radical indifference is indifferent even towards itself (if one could speak of ontological conditions in such a representative tone, which Nietzsche certainly does from time to time). Nature is disturbed, and the human being, having thus become aware of its own identity and of others, works towards preserving itself by tying things down with definitions; enhancing itself, occasionally, by loosening the fetters of old, worn-out forms; creating and destroying in such patterns, so as to make humanity and even nature appear to conform to some bit of tyranny. From within the logic of will to power, narrowly construed, human meaning is thus affirmed. But to what end? one might ask. To no end, Nietzsche would answer. Here, the more circumspect view could be taken, as is found in Twilight of the Idols The Four Great Errors: One is a piece of fate, one belongs to the whole, one is in the whole, there exist nothing which could judge, measure, compare, condemn our being, for that would be to judge, measure, compare, condemn the whole.But nothing exists apart from the whole! Nietzsche conceptualizes human fate, then, in his most extreme vision of will to power, as being fitted to a whole, the world, which is itself nothing besides a monster of energy, without beginning, without endeternally changing and eternally flooding back with tremendous years of recurrence. In such manner, will to power expresses itself not only through the embodiment of humanity, its exemplars, and the constant revaluation of values, but also in time. Dasein, for Nietzsche, is suspended on the cross between these ontological movementsbetween an in/different playing of destruction/creationand time. But, what temporal model yields the possibility for these expressions? How does Nietzsches experimental philosophy conceptualize time?
The worlds eternally self-creating, self-destroying play is conditioned by time. Yet, Nietzsches skepticism concerning what can be known of telos, indeed his refutation of an absolute telos independent of human fabrication, demands a view of time that differs from those that place willing, purposiveness, and efficient causes in the service of goals, sufficient reason, and causa prima. Another formulation of this problem might ask, what is the history of willing, if not the demonstration of progress and/or decay?
Nietzsches solution to the riddle of time, nevertheless, radicalizes the Christian concept of eternity, combining a bit of simple observation and sure reasoning with an intuition that produces curious, but innovative results. The solution takes shape as Nietzsche fills the temporal horizons of past and future with events whose denotations have no permanent tether. Will to power, the Heraclitean cosmic-child, plays-on without preference to outcomes. Within the two-fold limit of this horizon, disturbances emerge from their opposites, but one cannot evaluate them, absolutely, because judgment implicates participation in will to power, in the ebb and flow of events constituting time. The objective perspective is not possible, since the whole consumes all possibilities, giving form to and destroying all that has come to fulfillment. Whatever stands in this flux, does so in the midst of the whole, but only for a while. It disturbs the whole, but does so as part of the whole. As such, whatever stands is measured, on the one hand, by the context its emergence creates. On the other hand, whatever stands is immeasurable, by virtue of the whole, the logic of which would determine this moment to have occurred in the never-ending flux of creation and destruction. Even to say that particular events seem better or worse suited to the functionality of the whole, or to its stability, or its health, or that an event may be measured absolutely by its fitted-ness in some other way, presupposes a standpoint that Nietzsches cosmology will not allow. One is left only to describe material occurrences and to intuit the passing of time.
The second part of Nietzsches solution to the riddle of time reasons that the mere observation of an occurrence, whether thought to be a simple thing or a more complex event, is enough to demonstrate the occurrences possibility. If something has happened, then its happening, naturally, must have been possible. Each simple thing or complex event is linked, inextricably, to a near infinite number of others, also demonstrating the possibilities of their happenings. If all of these possibilities could be presented in such a way as to account for their relationships and probabilities, as for example on a marvelously complex set of dice, then it could be shown that each of these possibilities will necessarily occur, and re-occur, given that the game of dice continues a sufficient length of time.
Next, Nietzsche considers the nature of temporal limits and duration. He proposes that no beginning or end of time can be determined, absolutely, in thought. No matter what sort of temporal limits are set by the imagination, questions concerning what lies beyond these limits never demonstrably cease. The question, what precedes or follows the imagined limits of past and future? never contradicts our understanding of time, which is thus shown to be more culturally and historically determined than otherwise admitted.
Finally, rather than to imagine a past and future extended infinitely on a plane of sequential moments, or to imagine a time in which nothing happens or will happen, Nietzsche envisions connecting what lies beyond the imaginations two temporal horizons, so that time is represented in the image of a circle, through which a colossal, but definitive number of possibilities are expressed. Time is infinite with this model, but filled by a finite number of material possibilities, recurring eternally in the never-ending play of the great cosmic game of chance.
What intuition led Nietzsche to interpret the cosmos as having no inherent meaning, as if it were playing itself out and repeating itself in eternally recurring cycles, in the endless creation and destruction of force-points without purpose? How does this curious temporal model relate to the living of life? In his philosophical autobiography, Ecce Homo, Nietzsche grounds eternal recurrence in his own experiences by relating an anecdote regarding, supposedly, its first appearance to him in thought. One day, Nietzsche writes, while hiking around Lake Silvaplana near Sils Maria, he came upon a giant boulder, took out a piece of paper and scribbled, 6000 Fuss jenseits von Mensch und Zeit. From here, Nietzsche goes on to articulate the eternal recurrence of the same, which he then characterizes as a doctrine or a teaching of the highest form of affirmation that can possibly be attained.
It is important to note that at the time of this discovery, Nietzsche was bringing his work on The Gay Science to a close and beginning to sketch out a plan for Zarathustra. The conceptualization of eternal recurrence emerges at the threshold of Nietzsches most acute positivistic inquiry and his most poetic creation. The transition between the two texts is made explicit when Nietzsche repeats the final aphorism of The Gay Sciences Book IV in the opening scene of Zarathustras prelude. The repetition of this scene will prove to be no coincidence, given the importance Nietzsche places upon the theme of recurrence in Zarathustras climactic chapters. Moreover, in the penultimate aphorism of The Gay Science, as a sort of introduction to that texts Zarathustra scene (which itself would seem quite odd apart from the later work), Nietzsche first lays out Zarathustras central teaching, the idea of eternal recurrence.
The greatest weight.What, if some day or night a demon were to steal after you into your loneliest loneliness and say to you: This life as you now live it and have lived it, you will have to live once more and innumerable times more; and there will be nothing new in it, but every pain and every joy and every thought and sigh and everything unutterably small or great in your life will have to return to you, all in the same succession and sequenceeven this spider and this moonlight between the trees, and even this moment and I myself. The eternal hourglass of existence is turned upside down again and again, and you with it, speck of dust! (GS 341).
What if, wonders Nietzsche, the thought took hold of us? Here, the conceptualization of eternal recurrence, thus, coincides with questions regarding its impact: how well disposed would you have to become to yourself and to life to crave nothing more fervently than this ultimate eternal confirmation and seal?
How would the logic of this new temporal model alter our experiences of factual life? Would such a thought diminish the willfulness of those who grasp it? Would it diminish our willingness to make normative decisions? Would willing cease under the pessimistic suspicion that the course for everything has already been determined, that all intentions are in vain? What would we lose by accepting the doctrine of this teaching? What would we gain? It seems strange that Nietzsche would place so much dramatic emphasis on this temporal form of determinism. If all of our worldly strivings and cravings were revealed, in the logic of eternal recurrence, to be no more than illusions, if every contingent fact of creation and destruction were understood to have merely repeated itself without end, if everything that happens, as it happens, both re-inscribes and anticipates its own eternal recurrence, what would be the affect on our dispositions, on our capacities to strive and create? Would we be crushed by this eternal comedy? Or, could we somehow find it liberating?
Even though Nietzsche has envisioned a temporal model of existence seemingly depriving us of the freedom to act in unique ways, we should not fail to catch sight of the qualitative differences the doctrine nevertheless leaves open for the living. The logic of eternity determines every contingent fact in each cycle of recurrence. That is, each recurrence is quantitatively the same. The quality of that recurrence, however, seems to remain an open question. What if the thought took hold of us? If we indeed understood ourselves to be bound by fate and thus having no freedom from the eternal logic of things, could we yet summon love for that fate, to embrace a kind of freedom for becoming that person we are? This is the strange confluence of possibility and necessity that Nietzsche announces in the beginning of Gay Sciences Book IV, with the concept of Amor fati: I want to learn more and more to see as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of those who make things beautiful. Amor fati: let that be my love henceforth!
Responses to this doctrine have been varied. Even some of the most enthusiastic Nietzsche commentators have, like Kaufmann, deemed it unworthy of serious reflection. Nietzsche, however, appears to stress its significance in Twilight of the Idols and Ecce Homo by emphasizing Zarathustras importance in the history of humanity and by dramatically staging in Thus Spoke Zarathustra the idea of eternal recurrence as the fundamental teaching of the main character. The presentation of this idea, however, leaves room for much doubt concerning the literal meaning of these claims, as does the paucity of direct references to the doctrine in other works intended for publication. In Nietzsches Nachlass, we discover attempts to work out rational proofs supporting the theory, but they seem to present no serious challenge to a linear conception of time. Among commentators taking the doctrine seriously, Lwith takes it as a supplement to Nietzsches historical nihilism, as a way of placing emphasis on the problem of meaning in history after the shadows of God have been dissolved. For Lwiths Nietzsche, nihilism is more than an historical moment giving rise to a crisis of confidence or faith. Rather, nihilism is the essence of Nietzsches thought, and it poses the sorts of problems that lead Nietzsche into formulating eternal return as a way of restoring meaning in history. For Lwith, then, eternal return is inextricably linked to historical nihilism and offers both cosmological and anthropological grounds for accepting imperatives of self-overcoming. Yet, this grand attempt fails to restore meaning after the death of God, according to Lwith, because of eternal returns logical contradictions.
The reception of Nietzsches work, on all levels of engagement, has been complicated by historical contingencies that are related only by accident to the thought itself. The first of these complications pertains to the editorial control gained by Elizabeth in the aftermath of her brothers mental and physical collapse. Elisabeths overall impact on her brothers reputation is generally thought to be very problematic. Her husband, Bernhard Frster, whom Friedrich detested, was a leader of the late nineteenth-century German anti-Semitic political movement, which Friedrich often ridiculed and unambiguously condemned, both in his published works and in private correspondences. On this issue, Yovel demonstrates persuasively, with a contextual analysis of letters, materials from the Nachlass, and published works, that Nietzsche developed an attitude of anti-anti-Semitism after overcoming the culture of prejudice that formed him in his youth (Yovel, 1998). In the mid-1880s, Frster and wife led a small group of colonists to Paraguay in hopes of establishing an idyllic, racially pure, German settlement. The colony foundered, Bernhard committed suicide, and Elisabeth returned home, just in time to find her brothers health failing and his literary career ready to soar.
Upon her return, Elisabeth devised a way to keep alive the memory of both husband and brother, legally changing her last name to Frster-Nietzsche, a gesture indicative of designs to associate the philosopher with a political ideology he loathed. The stain of Elisabeths editorial imprint can be seen on the many ill-informed and haphazard interpretations of Nietzsche produced in the early part of the twentieth century, the unfortunate traces of which remain in some readings today. During the 1930s, in the midst of intense activity by National Socialist academic propagandists such as Alfred Bumler, even typically insightful thinkers such as Emmanuel Levinas confused the public image of Nietzsche for the philosophers stated beliefs. Counter-efforts in the 1930s to refute such propaganda, and the popular misconceptions it was fomenting at the time, can be found both inside and outside Germany, in seminars, for example, led by Karl Jaspers and Karl Lwith, and in Georges Batailles essay Nietzsche and the Fascists. Of course, the ad hominem argument that Nietzsche must be a Fascist philosopher because the Fascists venerated him as one of their own, may be ignored. (No one should find Kants moral philosophy reprehensible, by comparison, simply on the grounds that Eichmann attempted to exploit it in a Jerusalem court). Apart from the fallacy, here, even the premise itself regarding Nietzsche and the Fascists is not entirely above reproach, since some Fascists were skeptical of the commensurability of Nietzsches thought with their political aims. The stronger claim that Nietzsches thought leads to National Socialism is even more problematic. Nevertheless, intellectual histories pursuing the question of how Nietzsche has been placed into the service of all sorts of political interests are an important part of Nietzsche scholarship.
Since the middle part of the last century, Nietzsche scholars have come to grips with the role played by Elisabeth and her associates in obscuring Nietzsches anti-Nationalistic, anti-Socialist, anti-German views, his pan-European advocacy of race mixing, as well as his hatred for anti-Semitism and its place in the late-nineteenth-century politics of exploitation. The work Elisabeth performed as her brothers publicist, however, undoubtedly fulfilled all of her own fantasies: in the early 1930s, decades after Friedrichs death, the Nietzsche-Archiv was visited, ceremoniously, by Adolf Hitler, who was greeted and entertained by Elisabeth (in perhaps the most symbolic gesture of her association with the Nietzsche image) with a public reading of the work of her late husband, Bernhard, the anti-Semite. Hitler later attended Elisabeths funeral as Chancellor of Germany.
In a matter related to Elizabeths impact on the reception of her brothers thought, the relevance of Nietzsches biography to his philosophical work has long been a point of contention among Nietzsche commentators. While an exhaustive survey of the way this key issue has been addressed in the scholarship would be difficult in this context, a few influential readings may be briefly mentioned. Among notable German readers, Heidegger and Fink dismiss the idea that Nietzsches thought can be elucidated with the details of his life, while Jaspers affirms the exceptional nature of Nietzsches life and identifies the exception as a key aspect of his philosophy. French readers such as Bataille, Deleuze, Klossowski, Foucault, and Derrida assert the relevance of various biographical details to specific movements within Nietzsches writings. In the United States, the influential reading of Walter Kaufman follows Heidegger, for the most part, in denying relevance, while his student, Alexander Nehamas, tends the other way, linking Nietzsches various literary styles to his perspectivism and ultimately to living, per se, as an self-interpretive gesture. However difficult it might be to see the philosophical relevance of various biographical curiosities, such as Nietzsches psychological development as a child without a living father, his fascination and then fallout with Wagner, his professional ostracism, his thwarted love life, the excruciating physical ailments that tormented him, and so on, it would also seem capricious and otherwise inconsistent with Nietzsches work to radically severe his thought from these and other biographical details, and persuasive interpretations have argued that such experiences, and Nietzsches well-considered views of them, are inseparable from the multiple trajectories of his intellectual work.
Attempts to isolate Nietzsches philosophy from the twists and turns of a frequently problematic life may be explained, in part, as a reaction to several early, and rather detrimental, popular-psychological studies attempting to explain the work in a reductive and decidedly un-philosophical manner. Such was the reading proffered, for example, by Lou Salom, a woman with whom Nietzsche briefly had an unconventional and famously complex romantic relationship, and who later befriended Sigmund Freud among other leaders of European culture at the fin-de-sicle. Saloms Friedrich Nietzsche in His Works (1894) helped cast the image of Nietzsche as a lonely, miserable, self-immolating, recluse whose external intellectual workand inner life coalesce completely. In some commentaries, this image prevails yet today, but its accuracy is also a matter of debate. Nietzsche had many casual associates and a few close friends while in school and as a professor in Basel. Even during the period of his most intense intellectual activity, after withdrawing from the professional world of the academy and, like Marx and others before him in the nineteenth century, taking up the wandering life of a good European, the many written correspondences between Nietzsche and life-long friends, along with what is known about the minor details of his daily habits, his days spent in the company of fellow lodgers and travelers, taking meals regularly (in spite of a very closely regulated diet), and similar anecdotes, all put forward a different image. No doubt the affair with Salom and their mutual friend, the philosopher Paul Re, left Nietzsche embittered towards the two of them, and it seems likely that this bitterness clouded Saloms interpretation of Nietzsche and his works. Elisabeth, who had always loathed Salom for her immoderation and perceived influence over Friedrich, attempted to correct her rivals account by writing her own biography of Friedrich, which was effusive in its praise but did little to advance the understanding of Nietzsches thought. Perhaps these kinds of problems, then, provide the best argument for resisting the lure to reduce interpretations of Nietzsches thought to gossipy biographical anecdotes and clumsy, amateurish speculation, even if the other extreme has also been excessive at times.
Another key issue in the reception of Nietzsches work involves determining its relationship to the thoughts of other philosophers and, indeed, to the philosophical tradition itself. On both levels of this complex issue, the work of Martin Heidegger looms paramount. Heidegger began working closely with Nietzsches thought in the 1930s, a time rife with political opportunism in Germany, even among scholars and intellectuals. In the midst of a struggle over the official Nazi interpretation of Nietzsche, Heideggers views began to coalesce, and after a series of lectures on Nietzsches thought in the late 1930s and 1940, Heidegger produces in 1943 the seminal essay, Nietzsches Word: God is Dead. Nietzsche, for Heidegger, brought the consummation of metaphysics in the age of subject-centered reasoning, industrialization, technological power, and the enframing (Ge-stell) of humans and all other beings as a standing reserve. Combining Nietzsches self-described inversion of Platonism with the emphasis Nietzsche had undoubtedly placed upon the value-positing act and its relatedness to subjective or inter-subjective human perspectives, Heidegger dubbed Nietzsche the last metaphysician and tied him to the logic of a historical narrative highlighted by the appearances of Plato, Aristotle, Roman Antiquity, Christendom, Luther, Descartes, Leibniz, Schopenhauer, and others. The one thought common to each of these movements and thinkers, according to Heidegger, and the path Nietzsche thus thinks through to its consummation, is the metaphysical determination of being (Sein) as no more than something static and constantly present. Although Nietzsche appears to reject the concept of being as an empty fiction (claiming, in Twilight of the Idols, to concur with Heraclitus in this regard), Heidegger nevertheless reads in Nietzsches Platonic inversion the most insidious form of the metaphysics of presence, in which the destruction and re-establishment of value is taken to be the only possible occasion for philosophical labor whereby the very question of being is completely obliterated. Within this diminution of thought, the Nietzschean Superman emerges supremely powerful and triumphant, taking dominion over the earth and all of its beings, measured only by the mundane search for advantages in the ubiquitous struggle for preservation and enhancement.
As is typically the case with Heideggers interpretations of the history of philosophy, many aspects of this reading are truly remarkableHeideggers scholarship, for example, his feel for what is important to Nietzsche, and his elaboration of Nietzsches work in a way that seems compatible with a narrative of the concealing and revealing destiny of being. However, the plausibility of this reading has come into question almost from the moment the full extent of it was made known in the 1950s and 60s. In Germany, for example, Eugen Fink concludes his 1960 study of Nietzsche by casting doubt upon Heideggers claim that Nietzsches thought can be reduced to a metaphysics:
Heideggers Nietzsche interpretation is essentially based upon Heideggers summary and insight into the history of being and in particular on his interpretation of the metaphysics of modernity. Nevertheless, the question remains open whether Nietzsche does not already leave the metaphysical dimensions of any problems essentially and intentionally behind in his conception of the cosmos. There is a non-metaphysical originality in his cosmological philosophy of play. Even the early writings indicate the mysterious dimension of play.
Finks reluctance to take a stronger position against the reading of his renowned teacher seems rather coy, given that Finks study, throughout, has stressed the meaning and importance of cosmological play in Nietzsches work. Other commentators have much more explicitly challenged Heideggers grand narrative and specifically its place for Nietzsche in the Western tradition, concurring with Fink that Nietzsches conceptualization of play frees his thought from the tradition of metaphysics, or that Nietzsche, purposively or not, offered conflicting views of himself, eluding the kind of summary treatment presented by Heidegger and much less-gifted readers (who consider Nietzsche to be no more than a late-Romantic, a social-Darwinist, or the like). In this sort of commentary, Nietzsches work itself is at play in deconstructing the all-too-rigid kinds of explanations.
Continued here:
Posted in Nihilism
Comments Off on Nietzsche, Friedrich | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
30 Religious Terms You Should Know – Daily Writing Tips
Posted: at 3:16 pm
By Maeve Maddox
When I was growing up in small town America, stories about religion were generally confined to the Saturday church pages in the local newspaper. Catholics and Jews were the most exotic religious practitioners in town, and atheist was a strong term of disapprobation.
These days religion is front page news. People are killed or driven into hiding because someone somewhere has labeled their work blasphemy. School children with attitude get away with refusing to do their homework because they know that school officials are easily spooked by anything relating to religion.
Journalists and school officials shouldnt have to tiptoe around religious topics. The topic of religion, like that of ecology, is one that concerns all human beings. Although the three Abrahamic religions get most of the news copy, the number of religions that matter to people number in the double digits. Whether we care about it or not, we ought to be able to read and write about religion with some understanding of the terminology.
NOTE: The definitions given here are not intended to be exhaustive. For one thing, some of the terms are defined differently by different religious groups. For permutations of meaning, see the OED or some other authoritative dictionary.
Abrahamic religions: Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. All three faiths trace their origins to the patriarch Abraham who rejected the polytheism of ancient Sumer to embrace a belief in one, invisible, deity. Sometimes referred to as the desert religions.
agnosticism: the philosophical position that the existence or non-existence of God or a First Cause is unknowable.
Anglican: relating to the Church of England. An ancient name for the English people was Angles. The Church of England traces its beginning to 597, the year in which Pope Gregory I sent St. Augustine to Canterbury. The Church of England remained under papal authority until 1534 when Henry VIII declared himself the Supreme Head of the Church because of conflicts with Pope Clement VII.
animism: the belief that every material form of reality (plants, animals, stones, thunderstorms, earthquakes) have an indwelling spirit; often includes belief in the continued existence of individual disembodied human spirits capable of helping or harming the living.
asceticism: a mode of life that excludes physical pleasures and self-indulgence. Many religions regard asceticism (fasting, abstaining from sexual activity, wearing inadequate clothing) as a means of reaching a higher spiritual state.
atheism: disbelief in any deity or supernatural power.
blasphemy: indignity offered to God, from Greek blasphemia, a speaking ill, impious speech, slander. Religions define blasphemy in terms of their own beliefs, often designating prophets and holy objects along with God as subjects not to be profaned. Many countries have anti-blasphemy laws.
Buddhism: the teaching that suffering is inherent to life and that the way to escape suffering and repeated existence is to limit ones desires and expectations. There are various sects with varying beliefs.
Confucianism: a system of teachings characterized by central emphasis on the practice and cultivation of the cardinal virtues of filial piety, kindness, righteousness, propriety, intelligence, and faithfulness.
ecclesiastic: relating to a church. Greek ekklesiastikos referred to the ancient Athenian political assembly. First century Christians writers adopted the word to mean assembly of believers, or church.
episcopal: having to do with a bishop. Like ecclesiastic, the English word bishop derives from a Greek word, episkopos, watcher, overseer. The Greeks used their word to refer to government officials. First century Christian writers used bishop or episkopos to refer to church elders. In time bishop came to mean the chief administrator of a diocese (administrative district governed by a bishop) with the power to ordain. Episcopal is the adjective for bishop.
evangelical: having to do with the Christian gospel/New Testament writings. The word is also used to describe a type of Christian belief that emphasizes the inerrancy of scripture and salvation through personal conversion.
Eucharist: the sacrament of the Lords Supper, a rite in which bread and wine are consecrated and consumed in symbolic union with Christ. The word comes from a Greek word meaning grateful.
ecumenical: worldwide. As applied to religion, the words current use to mean cooperation among religious groups began with a 20th century movement promoting the idea of an inter-confessional Christian unity. Now an ecumenical group cooperating on some matter of general social benefit might include representatives from non-Christian religions.
eschatology: the study of matters relating to the ultimate destiny of mankind and the world.
Gnosticism: the belief that salvation is to be obtained by means of secret knowledge and that the material world is evil. Gnostic mystery religions abounded in the Roman Empire. The early Christian church was fragmented into various sects, many of which taught a Gnostic version of the new religion.
gospel: the story of Christs life and teachings as told in the first four books of the Christian New Testament. The literal meaning of the word is good news.
heresy: a religious opinion, or adherence to such an opinion, that is contrary to an established religious teaching. The word comes from Greek hairesis, action of taking, choice, sect. Originally a heresy was simply a difference of opinion. It became a religious crime, often punished by death.
Hinduism: a body of social, cultural, and religious beliefs and practices found chiefly in India. It includes a belief in reincarnation and transmigration of souls.
indulgence: in Roman Catholicism, a remission of punishment, especially punishment in Purgatory (in Catholic belief, Purgatory is an intermediate place of purification for souls that departed stained with minor sins not deserving of eternal punishment in Hell).
Immaculate Conception: the Roman Catholic doctrine that the Virgin Mary was conceived without Original Sin (the sin of Adam and Eve conveyed to all human beings). This is not the same thing as the Virgin Birth, the belief that Jesus was divinely begotten and miraculously born of a virgin mother.
jihad: a holy war on behalf of Islam. The Christian equivalent word is crusade, a campaign or war sanctioned by the Church against unbelievers or heretics. Literal crusades were common in the Middle Ages and were directed against Christian heretics as well as non-Christians. Now the term is used figuratively to mean any remedial activity pursued with zeal and enthusiasm. The same meaning is becoming attached to jihad.
lay: not in holy orders. In a monastery there are monks who pray and do intellectual work, and those who do manual work and attend to secular affairs. The latter are called lay brothers. The term has spread to non-religious professions. Someone who lacks professional knowledge of a particular profession is called a layman. In a church setting one may speak of the clergy and the laity (non-clerical members of the church).
monotheism: the doctrine or belief that there is only one God.
nihilism: the viewpoint that all traditional beliefs are unfounded and that human life has no meaning.
orthodox: in agreement with the official doctrine of a given religion. The word is from Greek orthodoxein, to have the right opinion. The noun is orthodoxy. Departure from orthodoxy is called heterodoxy.
pagan This is a term difficult to define in even such a superficial treatment as this. For the early Christians, a pagan was a believer in polytheistic religion. The word originally meant country dweller. The rural population was slower to adopt Christianity than the city dwellers, probably because their religion was closely bound to agricultural cycles. Nowadays there are religious groups that identify themselves as Pagans. Modern paganism is earth-centered and can include polytheistic beliefs. The word heathen is used pejoratively to mean a person without religion. Like pagan, heathen also points to the fact that non-city dwellers tended to reject religious change. Heath comes from a word meaning field. Heathen was originally an adjective meaning of the heath.
polytheism: belief in more than one god.
profane: not holy. Anything not related to religion and spirituality is profane. The word can also be used as a verb meaning to treat something sacred with irreverence.
secular: worldly, not sacred. Similar to profane, secular refers to anything that is not specifically religious.
Visit link:
Posted in Nihilism
Comments Off on 30 Religious Terms You Should Know – Daily Writing Tips
The Difference Between Existentialism, Nihilism, and Absurdism
Posted: at 3:16 pm
Three different ways of approaching the lack of intrinsic meaning.
Created/Updated: November 17, 2020
For centuries there have been people who believe there is no intrinsic meaning in the universe. Here Ill summarize the three major branches of this belief, and how each proposes we deal with the situation.
How Absurdism Applies in Everyday Life
Intrinsic as opposed to created.
For those who come to accept that life is without intrinsic meaning, there are three main ways to react.
I view Camus Absurdism as the most satisfactory response, as it takes the third option of acceptance and works from there.
Free Wills Absurdist Paradox
Adopting a religion or some sort of nebulous spiritualityas someone who has accepted the truth of intrinsic meaninglessnessamounts to either intellectual laziness, emotional weakness, or some combination thereof. It is to say that the truth is too difficult to consume and accept, and that youve chosen to believe something untrue because it is easier.
To commit suicide is to turn ones back on the beauty that life has to offer, which I feel should only be explored in extreme cases.
Resigning to truly believe something you know isnt true is a weak position, but it often looks identical to Absurdism, which is not.
The Difference Between Nihilism, Pessimism, and Skepticism
Camus Absurdism is about working within our human limitations, but without abandoning our respect for ourselves or the truth. Absurdists often either adopt or construct a belief structure that provides a day-to-day reprieve from the crushing impossibility of true meaning. Such constructs allow us to trick our evolution-soaked brains into extracting meaning from the universe, while never forgetting that the system itself is a trick.
The UL Newsletter: Finding the Patterns in the Noise
Get a weekly analysis of what's happening in security and techand why it matters.
Perhaps the Hipster drive to obsess over minutia is a form of Absurdism.
This awareness is the difference between rebellion and surrender.
A construct could be existing or new, and either structured or amorphous.
A person who has surrendered will say that they believe in their construct completely, and that it provides true meaning in the universe, while someone who has not surrendered may say theyve adopted a scaffolding for practical reasons, but they know its artificial.
The barrier is delicate between embracing a belief structure because not doing so is too empty or painful, and only doing so for practical purposes while still knowing its false. Many start as one or the other and then migrate, or exist day to day as one and become the other when pressed.
In my opinion, the defining characteristic of Absurdism/Rebellion is the maintaining of extreme clarity between seeking the benefits of belief in intrinsic meaning all the while knowing its impossible. Such a person can go to church with the family and mentally pray in some sort of secular but semi-spiritual way, while simultaneously knowing (but not actively thinking about) the fact that nobody is listening.
As humans, its virtually impossible to exist in both modes simultaneously. We either have faith in a system, a structure, or a person, or we deconstruct that thing into its parts and see its flaws, limitations, andperhapsthat its false. Transparency removes magic. And unfortunately, our brains are most happy when the magic is intact.
Knowing where one stands amongor perhaps outsidethese options is a crucial part of self-understanding.
Here is the original post:
The Difference Between Existentialism, Nihilism, and Absurdism
Posted in Nihilism
Comments Off on The Difference Between Existentialism, Nihilism, and Absurdism
Advantages and Disadvantages of Federalism American Government
Posted: at 3:14 pm
Learning Objectives
By the end of this section, you will be able to:
The federal design of our Constitution has had a profound effect on U.S. politics. Several positive and negative attributes of federalism have manifested themselves in the U.S. political system.
Among the merits of federalism are that it promotes policy innovation and political participation and accommodates diversity of opinion. On the subject of policy innovation, Supreme Court Justice Louis Brandeis observed in 1932 that a single courageous state may, if its citizens choose, serve as a laboratory; and try novel social and economic experiments without risk to the rest of the country.
What Brandeis meant was that states could harness their constitutional authority to engage in policy innovations that might eventually be diffused to other states and at the national level. For example, a number of New Deal breakthroughs, such as child labor laws, were inspired by state policies. Prior to the passage of the Nineteenth Amendment, several states had already granted women the right to vote. California has led the way in establishing standards for fuel emissions and other environmental policies (Figure). Recently, the health insurance exchanges run by Connecticut, Kentucky, Rhode Island, and Washington have served as models for other states seeking to improve the performance of their exchanges.
Figure 1. The California Air Resources Board was established in 1967, before passage of the federal Clean Air Act. The federal Environmental Protection Agency has adopted California emissions standards nationally, starting with the 2016 model year, and is working with California regulators to establish stricter national emissions standards going forward.(credit a: modification of work by Antti T. Nissinen; credit b: modification of work by Marcin Wichary)
Another advantage of federalism is that because our federal system creates two levels of government with the capacity to take action, failure to attain a desired policy goal at one level can be offset by successfully securing the support of elected representatives at another level. Thus, individuals, groups, and social movements are encouraged to actively participate and help shape public policy.
Federalism and Political Office
Thinking of running for elected office? Well, you have several options. As (Figure) shows, there are a total of 510,682 elected offices at the federal, state, and local levels. Elected representatives in municipal and township governments account for a little more than half the total number of elected officials in the United States. Political careers rarely start at the national level. In fact, a very small share of politicians at the subnational level transition to the national stage as representatives, senators, vice presidents, or presidents.
Table 1. This table lists the number of elected bodies and elected officials at the federal, state, and local levels.
If you are interested in serving the public as an elected official, there are more opportunities to do so at the local and state levels than at the national level. As an added incentive for setting your sights at the subnational stage, consider the following. Whereas only 28 percent of U.S. adults trusted Congress in 2014, about 62 percent trusted their state governments and 72 percent had confidence in their local governments.
If you ran for public office, what problems would you most want to solve? What level of government would best enable you to solve them, and why?
The system of checks and balances in our political system often prevents the federal government from imposing uniform policies across the country. As a result, states and local communities have the latitude to address policy issues based on the specific needs and interests of their citizens. The diversity of public viewpoints across states is manifested by differences in the way states handle access to abortion, distribution of alcohol, gun control, and social welfare benefits, for example.
Federalism also comes with drawbacks. Chief among them are economic disparities across states, race-to-the-bottom dynamics (i.e., states compete to attract business by lowering taxes and regulations), and the difficulty of taking action on issues of national importance.
Stark economic differences across states have a profound effect on the well-being of citizens. For example, in 2014, Maryland had the highest median household income ($73,971), while Mississippi had the lowest ($39,680).
There are also huge disparities in school funding across states. In 2013, New York spent $19,818 per student for elementary and secondary education, while Utah spent $6,555.Governing.
Furthermore, health-care access, costs, and quality vary greatly across states.
Proponents of social justice contend that federalism has tended to obstruct national efforts to effectively even out these disparities.
The economic strategy of using race-to-the-bottom tactics in order to compete with other states in attracting new business growth also carries a social cost. For example, workers safety and pay can suffer as workplace regulations are lifted, and the reduction in payroll taxes for employers has led a number of states to end up with underfunded unemployment insurance programs. (cf.Alexander Hertel-Fernandez. 2012. Why U.S. Unemployment Insurance is in Financial Trouble, February. http://www.scholarsstrategynetwork.org/sites/default/files/ssn_basic_facts_hertel-fernandez_on_unemployment_insurance_financing.pdf)
Nineteen states have also opted not to cover more of their residents under Medicaid, as encouraged by the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act in 2010, for fear it will raise state public spending and increase employers cost of employee benefits, despite provisions that the federal government will pick up nearly all cost of the expansion.
More than half of these states are in the South.
The federal design of our Constitution and the system of checks and balances has jeopardized or outright blocked federal responses to important national issues. President Roosevelts efforts to combat the scourge of the Great Depression were initially struck down by the Supreme Court. More recently, President Obamas effort to make health insurance accessible to more Americans under the Affordable Care Act immediately ran into legal challengesfrom some states, but it has been supported by the Supreme Court so far. However, the federal governments ability to defend the voting rights of citizens suffered a major setback when the Supreme Court in 2013 struck down a key provision of the Voting Rights Act of 1965.
No longer are the nine states with histories of racial discrimination in their voting processes required to submit plans for changes to the federal government for approval.
The benefits of federalism are that it can encourage political participation, give states an incentive to engage in policy innovation, and accommodate diverse viewpoints across the country. The disadvantages are that it can set off a race to the bottom among states, cause cross-state economic and social disparities, and obstruct federal efforts to address national problems.
Read the rest here:
Advantages and Disadvantages of Federalism American Government
Posted in Federalism
Comments Off on Advantages and Disadvantages of Federalism American Government