Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
The Evolution of Australian and Amerindian Intelligence
Edward M. Miller Department of Economics and Finance University of New
Orleans E Mail: emmef@uno.edu December 12, 1995 Mankind Quarterly, Vol. 37
(Winter 1996) No. 2, 149-186.
Table of Contents
Stylized Facts 2 The Steady Growth of Intelligence 4 Genetic Mechanisms 9
The Mechanism of the Intelligence Lag in Australia 12 Australian Aboriginal
Intelligence 15 American Aboriginal Intelligence 23 Testable Implications 24
The Role of Isolation in Evolutionary Advance 27 Conclusions 29 References 30
Abstract
There has been continuous worldwide selection for intelligence, although
its strength may have varied with climate. Intelligence gradually increased,
as reflected in the sophistication of the human tool kits. This increase was
caused by intelligence increasing mutations, followed by the spread of these
mutations. These mutations occurred at approximately the same rate (per
million population) on different continents, but in absolute number were most
common in the Eurasian land mass with its high population. When Australia and
the Americas were settled the original populations lacked certain alleles
because the relevant mutations had not yet occurred, or because these
mutations had not reached the relevant parts of Eurasia. After Australia and
the Americas came to be isolated from the larger Eurasian populations, they
did not receive further immigrants. Although, a few intelligence raising
mutations occurred in their populations, the smaller Australian and American
(Indian) populations implied that the total number of beneficial mutations was
less than in Eurasia. Thus, the intelligence of the Australian and American
aboriginal populations came to lag behind that of the rest of the world. The
literature on Australian aboriginal intellectual performance is reviewed,
being shown to be low as expected.
[Image]
In his survey of the intelligence of the world's peoples Lynn (1991) found
that the highest levels were found in people that evolved in Eurasia
(Mongoloids and Caucasoids), while low values were found for those that
evolved in Africa (Negroids), and among those from the Americas and
Australasia. Most of the discussion of causes for this has focused on the
differences between the three major races, with little attention paid to the
Amerindians and the Australians.
Among the few who have tried to explain the evolution of racial differences
in intelligence, the most common explanation has been climate. These theorists
have argued that the intellectual demands of life in cold climates were
greater than in warm climates. Lynn has placed emphasis on the intellectual
abilities needed to survive cold, to build fires, and to hunt in groups.
Miller (1991) has pointed to the need to store food to survive the winter and
how this may have selected for intelligence. He has also emphasized the
importance in cold climates of avoiding a mate who deceives promising
continued provisioning that is not delivered, or accepting provisioning when
the resulting children will not be those of the provisioning mate (Miller,
1995). Intelligence helps both in carrying out, and in detecting such
detection. The implicit assumption in all such models of differential
selection is that all populations had access to the genetic variation required
for intelligence to evolve. Thus, intellectual differences between populations
had to reflect differences in the strength of selection for intelligence.
The alternative to be presented here is that more of the mutations that led
to high intelligence occurred on continents with large populations than on
less populated continents (Australia and the Americas). The selective forces
for intelligence were present on all continents, although quite possibly
differing in strength. The continents where the most such mutations had
occurred would have the highest average intelligence. With equal mutation
rates throughout the world, the continental area experiencing the largest
number of mutations would be Eurasia. The fewest would be experienced in
Australia.
Stylized Facts
There are several stylized facts (well established generalizations) that
will be used in the argument.
1. Much of the current human variation in intelligence is genetic
(Bouchard, 1993; Bouchard, et al, 1990; Jensen, 1980, Plomin, & Loehlin, 1989;
Plomin, et al 1994; Plomin et al., 1995; Rowe, 1994). Behavior genetics
research suggests that there is no single gene for intelligence. Instead, it
appears to be affected by a large number of different genes. Wills (1991)
suggests 50 genes, each contributing about 3 IQ points is of a plausible order
of magnitude. Jinks & Fulker (1970, 2. 343) conclude that at least 22 loci
seem to be controlling IQ. Later (p. 344), using data for inbreeding
depression they conclude that about 100 genes seem to be showing dominance for
high IQ. 3. There has been unidirectional selection for intelligence in most,
if not all, of the world. It is not known exactly what selected for
intelligence in the course of human evolution. That something did is indicated
by the brain's steady increase in size with time, as does the steady increase
in the complexity of technology revealed in the archaeological record (see
below). The fact of inbreeding depression suggests that many of the alleles
that contribute to low intelligence are recessive, with the alleles
contributing to high intelligence being dominant. This suggests that the genes
for high intelligence have been the subject of a continual process of
directional selection (Jinks & Fulker, 1970, p. 343). Because directional
selection acts very slowly in eliminating recessive genes, but quickly to
increase the frequency of dominant alleles, a high average level of dominance
suggests long continued directional selection for a trait.
One view has focused on the external world, discussing factors such as tool
use, hunting, gathering, throwing (Calvin, 1990), etc. This approach seems to
have become less fashionable recently, possibly because environmental driven
evolution would seem to imply that if the environments differed, the strength
of selection for intelligence would differ. Since environments obviously
differ, populations might differ in intelligence. This conclusion is
unacceptable to many, although others have considered the possibility of this
happening in response to climatic differences (Miller 1991, Lynn 1991).
Others have emphasized the selective pressures for greater intelligence
that can be created by humans interacting among themselves. Alexander (1990)
has emphasized competition among individuals, and the need to outwit ones
fellow men.
Buss (1994, p. 34) reports that in a survey of 10,047 people in 37 nations
concerning desirable traits in a mate, women ranked intelligence fifth out of
eighteen traits. In a smaller list of thirteen desirable characteristics,
intelligence emerges in second place worldwide. In ten cultures women ranked
intelligence higher than men did. However, in the other 27 countries both
sexes placed an equally high premium on intelligence.
It is not hard to explain why this preference for intelligent mates exists.
According to Buss (1994, p. 34), "these are likely to include good parenting
skills, capacity for cultural knowledge, and adeptness at parenting. In
addition, intelligence is linked with oral fluency, ability to influence other
members of a group, prescience in forecasting danger, and judgment in applying
health remedies. Beyond these specific qualities, intelligence convey the
ability to solve problems." Of course, in modern industrial societies,
intelligence is correlated with socioeconomic status (Herrnstein & Murray,
1994; Itzkoff, 1994), and "in tribal societies the head men or leaders are
inevitably among the most intelligent in the group." (Buss, 1994, p. 34). Of
course, the leaders of a group usually have greater access to fertile females
and the resources to raise them.
Buss (1994) also emphasizes how in human mating deception is often used.
Men try to convince women that they have, or will have resources, and will
devote them to the well-being of a particular woman and her children (and not
squander them on other women and their children), while women try to convince
men that they will be sexually faithful to them (while possibly seeking better
genes from other men). Buss states (p. 155), "Because the deceived can suffer
tremendous losses, there must have been great selection pressures for the
evolution of a form of psychological vigilance to detect cues to deception and
to prevent its occurrence. The modern generation is merely one more cycle in
the endless spiral of an evolutionary arms race between deception perpetuated
by one sex and detection accomplished by the other. As the deceptive tactics
get more subtle, the ability to penetrate deception become more refined."
Miller (1995) has argued that the above selective pressures would be
strongest in cold climates. In such climates, male provisioning is critical
for surviving the winter. Males have an incentive to deceive females as to
their long term reliability. Females use intelligence to deceive males as to
their sexual faithfulness, and the paternity of their children. Both sexes are
under strong selection for the intelligence required to avoid being deceived.
In the tropics, where females can support themselves, the selective pressures
for intelligence are not as strong.
Wills (1993) has emphasized also a possible role for sexual selection,
titling one of his books The Runaway Brain. Once mates came to be selected on
the basis of intelligence, or something produced by it (such as musical or
conversational ability) there would have been unidirectional selection for
intelligence with the most intelligent individuals having the best access to
mates, and leaving more descendants.
It will be presumed that each individual has a equal probability of
experiencing an intelligence raising mutation (regardless of the population
they live in). This is standard genetic theory, since no population
differences in vulnerability to mutations are known. Weakening this assumption
would not change the nature of the argument. [Image]
The Steady Growth of Intelligence
There is evidence from archaeology that human intelligence has been
steadily increasing.
The material culture of prehistoric man was at a very low level before the
emergence of anatomically modern man, and gradually increased. The rate of
progress was very slow. There were periods of tens of thousands to hundreds of
thousands of years when the tool kits used by primitive hominids remained
essentially constant.
This slow rate of progress is more consistent with biological evolution
than with cultural evolution. If the populations had been similar to current
populations in ability, it is likely that better methods would have been
quickly discovered and adopted. The best way to explain the failure to
discover and to adopt more sophisticated tools is that the population had not
yet acquired the intellectual abilities needed to develop and use these
methods.
A quick history of stone technology may be useful. Because organic material
perishes, most of our evidence of early human intellectual achievements
consists of the stone tools they left behind. The earliest tools are the
Oldowan, which were extremely crude scrapers, choppers, and flakes, each being
the product of a few strokes with a hammerstone, and are dated at about 2.5
million years ago. This persisted for about a million years. It was followed
by the Acheulian industry, which represented only a modest advance. However,
this did represent "the first tool in which a predetermined shape has been
imposed on a piece of raw material" (Lewin, 1989, p. 114). The hand ax, which
was characteristic of this technology involved two converging sharp edges,
which "required the shape to be seen within the lump of stone, which is then
worked toward with a series of careful striking actions," (Lewin, 1989, p.
114). Constructing such "esthetically pleasing products of hours of skilled
labor" probably required more intelligence than merely knocking two stones
together.
Once developed the Acheulian technology persisted for over a million years.
The most plausible explanation for the failure to adopt more sophisticated
techniques is that the population lacked the intellectual ability to conceive
of and adopt these techniques. If the population had the ability required to
use a more sophisticated technology, surely it would have been invented and
adopted within a million years.
About 150,000 years ago, change accelerated in stone working technology.
"It is, as Isaac says, as if some threshhold was passed:, a critical threshold
in information capacity and precision of expression," (Lewin, 1989, p. 115).
Presumably, for any given human population, the crossing of this threshold was
caused by a sufficient number of advantageous mutations originating in them,
or more likely, reaching them from the populations where the original
mutations had occurred.
The major technical development that brought the Acheulian era to an end
was the development of the Levallois technique in which a carefully prepared
core was first constructed, from which virtually complete flakes could be
struck at a single blow, to be followed by a retouching to give the final
desired shape. One of the major advantages of this new technique was a greater
efficiency in the use of raw materials. An Acheulian tool maker could produce
5.1 to 20.3 centimeters of cutting edge from .45 kilograms of flint, whereas a
Mousterian (as the new technology is referred to) tool maker could strike 10.2
meters of cutting edge from the same quantity of flint (Lewin 1980, p. 116).
This was a clear improvement that would have been adopted earlier if the
humans of the period had possessed the required intelligence. Unfortunately,
the two step procedure of constructing a core and then striking it just as
required to produce the desired blades required considerable intelligence.
Presumably, when sufficient mutations had accumulated in a population, the
newer technique was adopted. Plausibly, individuals of unusual ability might
have invented the improved technique earlier, but in the absence of a high
enough average ability, the technique might have died with the inventors.
Eventually, the Middle Paleolithic tools were replaced with those of the
Upper Paleolithic, which were finer. In Europe, the transition went along with
anatomically modern humans replacing the Neandertal, making it very plausible
that the modern humans were more intelligent, although the size of the brain
case did not increase. (There is some dispute as to how perfectly the
replacement of the Neandertals corresponds with the change in the tool kits).
Also with the shift from the Middle Paleolithic to the Upper Paleolithic were
a number of other changes including the introduction of bone and ivory as raw
materials, and the production of elaborate works of arts. These make it very
likely that intelligence indeed increased, probably due to replacement of the
Neandertals by new arrivals who benefited from more accumulated mutations.
As Mellars (1994, p. 49) recently put it, "there can be no doubt that the
whole spectrum of stone tool production in Upper Palaeolithic communities
shows a degree of dynamism and creativity which contrast sharply with the much
more uniform and conservative patterns of technology documented throughout the
long time ranges of the Lower and Middle Palaeolithic periods." He had earlier
summarized the evidence (Mellars, 1991) and discussed the possibility that
(Mellars, 1989, 357) "the increased complexity apparent in Upper Palaeolithic
technology reflects-at least in part-some kind of fundamental change in the
basic structure of human thinking or cognition associated (at least broadly)
with the transition from archaic to modern human populations." The most
obvious explanation of this is that the intelligence of the earlier
populations had not yet reached the levels required for the Upper Palaeolithic
technology.
Wynn (1985) after examining stone tools, classifies the makers of Oldowan
scrappers as using only preoperational thinking in the Piagetian scheme, while
the makers of Acheulean artifacts from Isimila as using operational concepts,
partially because the later work exhibited a high level of symmetry. However,
Wynn did not believe Levallois technique required more intelligence. He states
it is a difficult technique to master, but not one that is difficult
conceptually. Gowlett (1984) is another author who has emphasized the
intellectual abilities of early hominids.
It is hard to imagine that during the long periods when humans used only
primitive technologies, that the only thing preventing them from using more
sophisticated technologies was that no one had discovered these technologies.
It is implausible, for instance, that during very long periods of time
(thousands of years) that someone would not have invented fancier methods of
knapping stones, or the idea of hafting tools. Given the superiority of these
methods, they would have been widely used had the population been
intellectually capable of mastering their use.
The conclusion is that the earlier populations were of lower intelligence
than current populations. With ongoing selection for intelligence it is likely
that intelligence gradually increased. This evolution of intelligence
presumably took the form of the occasional appearance of intelligence
increasing mutations, and then the gradual diffusion of these mutations. The
slow rate of increase of intelligence would be consistent with the rate at
which intelligence increasing mutations were occurring limiting the increase
in intelligence, rather than any cultural factors, which operate much more
rapidly.
There is other evidence for gradual increases in intelligence within
relatively recent periods. Whallon (1989) points out that two major
demographic events occurred in the earlier part of the Upper Palaeolithic, the
expansion of human populations in Australia and Siberia, arguing that the
occurrence of these two events after a long period of human presence on earth
requires an explanation. He argues these required new socio-cultural
structures, but that these structures would have required the development at
this time of even more fundamental human capacities for conceptualization and
communication. He associates most of these changes with a greater capacity for
more complex language, but a reading of his argument shows that all of the
required adaptations could have resulted from a higher level of intelligence,
with humans earlier not having the intelligence needed to settle these
relatively difficult environments of low resource density and high
unpredictability, and then settling them once they had developed the required
intellectual abilities to support the cultural and communicative changes
required.
To argue that humans very early had high levels of intelligence requires
explaining why they did not settle these difficult environments. To argue they
had not yet developed necessary cultural traits raises the question of why
not. It is far simpler to argue that intelligence had been gradually
increasing, and at earlier periods it was inadequate to provide the cultural
techniques needed to settle such areas. As Whallon points out, the obstacle
could not have been the development of specific cultural forms since the forms
required for the Australian desert and for the cold of Siberia are quite
different. However, developing the relevant cultural forms (of kinship, past
and future tenses in language, the ability to communicate complex concepts, to
maintain rule based social organizations required to avoid wasting fights over
resources, etc.) could have required high intelligence (not his word, but his
words seem to imply intelligence) which had not earlier existed.
One terminological implication of the unidirectional selection should be
noted. It is frequently argued that one cannot speak of more advanced or more
primitive populations because all populations that have survived to the
present are well adapted to their environment, as evidenced by their having
survived. However, if all populations are evolving in the same direction, it
does make sense to discuss how far populations have progressed in the common
direction. For what ever characteristic being discussed, it does indeed make
sense to speak of some populations as advanced, and others as primitive.
Genetic Mechanisms
At first glance, if all current populations originated from a common
population, and each descendant population had experienced similar selective
pressures, the descendant populations would have experienced similar shifts in
gene frequencies. Thus, we would expect them to have similar intelligences.
One exception to this principle would be the action of chance, what is
known in population genetics as drift. If a population is small, the
accumulated action of chance can cause the frequency of a single gene in one
population to differ considerably from that in another population (see any
population genetics text such as Cavalli-Sforza & Bodmer, 1971). If
intelligence was determined by a single gene, observed population differences
in intelligence could easily be explained by drift. However, if drift was the
only factor operating, different intelligence promoting alleles would
predominant in different populations. One population might have an advantage
in having a higher frequency of one intelligence promoting allele, and another
population would have an advantage in the frequency of another intelligence
promoting allele. Many of the differences in frequency would cancel each other
out, leaving relatively small differences between populations in intelligence,
even if there were large differences in the frequencies of specific
intelligence promoting genes.
If we leave aside the influence of differential natural selection and
drift, natural selection with a uniform strength would apper unable to change
gene frequencies sufficiently to produce population wide intelligence
differences. Yet we do observe such differences. Why? A possible answer is
that, if populations do differ in size, they will differ in number of
advantageous mutations. This will lead to differences in intelligence.
Incidentally, this same theory could be applied to other issues such as the
evolution of disease resistance. The disease organisms in a large population
should have evolved more effective mechanisms for overcoming the host's
defenses than the organisms in a small population. When the populations come
into contact, there will be more diseases spreading from the large population
to the small population, than from the small to the large population. This is
indeed what was observed when the New and Old World populations were brought
into contact. The diseases introduced from Europe and Africa into the
Amerindian populations were more numerous and caused more harm than the
diseases introduced from the Americas into Europe (of which syphilis appears
the chief example).
The fact that more diseases spread from the Old World into the New World,
than in the other direction, is consistent with the Old World population
having indeed been significantly larger than the New World population during
the period when the two populations were separated.
Once such intelligence related genes had appeared in a population and
reached a high enough frequency that mere random variation could not eliminate
them (even advantageous mutations can disappear through the operation of
random factors), natural selection would have caused these genes to increase
in frequency and to gradually spread until they had reached all of the
populations that were exchanging genes with the populations where the
mutations first occurred.
What could happen to stop the spread of intelligence increasing mutations?
Obviously, if there was a large barrier to human migration, such as an ocean
across which people did not move, the spread of the advantageous alleles would
be stopped. Thus, one would expect that certain advantageous mutations would
have reached populations on one side of such a barrier, but not on the other
side.
Depending on which side of the barrier a particular advantageous mutation
emerged, there could be different favorable mutations on each side. For
instance, it is quite plausible that certain mutations originating in the
Americas were prevented from reaching Asia by the Pacific Ocean, while other
mutations originating in Asia were prevented from reaching the Americas by the
Pacific Ocean.
Current thinking is that the variations in intelligence between individuals
are related to variations in a large number of genes. While the magnitude of
the effects of variation at different genetic loci presumably vary, it is
plausible that the individuals who have received the larger number of
advantageous mutations have the higher intelligence. Of course, strictly
speaking, the individuals with the smallest number of advantageous mutations
could have had the mutations that exert the greatest effects, but it is a
convenient shorthand to talk merely in terms of the number of advantageous
mutations.
Likewise for populations. The population that has received the greatest
number of advantageous mutations would normally have the highest average
intelligence. This brings us to a natural question. Is there any reason to
believe that populations on one side of a barrier will have received more
mutations than on the other side? Yes, there is.
Given the same mutation rate on all continents (and there is no reason to
believe it differs) the number of favorable mutations (and only a small
percentage of mutations are likely to be intelligence increasing) will be
proportional to a continent's total population. Admittedly, a mutation may
take longer to diffuse through a large continent's population than through a
small ones population, but eventually any advantageous mutations should spread
throughout the whole population. Thus, we reach the conclusion that more
favorable mutations should be found on the side of a barrier with the larger
population.
Biraben, (1980, see the table in Cavalli-Sforza, Menozzi, & Piazza, 1994,
p. 68) has estimated prehistoric populations. The total world population at
400 B. C. is estimated to be 162 million. Oceania is only 1 million and the
Americas 6 million. Since the above estimates were for 400 B. C. when many Old
World areas had agriculture, the population differences may be somewhat
overstated. However, given the large area of Eurasia, it is plausible that its
total population at all times was appreciably larger than that in Australia or
the Americas.
As noted earlier, this implies that these two latter areas would have a lot
fewer intelligence raising mutations during any particular period. This would
in turn imply that over any particular period, such as that since the first
settlers reach Australia or the Americas, that any given degree of selective
pressure would have produced a greater increase in intelligence in Eurasia
than in Australia or the Americas.
The Mechanism of the Intelligence Lag in Australia
Let us start the discussion with the case of isolated populations with no
gene flow between them. The population's expected average intelligence would
vary with the number of relevant mutations that have occurred in it. In turn,
the total number of favorable mutations experienced would be proportional to
the population size (and to time).
The smaller, more isolated populations would lag in intelligence.
Populations for which this effect would be expected to be important include
Australia and the Americas. Both have relatively small populations that have
been isolated from the rest of the world for most of their history.
Roberts, Jones, & Smith (1990) have reported a date of 50+ years for human
related material from North Australia. Although the Australian population was
probably intellectually advanced when the continent was settled (they had to
be able to build at least bamboo rafts in order to cross the open ocean and
settle the Australian/New Guinea continent), after settlement it was probably
isolated from mutations originating elsewhere in the Old World. With a
population too small to generate as many mutations as the much larger Eurasian
population, it would have gradually lagged further and further behind Eurasia
in intelligence, even if the selective pressures for intelligence were as
strong.
Might there have been a continued arrival of new Eurasian genes? Probably
not. The Australians on upon European contact lacked ocean going boats. Most
likely, the continent was settled by accidental immigrants who were
shipwrecked there while attempting voyages along the coast of the Sunda shelf,
which is now Indonesia (for a summary history see Jones, 1989, pp. 754-756).
The first settlers were unopposed and had a virgin continent to exploit. Thus
they were able to settle and to flourish, even if upon arrival they were
tired, unorganized, and not knowledgeable about the terrain or food.
However, once the land was settled, newer arrivals would have a much
smaller chance of contributing to the Australian gene pool. Like many other
hunter-gatherers, the Australians encountered by the first Europeans were
suspicious of strangers and hostile to members of other groups not related to
them. Their ancestors were probably similar. Thus, after the first group had
settled the land, more recent arrivals would have been treated as hostile, and
would be expected to have been exterminated by the first arrivals (Jones 1989
argues that more recent arrivals would probably have been killed, although he
allows for the possibility of women being incorporated as wives). Upon
arrival, probably as a result of a raft being blown off course, the newcomers
would have been unorganized, weak, and few in number. This would have made it
possible for them to be killed, if those already there had wished to do so.1
New arrivals would have had the disadvantage of not knowing the terrain, or
how to exploit local food sources. Hunting and gathering by the first settlers
would have lowered the density of food resources, putting new arrivals at a
disadvantage.
Also, as sea levels rose, the distances from Indonesia to Australia grew.
This may have prevented, or even eliminated any further settlement and gene
flow.
After the initial Australian/New Guinea settlement, any favorable genes
reaching the Indonesian Archipelago would have been unlikely to reach the
Australians. The Australians would have gradually fallen behind in
intelligence due to their isolation from the rest of the world's population.
The above argument is strongest if once Australia was settled, there were
no further arrivals of peoples from Eurasia who could have brought
intelligence raising alleles from Eurasia. However, some argue that the
prehistoric Australian human skeletal remains differ sufficiently from each
other to imply the arrival of more than one wave of migration (Brown, 1993).
Variations in morphology and gene frequencies among various Australian
populations have been interpreted as evidence of multiple waves of settlement
(Cavalli-Sforza et al. 1994, pp. 345-346). In particular, Thorne has
identified two morphological types of late Pleistocene Australian crania which
he interprets as evidence of two separate migrations to Australia (Thorne 1977
as cited by Habgood, 1989, p. 259). The arrival of the dingo, a
semi-domesticated dog, almost certainly a companion of people, at about 4
thousand years ago, shows that at least one other successful incursion
occurred (Jones, 1989, p. 756).
Shortly before the first Europeans arrived, there were trepanging visitors
to northern Australia from what is now Indonesia (Macknight, 1976), but they
were too few and too late to have an appreciable genetic impact.
A somewhat similar theory is provided by Thorne and Wolpoff (1981) to
explain the larger facial size and masticatory apparatus in the peripheral
regions of Australasia. They hypothesize that technological progress in food
preparation first occurred in South China, where genes for reduced masticatory
apparatus appeared. These gradually spread to the periphery of the region in
Australia. They say that (p. 348) "while some changes might eventually
characterize the periphery, by this time further reductions would have
occurred at the center." While their argument does not explain why the
shrinkage of the masticatory apparatus should proceed more rapidly in the
center than in the periphery, their theory does have some resemblance to the
theory proposed here. The theory proposed here makes the progress more rapid
at the center because its population is larger, and the total number of
favorable mutations greater. Incidentally, if intelligence does lead to
greater progress in food preparation (such as the discovery of cooking, or of
the ability to make pots for boiling), the theory here could explain the
larger masticatory apparatus in the Australians.
So far only a theoretical case has been made for why lower intelligence in
Australian aboriginals and American Indians should be expected. It is now time
to look at the evidence to see if the theory is supported.
Australian Aboriginal Intelligence
The evidence is that Australian aborigines are low in intelligence in
comparison to other populations (Seagrim & Lendon, 1980, and Klich, 1988,
provide an introduction to the literature).
McElwain & Kearney (1973, p. 53) summarize the results of a number of
intelligence tests. The aborigines do consistently worse, with the
disadvantage greatest on those with a high verbal component. On Raven's
Progressive Matrices the difference is given as .95 standard units. The
Queensland Test restults are perhaps the most useful. This is a modification
of a test (the PIR test) devised to select troops from the Pacific Islands.
'se of this test in Papua and New Guinea reduced the proportion of those
unable to master the basic Australian Infantry training from 20% to about 2%.
It thus appears to have validity in indicating the ability of a population
from a different culture to master European techniques. The material is
completely non-verbal in both administration and response and the material is
non-representational with no pictures and no object used that has a common use
or meaning. The scores are reported to be .99 standard units below that of
Europeans (McElwain & Kearney, 1973, p. 53), with the scores varying with the
extent of contract with Europeans. "the aboriginal groups are inferior to
Europeans, and in approximately the same degree as they have lacked contract
with European groups. The Dunwich children give results very close to those
for European children, the Palm Island results are lower and the remote areas
of the Northern Territory are further depressed" (McElwain & Kearney, 1973, p.
47).
Reference to the test manual (p. 123) shows the Palm Island group to be one
where "Traditional tribal life has been absent for many years and only a few
old people are familar with Aboriginal languages. The Aborginal people have
been drawn from tribes from all parts of Queensland and have no common
language except English and a form of camp-Pidgin. Very little of the food
consumed is derived from native sources or by traditional means." Of the other
medium contact group, that at Cherbourg, it was said "Tribal life and language
are virtually extinct."
To give a flavor for the results, Figure 1 shows the results for a European
group Taringa State Primary School, a Brisbane suburb, a medium contact
aboriginal school (Palm Island), and a low contact aboriginal group
(Maningrida Schoo. in Arnhem Land) whose tribal life was described as almost
intact. The age patterns are rather interesting, with there apparently being a
ceiling effect for the European children, and the low contact aboriginals
shows surprisingly little improvement with age.
Although not graphed, the Dunwich European and aboriginal samples (given
for only three age groups) are indeed very similar.
De Lacey (1971, 1972) has reported Peabody Picture Vocabulary test scores
for high-contact aboriginals (urban, not speaking a native dialect) and for
low-soci-economic status whites. The 40 Northern territory aboriginals
averaged 64, and the 80 Wollongong low-socio-economic white children averaged
94, a difference well beyond the .01 level of probability. Interestingly, on
Piagetian classificatory ability tests the aborigines were in the same range
as the low-socioeconomic status whites (i.e, below the white average) (De
Lacey, 1970, 1971). De Lacey (1972) also reports Peabody results for Bourke
Island part aborigines (63 IQ) and Bourke Island low socio-economic status
whites (87 IQ).
Of course, it is hard to know from test results whether the poor
performance is due completely to environmental effects, or partially to
genetics. The controversy with regard to aborigines appears in form and nature
of arguments to be very similar to that in the US about blacks and whites.
Space does not permit reviewing the issue here (Jensen, 1980, is the standard
early source and Herrnstein & Murray, 1994, give more recent references)
One preliminary issue should be dealt with. Much of the work done with
aborigines has involved Piagetian tests, especially of conservation. Those
working in the Piagetian tradition (including, I suspect, the authors of the
cited studies) do not think of these as intelligence tests. However, the
results of these tests do correlate well with traditional intelligence when
used with young children, and with performance on tests of academic
achievement, including mathematics and reading (see Table 14.1 in Jensen for a
long list of the correlation coefficients that have been discovered in various
studies). Indeed, as Jensen (1980, pp. 669-676) points out, the individual
items of these tests appear to be superior to the individual items on standard
intelligence tests. The tests appear to involve less knowledge that is
specific to Western cultures than some may think.
Consider the conservation of volume. Seagrim & Lendon (1980, Chap. 3)
describe in detail their procedures. For instance, for the conservation of
quantity the test starts with pouring water from one glass to another of the
same size and confirming that the child understands they contain the same
quantity. The water from one of these glasses is then poured into a tall, thin
glass and the child asked if it still contains the same amount as before, with
the practical implications made obvious by offering to give the child one of
the glasses. Interesting, young children will normally believe there is more
water in the taller glass than in a shorter glass, even though the water had
just been poured from an identical glass into the taller one. As children
mature they come to understand that the quantity of water is conserved when it
is poured form one glass to another. The child is then considered to have
acquired the concept of conservation. Questions are used to establish whether
the child understands the concept of conservation of volume, and the idea of
reversibility. In general, more intelligent children make the transition at an
earlier age.
A similar test for conservation of weight used identical balls of
plasticine. Two identical balls were shown to have the same effect on simple
balance, and the child was questioned to be sure he understood the role of
weight. "The child was then asked to deform one of the balls of plasticine and
to make judgements about the consequences of placing it and its equal partner
on the pans of the balance." The child would then be questioned to see if he
really understood that weight was unchanged when he deformed the ball of
plasticine.
Tests of this type can be given to children not exposed to Western cultures
since they will have had experience with such simple tasks such as pouring
liquids from one container to another. Indeed, it could be argued that in the
dry Australian desert a knowledge of the idea of conservation would be more
important than in Western civilization, where water conservation is
unimportant. Certainly, the child who can be deceived about whether he was
getting as big a drink as another by simply giving him less, but in a taller
container would be at a disadvantage.
In the US, differences between whites and blacks have been found using
Piagetian tests that are similar to those found using traditional intelligence
tests. Interestingly, US aboriginals score well above blacks and close to very
low socio-economic status whites, although they are culturally further (many
being bilingual) from the white majority than the blacks (Gaudia, 1972). While
the charge is frequently made that Westerners always do better on tests
designed by Westerners, this is not true for the Piagetian tests, and Arctic
Eskimos have been found to do better than white Canadian children (McArthur,
1968, p. 48) on many Piagetian tests, including one of volume conservation
(such as employed with Australian aborigines), and Canadian Indians do almost
as well as Eskimos (Jensen, 1980 citing Vernon,1965, and McArthur, 1968).
A sample of adopted and fostered aboriginals (typically of mixed European
and aboriginal ancestry) children in Adelaide that had been reared in the
homes of Australians showed performance on tests of conservation of quantity
and conservation of weight that was significantly poorer than the norms for
Europeans, although on other tests, including serration, the Nixon test, and
the Peabody Picture Vocabulary test, the performance approximated European
norms (Dasen, de Lacey, & Seagrim, 1973). The majority of the children were
also reported to be below average in school work, and most were reported to
experience particular difficulty with math. Since being raised in a European
background controlled for differences in the environment, that aboriginal
performance was below European norms is strong evidence for a genetic
difference.
The general performance of aboriginal children in school is poor. Seagrim,
& Lendon (1980, p.7) describing it as follows, "The realities are that the
Aboriginal children of Australia are obliged to undergo a form of Westernized
schooling which is rarely modified to suit their particular needs. This
involves most of them in daily attendance at school for about eight years but
leaves them mainly illiterate and innumerate. The imposition of this regime is
seen by its purveyors to be in the best interests of the Aborigines and is not
obviously resented by the children's parents who, one the contrary, ask only
that it be more successful." If the phrase "mainly illiterate and innumerate"
is accurate (and the writers are clearly very sympathetic to the aborigines
and reluctant to impugn their abilities), it would seem hard to argue that the
aborigines are of an intelligence similar to that of many other groups. For
instance, in the United States, Amerindians after eight years of schooling
would not be described as "mainly illiterate and innumerate", although they
clearly perform below white norms. The evidence is that the aborigines do
poorly in school and are disproportionately in slow learner classes (Callan,
1986, p. 42).
Additional evidence is supplied by studies of aborigines in the Northern
Territory (de Lemos, 1967, 1969a). On Piagetian tests of conservation the
aboriginal children did appreciably worse than Swiss children did on the same
tests. There was a statistically significant tendency for the part-European
children (even though typically only one eighth European) to do better on
tests of conservation, even though both were in the same culture. This was
significant at the 1% level for the tests on quantity and weight, and
significant at the 5% level for the tests on area and length (de Lemos, 1967).
The non-aboriginal genes had been left by various temporary male residents of
the community several generations ago, and children of different ancestries
were treated the same in the community. De Lemos (1967, 1969b) reports an
experiment with conservation in which adult aboriginal subjects were offered a
choice between two glasses of sugar. One long and thin glass had been filled
with one cup of sugar in front of the subjects, and the other, a wider and
shorter glass, had been filled with one and a half cups of sugar, again in
front of the subject. "Eight out of twelve Aborginal women took the sugar from
the long glass; that is the glass which had less sugar." (De Lemos, 1967, p.
7,). Incidentally, this illustrates the type of discriminations that are
tested in a test of conservation (here of quantity).
De Lemos (1967) notes in reference to conservation that "According to
Piaget's theory this concept is basic to all logical thinking, and this
retardation would therefore indicate that intellectual development proceeds
much more slowly in the Aboriginal culture, and that in general Aborigines
would achieve a lower level of intellectual functioning than in normally
achieved in the European-culture." She goes on to say "However the significant
differences found between the part-Aboriginal and the full-Aboriginal children
tested at Hermannsburg suggest that they may be racial differences in
intelligence which could have contributed to this retardation. Vetta (1972)
has critiqued her methodology.
However, Dasen (1972) was unable to reproduce in the same populationthe de
Lemos results for better performance in the partly white aboriginals (and
again found poor performance), leaving the situation unclear. An examination
of the Dasen (1973) results shows that the part-aboriginal children generally
did do better than the full aboriginal children (except on conservation of
length tests) although the differences were not statistically significant. It
is not known whether the difference between the two studies is statistically
significant, or if it might better be attributed to sampling variability.
Taking the two samples together, some support for a genetic difference can be
deduced.
Of course, aboriginals need not do poorly on all tests. Kearins (1981,
1986) reports on experiments measuring memory for spatial location of objects.
She found that aboriginals did better than whites. Since this was true of
aboriginal who were at least a couple of generations removed from their
original lifestyles, while these did not differ much from those who were less
acculaturated, it appears likely that there is a genetic difference here.
Kearins argued that this spatial ability was very useful for pathfinding in
the desert. However, Drinkwater (1976) did not find such an advantage for a
sample of non-desert aboriginals, although Kearins pointed out that even
performing at the white level was impressive, since the aboriginals in general
did not do this well.
Additional evidence of aboriginal superiority at spatial relations is
supplied by Kearins (1988). She found that when day care children (4 to 4.5
years of age) were asked to indicate by pointing the direction to their home,
58% of the aboriginal children were correct while none of the university day
care center children could do this and only 5% of those in an urban blue
collar center, while the aboriginal children were significantly worse at
knowing their addresses, ages, or at counting than were the white children.
The aboriginal children were also significantly better at the kindergarten
game of fishing (catching artificial fish) which required speed and manual
dexterity.
A possible explanation for the aboriginal advantage in spatial memory is
provided by (Klekamp et al.,1994) who report that Australian aboriginals have
a larger visual cortex than Caucasians.
The brains of Australian aborigines also show a prominent lunate sulcus at
a higher rate than in other races (Baker, 1974, p. 293), which Baker notes
indicates that "the visual area does not extend nearly so far round the
posterior end of the occipital lobe on to its lateral surface" in Europids as
in Australids. This is a feature considered by some to be relatively
primitive. Also the percentage of skulls with fronto-temporal pteriorn or one
or both sides is much higher in Australids (and Negrids) than in Europids of
Europe (Baker 1974, p. 299). It is not known what the implications, if any, of
these morphological differences are for brain function. However, the tendency
that some observers see for the Australian aborigines to retain many primitive
features is very consistent with their isolation having prevented the genes
for many traits from having reached them.
A possible biological basis for low intelligence in Australian aborigines
is provided by their relatively small brain sizes, which is reported to be
about 85% of that for the normal European (Baker, 1974, p. 292), with some of
the smallest brains reported in normal people being found among them (Coon,
1962, p. 411). The most recent work (Klekamp et al., 1987) confirmed earlier
work by finding a statistically significant difference in fresh brain weight
with aboriginal brains averaging 1241 grams, versus 1421 for Caucasians.
Harper & Mina (1981) reported statistically signifucant (p<.001) brain weight
differences (from the same set of brains) in paired samples matched for age
and height. Brain size (as measured by either head size or magnetic resonance
imagining) is known to be correlated with intelligence (see the list of
studies in Lynn 1991b; Miller, 1994; Rushton, 1994, 1995; Rushton & Osborne,
1995, and Rushton & Ankney, in press).
The isolation of the now extinct Tasmanians should have isolated them from
late occurring mutations on the Australian mainland. Although no mental tests
data is available on the Tasmanians, their culture is usually considered among
the most primitive known. Apparently, they are the only people known that
could not make fire, but had to get it from another band if theirs went out.
Likewise, their stone tools were unhafted (Ryan, 1982).
Of course, in documenting the low intelligence of Australian aboriginals
the purpose is not to encourage arbitrary discrimination against them. There
is enough variability in humans that decisions should not be based only on
group membership. However, elementary application of Bayes' theorem does show
group membership to be relevant where the group averages differ (Miller,
1994).
American Aboriginal Intelligence
A similar story would apply to the American natives. They test worse than
Caucasians and Mongoloids (Lynn, 1991a, Table 5) even though they are
considered to be Mongoloids, a group that generally tests well (Lynn, 1987).
Space here does not permit reviewing the extensive literature on the
intelligence of American natives (fortunately much of it is reviewed in
McShane & Berry, 1988).
The best single source of evidence on American Indian intelligence is
provided by the Coleman report. This sampled large numbers of children widely
across the US and picked up non-reservation Indians who would be functioning
in the main stream US society. Jensen (1980, p. 479) calculated the
Indian/white differences as .67, .93, .79, and .93 standard deviation units at
grade 3, 6, 9, and 12 for verbal IQ and .38, .83, .54, and .57 for vonverbal
IQ. These were appreciably smaller than observed for blacks (in spite of their
higher socio-economic condition and greater acculturation). The smaller
deficit on the nonverbal tests is a widely reported result, which probably
reflects a true difference in the pattern of abilities.
The Americas are believed to have been settled by a relatively small
population passing over the Bering Land Bridge from Asia. They probably
brought only some of the alleles for high intelligence with them from Asia.
The subsequent sea level rise cut them off from the mutations arising in
Eurasia. Since the Americas had a lower population than Eurasia (implying a
smaller number of favorable mutations), they gradually came to lag behind the
Eurasian populations in intelligence.
The parts of Siberia that the Amerindian ancestors came from is at the
continent's periphery, far from the more densely populated areas. Thus, it is
possible that advantageous alleles that had originated elsewhere in Eurasia
had not yet reached the populations at the time that they crossed the land
bridge, and that the alleles had not reached them when the Americas were
isolated by the bridge's submersion.
[Image]
Testable Implications
What other predictions emerge from the theory that mutations favorable to
intelligence have not reached certain populations? Right now, while the
evidence is quite strong that there are genes that contribute to intelligence
and other forms of behavior, exactly what these genes are and where they are
located is unknown.
Evidence has recently been presented that several genetic markers are
statistically more common in those of high intelligence than in those of low
intelligence (Plomin et al., 1994; Plomin et al., 1995). Recently the first
case of an allele that differs in frequency between racial groups and affects
a mental ability has been reported (Berman & Noble, 1995). Given the rate of
progress in molecular genetics, it is likely that several more alleles that
have a positive or negative effect on intelligence will soon be located.
Recently, alcohol consumption by Orientals in North America was shown to be
largely predicted by a single gene (Tu & Israel, 1995), with differing
prevalence of the gene able to explain much of the racial differences in
drinking. The above theory predicts similar patterns for intelligence
affecting genes.
If the above theory is right, not only will these genes prove to differ in
frequency between populations in different areas of the world, but some of the
ones identified in European or northeast Asian populations (the populations
most commonly studied, simply because they are convenient to the leading
laboratories) will be found to be essentially absent (a low frequency may be
the result of recent mixing with Europeans) in the original aboriginal
populations in such areas as Australia and the Americas.
The above theory raises the possibility that certain alleles with a
favorable effect on intelligence may have become fixed in European or
Northeast Asian populations if they originated in these regions, (and possibly
even if they originated elsewhere but reached these populations early enough
for natural selection to fix them). Studies that are limited to just one group
(such as Caucasians or Japanese) may not detect a correlation of these genes
with intelligence. The above argument would suggest that mixed populations
(such as those of mixed Australian Aboriginal and Caucasian descent) might
very profitably be investigated. A finding that possession of a particular
genetic marker correlated with intelligence would suggest that the marker
either directly affected intelligence, or was close to a gene that affected
intelligence.
Of course, in populations that are a mixture of two populations that differ
in intelligence, any gene that differs in frequency may be merely serving as a
marker for the extent of admixture (or for the extent of acculturation). It
would be necessary to control for this. A good technique is to study siblings
of mixed parentage to discover if a sibling who inherited the allele believed
to raise intelligence also exhibited higher intelligence. An implication of
the theory of this paper is that sibling studies (ideally of dizygotic twins)
where one parent was aboriginal (either Australian or American) and one was
European or Asian (i.e. what in animal genetics is called a F1 cross) would be
a very good strategy for identifying alleles that affected intelligence. By
having the offspring raised in the same family, the risk that a particular
allele was merely serving as a marker for the extent of admixture or for
acculturation would be reduced.
Many genetic markers, including blood group, human leukocyte antigen genes,
and restriction length polymorphisms, are known to differ between populations
(Cavalli-Sforza et al. 1994). It should be possible to estimate the extent of
admixture independently of the genes believed to have a link with
intelligence. Independent measures of acculturation would have to be sought as
a control. This differs from the procedure of the major quantitative tract
loci studies of intelligence so far (Plomin, et al. 1994; Plomin, et al.
1995), which limited itself only to Caucasians.
It was argued that some isolated areas such as Australia may have received
few new mutations after settlement. However, if they experienced continued
selection for intelligence, some of the alleles that the population arrived
with may have become fixed, or nearly fixed in their populations. In this
case, the standard deviation of intelligence should be smaller in such
populations than in the populations that have been continually receiving new
genes from other populations. This is a testable prediction.
Africans are generally found to have somewhat lower standard deviations
than Caucasians (Jensen, 1980). This might be explained by a slower migration
of alleles into Africa. Many intelligence relevant alleles would have reached
them so long ago that they had become fixed, and many other alleles would not
have reached them yet, even if they accounted for appreciable variation in
other populations. In the areas that have had continual access to new
mutations there will be more alleles that have not become fixed, causing a
greater standard deviation of intelligence.
Incidentally, this ongoing process of new mutations coming into a
population followed by selection for them may be the way to resolve the
paradox of why there is so much genetic variation for intelligence (g), if g
is a beneficial trait.
If intelligence is subject to unidirectional selection in which people with
a higher intelligence always benefit reproductively from being able to outwit
those of lower intelligence, it is likely that any given time there will be
some of higher intelligence than others, thus solving the problem.
As intelligence gradually increases, it is to be expected that a few
individuals with sufficient intelligence to do psychometrics and discover the
concept of g will emerge. At this time, only a small fraction of the
population is likely to have sufficient intelligence to do psychometrics and
to understand the concept of g. Thus, the finding of a wide range in
intelligence is perhaps not as surprising as it might appear at first.
Likewise, with there being several continent sized populations of different
sizes, it is to be expected that the larger ones will benefit from access to a
larger number of mutations, and will pull ahead in intelligence. Thus the
theory predicts that the populations of continents of different size will
differ in intelligence. It is to be expected that the major innovations will
occur first among the more intelligent population on the most populous
continents (assuming equal selection pressure for intelligence). Thus, it is
not surprising that seagoing ships and the navigation skills required to cross
oceans to visit other continents first emerged in Eurasia. These innovations
brought more advanced populations into contact with the populations on the
less populated continents. The more advanced populations had developed more
advanced technology and established control of the Americas and Australia. The
superior intelligence of the Eurasian populations (primarily from Europe) led
to them having a higher level of education and higher incomes that the
aboriginal populations of Australia or the Americas (for documentation of the
role of intelligence in affecting income see Herrnstein & Murray, 1994)
The Role of Isolation in Evolutionary Advance
The argument that isolated populations, lacking access to mutations
originating on other continents, may lack certain intelligence promoting
alleles, may surprise those who remember that biologists have argued that
evolution is faster in small isolated populations (Mayr, 1966). Am I arguing
against this generally accepted proposition? No. The two propositions are
really different.
The belief that evolution occurs faster in small isolated populations can
be traced to several effects. One is that deleterious recessive mutations may
be eliminated more rapidly in such populations since the carriers are more
likely to mate.
Another is that gene flow from outside of the population may prevent the
evolution of gene combination best adapted to a particular environment,
especially one on the fringes of the range of an environment. With isolation,
the gene flow stops and such new combinations can emerge.
More importantly, innovations that require two or more mutations to succeed
may occur more easily in small populations. Suppose that one gene could occur
in forms Aa and another in Bb where AB represents a superior combination to
ab, aB, and to Ab. However, ab is fitter than aB and Ab. This could happen if
A and B work well together, and a and b work well together, but aB and Ab are
not as successful combinations. Suppose the population starts out with all
individuals being ab. If mutations occur causing A or B appear, these genes
would be expected to die out since they would be appearing in the heterozygous
forms of Ab or aB, which have lower reproductive success. Even if simultaneous
mutations occurred which created AB, it would have only ab's to mate with, and
its offspring would be Ab or aB, both of which would be at a disadvantage.
Thus, a large population of ab is evolutionary stable against invasion by a or
b.
Now consider a small isolated population, possibly on an island. The B
allele could emerge, and by the operation of drift come to be the common
allele, and possible to be even fixed. In a population that was predominantly
aB, the A allele can then invade. Since AB is fitter than aB, once the A
allele appears at an appreciable frequency, it can be expected to spread.
Thus, the small isolated population can come to have the genotype of AB, which
is fitter than ab. If the populations then become combined (perhaps by the
island reuniting with the mainland), the AB variety may be able to spread at
the expense of the ab. Such a spread is especially plausible if there has
emerged a mechanism that keep AB from mating with those of the ab type.
The argument can easily be extended to where three mutations or more are
required to produce a new variety or a new species. It is argued such
combinations can most easily occur in small, isolated populations. This
especially applicable to the emergence of new species where multiple mutations
may be required which work well as a group, but any one of which is
deleterious alone.
In contrast, this paper deals with simple mutations which increase the
intelligence, and hence the fitness of the organism. These mutations are
capable of invading a population and then diffusing through it. For these
types of alleles, the key question is how many such mutations have reached a
population.
Conclusions
There has been continuous worldwide selection for intelligence, although
its strength may have varied with climate. Intelligence gradually increased,
as reflected in the sophistication of the human tool kits. This increase was
caused by intelligence increasing mutations, followed by the spread of these
mutations. These mutations occurred at approximately the same rate (per
million population) on different continents, but in absolute number were most
common in the Eurasian land mass with its high population.
When Australia and the Americas were settled the original populations
lacked certain alleles because the relevant mutations had not yet occurred, or
because these mutations had not reached the relevant parts of Eurasia. After
Australia and the Americas came to be isolated from the larger Eurasian
populations, they did not receive further immigrants. Although a few
intelligence raising mutations occurred in their populations, the smaller
Australian and American populations implied that the total number of
beneficial mutations was less than in Eurasia. Thus, the intelligence of the
Australian and American populations came to lag behind that of the rest of the
world. Of course, other factors, such as weaker selection for intelligence in
certain parts of the world (such as the tropics) may have played a role.
This lower intelligence, along with other effects of isolation due to lack
of disease resistance, and lack of access to cultural innovation, placed these
populations at a disadvantage when they did come into contact with seafaring
populations from Eurasia (Europeans) and led to European conquest of these
populations. After the conquests, the lower intelligence result in the native
populations having trouble competed and having an on average lower income than
those of Eurasian descent in all of these countries.
References
Alexander, Richard D. (1990). How Did Humans Evolve. Ann Arbor, Museum of
Zoology, Special Publication No. 1.
Baker, J. R. (1974). Race. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barbujani, G., Pilastro, A., Domenico, S. D., & Renfrew, (1994). Genetic
variation in North Africa and Eurasia: Neolithic demic diffusion vs.
Paleolithic colonization. American Journal of Physical Anthropology 95:
137-154.
Berman, S. M. & Noble, E. P. (1995). Reduced visuospatial performance in
children with the D2 dopamine receptor A1 alle. Behavioral Genetics, 25,
45-58.
Biraben, J.-N. (1980). An essay concerning mankind's evolution. Population
4: 1-13.
Bouchard, T. J., Jr., (1993). The genetic architecture of human
intelligence. In Vernon, P. A. (Ed.). The Biological Basis of Intelligence,
Norwood: Ablex, 33-94.
Bouchard, T. J., Jr., Lykken, D. T., McGue, M., Sega, N. L., & Tellegen, A.
(1990). Sources of human psychological differences: The Minnesota study of
twins reared apart. Science, 250, 223-250.
Brown, P. (1993). Recent human evolution in East Asia and Australasia. in
Aitken, J., Stringer, C. B., & Mellars, P. A. Eds. The Origin of Modern Humans
and the Impact of Chronometric Dating. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
pp. 217-233.
Buss, David M. (1994). The Evolution Of Desire. New York: Basic Books.
Calvin, W. (1990). ThE Ascent Of Mind: Ice Age Climates and the Evolution
of Intelligence. New York: Bantam.
Callan, V. J. (1986). Australian Minority Groups. Syndney, Harcourt, Brace,
Jovanovich
Cavalli-Sforza, L. L. & Bodmer, W. F. (1971). THe Genetics of Human
Populations. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., Menozzi, P., & Piazza, A. (1994). The History And
Geography Of Human Genes. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Coon, C. S. (1962). The origin of races. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Dasen, P. R. (1972). The development of conservation in aboriginal
children. International Journal of Psychology, 7, No. 2, 75-85.
Dasen, P. R. (1973). Piagetian research in Central Australia. In Kearney,
G. E., de Lacey, P. R. & Davidson, G. R. (Eds.). THe Psychology Of Aboriginal
Australians (pp. 89-96). Sydney: John Willey and Sons Australasia Pty. Ltd.
Dasen, P. R., de Lacey, P. R. & Seagrim, G. N. (1973). Reasoning ability in
adopted and fostered aboriginal children. In Kearney, G. E., de Lacey, P. R. &
Davidson, G. R. (Eds.), The Psychologyof Aboriginal Australians (pp. 97-104).
Sydney: John Willey and Sons Australasia Pty. Ltd.
de Lacey, P. R. (1970). A cross-cultural study of classificatory ability in
Australia. Journal of Cross Cultural Psychology, 1, No. 4, 293-304.
de Lacey, P. R. (1971). Classificatory ability and verbal intelligence
among high-contact aboriginal and low socioeconomic white Australian children.
Journal of Cross Cultural Psychology, 2, No. 4, 393-396.
de Lacey, P. R. (1972). A relationship between classificatory ability and
verbal intelligence. International Journal of Psychology, 7, No. 4, 243-246.
de Lemos, M. M. (1967). The development of the concept of conservation in
Australian aboriginal children. A paper presented to the 39th ANZAAS Congress,
Section J, Melbourne.
de Lemos, M. M. (1969a). Conceptual development in aboriginal children:
implications for aboriginal education. In Dunn, S. S., & Tatz, C. M. (Eds.)
Aborigines & Education. (pp. 244-263) Melbourne: Sun Books.
de Lemos, M. M. (1969b). The development of the concept of conservation in
Australian aboriginal children. International Journal of Psychology, 4, No. 4,
255-269.
Drinkwater, B. A. (1976). Visual memory skills of medium contract
Aboriginal children. Australian Journal of Psychology, 28, 37-43
Drinkwater, B. A. (1978). A reply to Kearins. Australian Journal of
Psychology, 30, 115-118.
Gaudia, G (1972). Race, social class, and age of achievement of
conservation on Piaget's tasks. Developmental Psychology, 6, 158-165.
Gowlett, J. (1984). Mental abilities of early man: A look at some hard
evidence. In Foley, R. (Ed.). (pp. 167-189). Hominid Evolution and Community
Ecology. London: Academic Press.
Habgood, P. J. (1989). The origin of anatomically modern humans in
Australasia. in Mellars, P. A., & Stringer, C. B. (Eds.). The Human
Revolution. (pp. 245-273). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Harper, C., & Mina, L. (1981). A comparison of Australian Caucasian and
Aboriginal brain weights. Clinical and Experimental Neurology 18, 44-51.
Herrnstein, R. J. & Murray, C. (1994). The Bell Curve: Intelligence and
Class Structure in American Life. New York: The Free Press.
Isaac, G. (1984). The archaeology of human origins. In Advances in World
Archeology, Vol. 3, pp. 1-87.
Itzkoff, S. (1994). The Decline of Intelligence in America. Westport:
Praeger.
Jensen, A. R. (1980). Bias In Mental Testing. New York: The Free Press.
Jinks, J. L. & Fulker, D. W. (1970). Comparison of the biometrical
genetical, MAVA, and classical approaches to the analysis of human behavior.
Psychological Bulletin, 73, 311-349.
Jones, R. (1989). East of Wallace's Line: Issues and problems in the
colonization of the Australian continent. In Mellars, P. A., & Stringer, C. B.
(Eds.). The Human Revolution. (pp. 31-38). Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Kearins, J. M. (1981). Visual spatial memory in Australian aboriginal
children of desert regions. Cognitive Psychology, 13, 434-460
Kearins, J. M. (1978). Visual memory skills of western desert and
Queensland children of Australian Aboriginal descent: A reply to Drinkwater.
Australian Journal of Psychology, 30, 1-5.
Kearins, J. M. (1986). Visual spatial memory in Aboriginal and white
Australian children. Australian Journal of Psychology, 38, 203-214
Kearins, J. M. (1988). Cultural elements in testing: The test, the tester,
and the tested. in Davis, G. (Ed.) Ethnicity and Cognitive Asessment:
Australian Perspectives. Darwin, DIT Press.
Klekamp, J., Riedel, A., Harper, C., Kretschmann, H. J. (1987). A
quantitative study of Australian aboriginal and Caucasian brains. Journal of
Anatomy, 150, 191-210.
Klekamp, J., Riedel, A., Harper, C., Kretschmann, H. J. (1994).
Morphometric study of the postnatal growth of the visual cortex of Australian
aborigines and Caucasians. Journal of Brain Research, 35, 541-548.
Klich, L. Z. (1988). Aboriginal cognition and psychological nescience. In
Irvine, S. H. & Berry, J. W. (Eds.) Human Abilities in Cultural Context (pp.
427-452). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lewin, R. (1989). HumAn Evolution: An Illustrated Introduction. Boston:
Blackwell Scientific Publications.
Lynn, R., (1987). The intelligence of the Mongoloids: A psychometric,
evolutionary and neurological thory. Personality and Individual Differences 8,
813-844.
Lynn, R., (1991a). Race differences in intelligence: a global perspective.
Mankind Quarterly, 31, 254-296.
Lynn, R., (1991b). The evolution of racial differences in intelligence.
Mankind Quarterly, 32, 99-121.
Macknight, C. C. (1976). The Voyage to MaRege: Macassan Trepangers in
Northern Australia. Carleton, Victoria: Melbourne University Press.
Mayr, E. (1966). Animal Species And Evolution. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
McArthur, R. S. (1968). Some differential abilities of northern Canadian
native youth. International Journal of Psychology, 3, 43-51.
McElwain, D. W.& Kearney, G. E. (1970). Queensland Test Handbook.
Melbourne: Australian Council for Educational Research, 1970.
McElwain, D. W.& Kearney, G. E. (1973). Intellectual development. In
Kearney, G. E., de Lacey, P. R. & Davidson, G. R. (Eds.). The Psychology of
Aboriginal Australians (pp. 43-56). Sydney: John Willey and Sons Australasia
Pty. Ltd.
McShane, D. & Berry, J. W. (1988). Native North Americans: Indian and Inuit
abilities. In Irvine, S. H. & Berry, J. W. (Eds.), Human Abilities In Cultural
Context (pp. 385-426). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mellars, P. (1989). Technologic changes across the Middle-Upper
Palaeolithic transition: economics, social, and cognitive perspectives. In
Mellars, P. A., & Stringer, C. B. (Eds.). The Human Revolution. (pp. 433-454).
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Mellars, P. (1991). Creative change and the emergence of modern humans in
Europe. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 1(1), 63-76.
Mellars, P. (1994). The Upper Palaeolithic Revolution. In Cunliffe, B.
(Ed.). The OxfoRd Illustrated Prehistory Of Europe. (pp. 42-79). Oxford,
Oxford University Press.
Miller, E. M. (1991). Climate and intelligence. Mankind Quarterly, 32
127-132.
Miller, E. M. (1993). Could r Selection Account for the African Personality
and Life Cycle? Personality and Individual Differences 15, 665-676.
Miller, Edward M, Paternal Provisioning versus Mate Seeking in Human
Populations, Personality and Individual Differences, Vol. 17, August 1994, No.
2, 227-255.
Miller, E. M, (1994). Intelligence and Brain Myelination: A Hypothesis.
Personality and Individual Differences, 17, 803-833.
Miller, E. M, (1994). The Relevance of Group Membership for Personnel
Selection: A Demonstration 'sing Bayes Theorem, Journal of Social, Political,
and Economic Studies 19, 3, 323-359.
Miller, E.M, (1995). Environmental Variability Selects for Large Families
only in Special Circumstances: Another Objection to Differential K Theory,
Personality and Individual Differences, 19 , 903-918.
Miller, E. M, (1995). Did the Neandertals Separate the Africans from the
Eurasians? Manuscript
Phelps, M. T. (1993). An examination of Lynn's evolutionary account of
racial differences in intelligence. Mankind Quarterly, XXXIII, 295-308.
Plomin, R., & Loehlin, J. C. (1989). Direct and indirect IQ heritability
estimates: a puzzle. Behavior Genetics, 19, 331-342.
Plomin R., McClearn, G., Smith, D.,Vignetti, S., Chorney, M., Venditti C.,
Kasarda, S., Thompson, L., Detterman, D., Daniels J., Owen, M., & McGuffin P.
(1994). DNA Markers Associated with High Versus Low IQ: The IQ Quantitative
Trait Loci (QTL) Project. Behavior Genetics, 24, 107-118.
Plomin, R., McClearn, G., Smith, D., Skuder, P., Vignetti, S., Chorney, M.,
Chorney, K., Kasarda, S., Thompson, L., Detterman, D., Petrill, S., Daniels
J., Owen, M., & McGuffin P. (1995). Allelic associations between 100 DNA
markers and high versus low IQ. Intelligence, 21, 31-48.
Porteus, S. D. (1931). The Psychology of a Primitive People: A Study of the
Australian Aborigine. London: Edward Arnold & Co.
Porteus, S. D. (1965). Porteus Maze Test: Fifty Years of Application. Palo
Alto, Pacific Books.
Roberts, G., Jones, R., & Smith, M. A. 1990. Thermoluminescence dating of a
50,000-year-old human occupation site in northern Australia. Nature
345,153-156.
Rowe, D. C. (1994). The Limits Of Family Influence: Genes, Experience, And
Behavior. New York: Guilford.
Ryan, L. (1982). The Aboriginal Tasmanians. St. Lucia: University of
Queensland Press.
Rushton, J. P. (1994). Sex and race differences in cranial capacity from
International Labor Office data. Intelligence, 19, 281-294.
Rushton, J. P. (1995). Race, Evolution and Behavior: A Life History
Perspective. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Rushton, J. P. & Osborne, R. T. (1995). Genetic and environmental
contributions to cranial capacity estimated in Black and White adolescents.
Intelligence, 20, 1-13.
Rushton, J. P. & Ankney, C. D. (1995). Brain size and Cognitive ability:
correlations with age, sex, social class, and race. Psychonomic Bulletin and
Review, in press.
Seagrim, G. & Lendon, R. (1980). Furnishing the Mind: A Comparative Study
of Cognitive Development in Central Australian Aborigines. New York: Sydney.
Thorne, A. G. (1977). Separation or reconciliation: Biological clues to the
development of Australian society. In Allen, J., Golson J. & Jones, R. (Eds.),
Sunda and Sahul: Prehistoric studies in Southeast Asia, Melanesia and
Australia. London: Academic Press: 197-204.
Thorne, A. G. & Wolpoff, M. H. (1981). Regional continuity in Australasian
Pleistocene hominid evolution. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 55,
337-339.
Tu, G & Israel, Y. (1995). Alcohol Consumption by Orientals in North
America is predicted largely by a single gene. Behavioral Genetics, 25, 59-65.
Vernon, P. E. (1965). Environmental handicaps and intellectual development.
Part II and Part III. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 35, 1-22.
Vetta, Atam (1972). Conservation in aboriginal children and "genetic
hypothesis". International Journal of Psychology, 7, No. 4, 247-256.
Vraniak, Damian A. (1993). Native Americans. In Sternberg, R. J. (Ed.),
Encyclopedia of Human Intelligence, . New York: Macmillan Publishing Co.
Weiss, Volkmar (1991). Why are racial differences in intelligence not
larger. Mankind Quarterly, 32, 133-136.
Whallon, R. (1989). Elements of cultural change in the Later Palaeolithic.
in Mellars, P. A., & Stringer, C. B. (Eds.). The Human Revolution. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, pp. 433-454.
Wills, Christopher (1991). Exons, Introns, and Talking Genes. New York:
Basic Books.
Wills, Christopher (1993). The Runaway Brain. New York: Basic Books.
Wynn, T. (1985). Piaget, stone tools and the evolution of human
intelligence. World Archaeology, 17, 32-44.
Footnote
1This might not have applied to arrivals closely following the original
arrivals, but such immigrants would be unlikely to be carrying alleles that
the original settlers lacked.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone