Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
Discrimination and Differentiation: An Ethical Biological Issue
George Sunderland Policy Analyst, Washington, D.C.
This paper discusses the ethical and biological implications of the
concept of discrimination. The author perceives freedom of speech and action
as endangered by prevailing anti-discrimination laws and notes that certain of
these run counter to sociobiological reality.
According to the Oxford English Dictionary, discrimination is defined as
"the act of discriminating or distinguishing; a distinction (made with the
mind or in action); the power of observing differences accurately, or to
making exact distinctions." This traditional definition is relatively value
neutral, and permitted the word to be used in favorable, as well as negative,
contexts. Indeed, to have called a man or woman a discriminating person was
traditionally considered a high compliment to a person's judgment, discretion,
or taste.
By a kind of linguistic Gresham's Law, however, the verbal equivalent of
base metal has driven the verbal equivalent of gold coinage out of
circulation. Since the mid-1950s in America, the word "discrimination" has
come to acquire an exclusively negative shading because of its politically
loaded use as a term of condemnation. Discrimination has quickly acquired the
following meaning: unfair and reprehensible behavior towards a representative
of a given race, religion, ethnic group, sex, or behavioral dysfunction (e.g.,
homosexuality). Latterly, it has been regarded as invidious and legally
actionable for a citizen to even notice or comment upon the distinguishing
characteristics of some offended group, even if no unfair action follows.
This new meaning of the word discrimination has spread internationally in
parallel with the current Western ideological movement to compel the belief
that all the races of mankind are identical. In some languages, the
introduction of the word "discrimination" to other languages has resulted in
linguistic monstrosities. While in English one discriminates in favor of or
against something, in German the word has acquired a transitive usage as seen
in the following example of the results of a playground quarrel: "Mutti, er
hat mich diskriminiert!"
Free Speech: One of the First Casualties
Amusing as such solecisms are, it is a fact that in virtually all
industrialized Western societies discrimination as recently defined is
regarded with official opprobrium, and large sums of tax money are spent to
root it out and criminalize transgressors. Indeed, Canada has surpassed the
United States in this respect, as there have already been cases of individuals
whose writings have been suppressed because they were considered
discriminatory. Whether in Canada, America, or Britain, combatting
discrimination has come to be a major function of government. Commissions are
established, laws and regulations are promulgated, employees are enrolled in
compulsory lectures, private businesses are obliged to certify
nondiscrimination, and government security clearances can be withheld on the
basis of hearsay testimony regarding an individual's alleged discriminatory
remarks.
Before we consider the long-run implications of such policy enforcement,
however, I would like to draw the reader's attention back to the original
meaning of discrimination, and examine it as an adaptive behavior in human
beings. As the Oxford dictionary definition makes clear, discrimination is
actually the cognitive ability to differentiate. While this capacity may be
very rudimentary in the lower orders of fauna, such as insects, as we ascend
the phylogenetic scale, life becomes more complex and its ability to survive
depends on simple judgments based on the ability to perceive differences. Is
the creature of my own species who is approaching me friend or foe? Is that
animal dangerous or tame? Is this plant poisonous or edible? Distinctions of
this sort are ludicrously simple, but they form the experiential data base of
any creature that expects to survive and propagate. Internalized, these
distinctions become prejudices, i.e., mnemonic devices that help sentient
creatures cope with unfamiliar situations. The human species, in the absence
of tropism and instinct, requires the ability to differentiate.
An increasing sophistication in roles and diversity of skills in human
societies came with the development of a sophisticated capacity to
differentiate experience. Within individual communities there arose the
separation of individual members according to roles and duties. This process
is essentially the same as the free market notion of specialization of labor;
the surpluses created by specialization of function permitted not only
material abundance, but the development of a higher level of culture. Culture
is always dependent on the perception of members of the human species as
differentiated individuals, rather than as reflexive components of a group. It
is the achievement of individual identity which marks the dawn of Homo
sapiens.
With the acquisition of sapiency and culture, mankind developed religion
and religion-derived systems of ethical conduct. A distinguishing feature of
every known religion and ethical system has been the construction of a
hierarchy of values. It would be a metaphysical absurdity otherwise, for a
religion or ethic without a scale of values would have no justification to
exist. Characteristic of all moral systems, at least until the advent of
existentialism and moral relativism in the twentieth century, has been a clear
differentiation between good and evil.
Until the end of the eighteenth century, the principle that man was a
sapient individual, responsible to a deity for his acts, was undisputed within
the ambit of Western Civilization. The first crack in this value system
appeared in the writings of the philosophers of the French Revolution, such as
Rousseau and Robespierre. They were affronted by the existence of different
classes and economic conditions within society, which could only be remedied
by a radical levelling of the conditions of individual men and women within
their republic of virtue. The revolutionaries' plans reveal not merely a
desire to alleviate the burden of immemorial poverty, but a positive desire to
erase any distinction between citizens for its own sake. Forcing the King to
don the tricolor rosette and be addressed as citoyen Capet could not
conceivably enrich the nation, but it was seen as a positive virtue to
eliminate the differences which distinguish one man from his neighbor.
An Exercise in Income and Status Equalization
The modern movement to erase distinctions among human beings thus began
largely as an exercise in income and status equalization among citizens within
a nation. Throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, this movement has
acquired messianic legitimation through Marxist doctrine, and has increased in
both intensity and geographic distribution to the point where laissez faire
economics is only permitted in a handful of states on the Pacific Rim. The
political collapse of the Leninist variant of Marxism does not seem likely to
significantly delegitimize the world-wide movement toward income and status
levelling; on the contrary, the creation of the "Single Europe", directed by a
socialist-bureaucratic secretariat headquartered in Brussels, is likely to
increase income redistribution in Western Europe while putting the brake on
free market entrepreneurialism further east.
During the latter half of the twentieth century, social and economic
levelling have been supplemented by a global political movement for racial
homogenization. Since the mid-1940s at the latest (coincident with the
founding of the United Nations), political elites have regarded those
phenomena which distinguish the various racial taxa in a cultural sense -
economic success, scientific achievement, and artistic tradition, among other
traits - as obstacles to be removed through exhortation, education, and the
force of law. According to the theories of anthropological relativism
popularized by Franz Boas and Margaret Meade, since all cultures are ipso
facto equal, the inequalities between groups are consequently false and
meretricious, and can only be explained by other factors, such as the
exploitation of one group by another. This twisted reasoning lies behind such
political programs as the U.N.'s New Economic Order (NEC) - global income
redistribution to favor those racial groups that are less advanced - the
Genocide convention (which defines statements that could be construed as
leading to "mental harm" to other races as genocidal acts meriting extradition
and trial), and UNESCO's programs of cultural propaganda paid for by the
taxpayers of the wealthier Western counties. Within the Western nations
themselves, the governmental apparatuses have implemented a panoply of legal
and regulative measures to eliminate distinctions between racial groups, such
as hiring and representational quotas, "antidiscrimination" laws which weaken
property rights, and various measures designed to suppress speech which might
draw attention to racial differences. Even more pervasive than the legal
measures, however, has been the more-or-less unofficial practice of social
coercion. While certain forms of speech touching on racial, ethnic, and
related distinctions are not formally proscribed, injudicious remarks will
usually result in pressure by organized groups to remove the offending
individual from his place of employment; image-conscious corporations, anxious
to avoid guilt by association, usually comply with demands of the aggrieved
minority.
By this process, the First Amendment to the Constitution, which employ to
legitimize various forms of non-verbal behavior (such as pornography and
flag-burning) as "protected speech," has ironically become a dead letter for
many traditional words and forms of speech currently ostracized by the
antidiscrimination movement. The career paths of James Watt, Jimmy "the Greek"
Snyder, Jackie Mason, and Andy Rooney are illustrative of this phenomenon.
"The Hate Crimes Statistics Act"
However, these informal persecutions are likely to gain the force of law
before the year 2000 in America. Not only is there ample legal precedent in
other Western countries, but recent legislative initiatives suggest that
organized social coercion by the antidiscrimination movement will eventually
be supplemented by a broad range of civil and criminal penalties. In February,
the U.S. Senate passed legislation emotively titled "The Hate Crimes
Statistics Act". This bill seeks to encourage the Justice Department to pass
judgment on whether certain crimes, misdemeanors, and civilly actionable
behaviors are motivated by racial, ethnic or anti-homosexual "hate." Not only
does this bill thereby involve the federal government in law enforcement
activities that were previously the domain of state and local authorities, it
also implicitly attempts to redefine common sense concepts of "crime." If
injudicious speech is motivated by "hate," is the commission of robbery and
murder by a professional criminal (which falls outside the penumbra of the
bill) considered a lesser act because it was presumably motivated by desire
for economic gain? On the other hand, is the American criminal class not
motivated, at least in part, by hatred of normal members of society? To read
the legislation, one would have to conclude otherwise.
The average middle class American might venture surprise that the
political elites would regard rude language towards a homosexual as a more
serious "crime" than murder, since the former merits urgent federal attention
and the latter does not. But that is precisely the tendency of American
political elites, whose membership is largely composed of the
antidiscrimination movement. It is noteworthy that President Bush's proposed
Omnibus Anticrime Act (which attempts to deal with the sorts of crime that
most Americans encounter) has not received a favorable review from Congress.
It is also worth noting a feature of the Hate Crimes bill which implies a
melding of government and private activist groups. A provision of the bill
exhorts the Justice Department to "coordinate" its statistics gathering
activities with such quasi-private groups as the B'nai B'rith and the NAACP.
This statute suggests therefore that agencies of a popularly elected
government are either technically incompetent or insufficiently zealous to
properly carry out the law on their own. By omission, also, the bill
insinuates that the average unaffiliated citizen's views on what constitutes
hate do not carry the same weight as those of the abovementioned groups. The
implication that a sanhedrin of private groups is required to pass judgment on
law enforcement matters suggests that within a few years the socially coercive
powers of private "antidiscrimination groups" will be fused with the executive
and judicial power of government.
The Civil Rights bill, which was killed by President Bush but which will
likely be resurrected in essentially similar form, would make civilly liable
those employers who cannot prove in court that the qualifications for
employment they have established are "essential" for the job description. In
other words, the plaintiff would not have to prove discrimination in order to
receive a judgment; while the defendant must not only prove that no
discrimination took place, but also that the stated qualifications for the job
(e.g., a university degree or tangible experience in the field) are not merely
"reasonable" but essential. Aside from the chilling implication that the shift
of the burden of proof from the plaintiff to the defendant has for the
protection of Constitutional rights, this bill marvelously illustrates the
unstated philosophy behind the antidiscrimination movement that has persisted
since Rousseau: the refusal to make reasonable distinctions, and the desire to
force others to desist from making such distinctions.
Discrimination is a Natural Process
The common denominator among all antidiscrimination movements, whether
they are concerned with skin color, income, sex, individual ability, or
dysfunctional behaviors, is that they resolutely refuse to honor traditional
common sense distinctions that have helped keep societies on an even keel.
They object to sodomy laws, for instance, on the grounds that such laws
"discriminate" against homosexuals. But that is precisely the point: the need
to protect society (and its children) against the kind of dysfunctional
behavior which spreads disease and social dissolution. Vagrancy laws
"discriminate" against vagrants. Laws to institutionalize the insane
"discriminate" against the insane, and so on. Of course, when a society no
longer discriminates against the insane by institutionalizing them, it ends up
with more vagrants.
This litany of folly is virtually endless. The death penalty
"discriminates" against those groups of people from whose ranks most murderers
are drawn. Intelligence tests "discriminate" against those with lesser
intelligence. English grammar "discriminates" against women. Western culture
"discriminates" against all that is not Western culture. A set of stairs
"discriminates" against the physically disabled. Airline safety regulations
"discriminate" against the blind. Private clubs "discriminate" because they
are not public clubs, i.e., open to everybody. This process leads to a
startling conclusion: if something is true to its original intent or
definition it is ipso facto discriminatory, because it is a set which does not
intersect with all other sets. A man is discriminatory because he is not a
woman; QED.
This paradigm, if allowed to control all aspects of society, may
eventually lead to the breakdown of society itself, because the society which
accepts this paradigm will not only be unable to defend its institutions
philosophically, but physically as well. In the 1960s and 70s, police forces
abolished height and weight requirements for police officer candidates because
these qualifications "discriminated" against women. As a result, police
departments must not only accept understrength women but puny men as well.
Unfortunately for society, such physical specimens in police uniform are not
only less able to defend themselves in a violent confrontation, their
unimposing appearance means they are less able to deter violence by their very
presence. A recent incident in Mansfield, Ohio, is a revealing case in point.
Two prisoners being arraigned were reported to have overpowered an armed woman
police officer, leading to a hostage situation.
However, the public report attempted to conceal the gravity of the
situation by distorting the truth. In fact, the two felons overpowered four
armed female officers and relieved them of their sidearms. The press, by
covering up the truth in its efforts to avoid hurting people's feelings, is
misleading the citizenry about the danger to public safety posed by misguided
social engineering.
The quality of the police forces is being further eroded by requirements
that entrance examinations be "normed" (i.e. fudged) downward so as to permit
unrestricted hiring of various racial and ethnic minorities. As older cohorts
of police officers reach retirement age, therefore, police forces across the
country will have to face the fact that their personnel will increasingly
consist of individuals who are either physically or mentally unfit by
traditional standards. One cannot overestimate the danger to public safety
that such a transformation in law enforcement will portend, but it will be
extremely difficult to counter the anti-discrimination paradigm, which
dictates levelling of standards and refusal to make common sense distinctions.
The standard that there shall be no standard is invading other fields
critical to health, safety, and national survival. Traditionally, a fireman
has required exceptional physical strength to perform the duties necessary to
protect the public. The ability to carry an unconscious man weighing upwards
of 200 pounds through a window and down a ladder is a punishing requirement -
but it is the whole point of fire fighting. Again, however, standards have
been "normed" so that physically weaker women can meet them. While the social
effects of this policy may not be felt for some time, within a generation it
is bound to dilute the effectiveness of another public service.
The most recent cause célèbre of the antidiscrimination movement has been
the effort to abolish the combat exclusion rule in the military. The movement
is challenging one of the most ancient social taboos of all, the principle
that women should not fight in wars. There are many profound socio-biological
implications to the overthrowing of this taboo, such as the social coarsening
of women (who, according to George Gilder, are the true custodians of
culture), the physical endangerment of society's childbearers, and the
breaking down, in the enemy's mind, of the distinction between combatants and
noncombatants.
Women in Combat
Leaving these issues aside for a moment, one should focus more closely on
a far simpler and more quantifiable factor: combat effectiveness. Although
proponents of women in combat consistently evade the issue, women almost
invariably fail to meet the physical standards required of combat soldiers.
According to tests conducted by the Marine Corps, for example, most women are
unable to throw a hand grenade beyond its lethal bursting radius. That would
seem to settle the argument rather conclusively, but anti-discrimination
zealots refuse to see why this would matter in practice. Proponents generally
fall back on the argument that modern war is such a "high tech" affair that
strength really does not matter (ignoring the inconsistency that it is usually
they who oppose the acquisition of expensive high tech weapon systems for the
reason that they don't work anyway). Nevertheless, veterans of the British
Army's slog to Goose Green during the Falklands Campaign or the 82nd Airborne
Division's drop into Panama would probably argue against the hypothesis that
strength and endurance don't matter in modern war.
There is also a misconception as to why certain warlike societies might
conscript women. The Israeli example is often cited as a good reason why women
should be allowed into combat, but this is entirely beside the point. Israel
conscripts women precisely in order that they can perform administrative and
supply functions which thereby free males for service in front-line units.
Israeli experience with women in combat units in 1948 was disastrous,
weakening the élan of males in the same unit and strengthening the resistance
of the enemy.
Proponents of women in combat also glide over the fraternization issue,
saying in effect that it simply won't exist among professional soldiers of
either sex. This assertion contradicts all kinds of common sense experience.
The feminists and anti-discrimination advocates, who ordinarily find everyday
life replete with sexual harassment, rape, and oppression of the female,
contend that these phenomena will magically cease to occur in the U.S.
military, even under the stress of combat and the long separation from spouses
and mates. In other words, the male is ordinarily a brute, but he will behave
like a gentleman in combat.
Before passing on to other aspects of the anti-discrimination phenomenon,
it will suffice to reflect on the prospects for national survival if the
combat exclusion rule is overturned. Like many other unfavorable social
trends, women in combat is an example of the principle of catastrophic
gradualism: perhaps the U.S. military can again prevail over a weak opponent
like Panama with its combat units composed of ten percent women. It may even
prevail under the same circumstances with twenty percent women in the front
lines. But should we ever have a fully "integrated" U.S military composed of
50 percent women facing a first class opponent, the United States will suffer
a shattering defeat.
The Erosion of Traditional Values
We have already seen how the anti-discrimination movement has begun to
erode the traditional hierarchy of religious and moral values common to
virtually all cultures, such as protection of women from combat and the public
health taboo against homosexual behavior. The antidiscrimination movement,
which is at bottom an exercise in moral relativism and epistemological refusal
to differentiate among the phenomena of the physical world, is taking aim at
other traditional values as well. One might say that the history of Twentieth
Century criminology is the story of an effort to make the criminal and the
victim change places on the moral ladder. But while this movement was in the
past confined to a relatively small number of psychologists and prison-system
bureaucrats, since the racial riots of the 1960s the effort to blur the
distinction between the criminal and the victim has become a core belief of
the antidiscrimination ideology.
The antidiscriminators were faced with the need to rationalize the
inconvenient fact that violent crimes were committed in lopsided disproportion
by members of certain of the ethnic minorities. Rather than accept the
hypothesis that increased apprehension and swift punishment would act as such
a deterrent as to bring the proportion of future ethnic offenders down, the
antidiscrimination movement theorized that (a) the criminals were not
responsible for their acts, and (b) the dominant white culture bore the blame.
Since proponents of the antidiscrimination movement are widely represented
among judges, lawyers, and parole board members, it now requires the most
extraordinary expenditures of time, taxpayer money, and effort to convict a
violent criminal and keep him incarcerated. Judicial standards have been
revised to the point where the trial is no longer a proceeding to determine
guilt or innocence, but rather an exhaustingly long, complicated, and
expensive ritual wherein a mountain of evidence may not suffice to convict a
criminal, but a scintilla of wrong procedure will serve to set the most
violent felon free. Given the almost unbelievable Constitutional protections
enjoyed by criminal suspects, the ability of judges to effectively abrogate
the decision of the jury by narrow instructions or setting aside jury
verdicts, plea bargaining, endless appeals, furloughs from prison,
work-release programs, parole, and even arbitrary court-ordered release of
inmates because of alleged prison "overcrowding", it is obvious that the
ancient and universally held principle that crime entails retribution has been
eroded to the point of extinction.
At the same time, progressive political opinion has deemed it necessary to
weaken the traditional Anglo-Saxon legal right of self-defense enjoyed by the
law-abiding citizenry. The Trojan horse employed for this effort has been the
propaganda campaign against private gun ownership, which has taken on curious
overtones of animism ("Police Officer Slain by Assault Weapon" is a typical
headline). While this partially successful campaign to restrict gun ownership
has had no effect on career criminals - indeed, the highest violent crime
rates are in jurisdictions with the most stringent gun laws, such as
Washington, D.C. - it has made many citizens uneasy about their ability to
defend their homes and families.
The prospect of a disarmed public, insufficiently protected by a mentally
and physically weakened police force (itself further shackled by the courts
and quasi-private antidiscrimination "activists") is bound to embolden
professional criminals.
Where this will lead should be evident to every sentient headline reader.
One of the greatest criminal cause célèbre of recent times was the incident
involving Bernard Goetz. The facts of the case are universally known. What is
significant, however, are the extraordinary lengths to which the New York
police went to apprehend Goetz, while one suspects the case would have been
handled routinely had he not turned the tables on his would-be assailants.
Also revealing was the extreme vindictiveness against Goetz expressed by the
Mayor, the District Attorney, official organs such as the New York Times, and
other "community leaders." Goetz was white, his assailants were black, and so
the matter was settled in the minds of those who represented the progressive
face of antidiscrimination. The little man had to be made an example, for if
the citizens at large were to follow his lead, the whole modern edifice of the
criminal justice system - its featherbedding police unions, corrupt judges,
criminal psychologists, social workers, halfway house administrators, parole
officers, the entire panoply of bureaucrats who draw material sustenance from
the perpetuation of criminality - would come crashing to the ground. In order
for the gears of modern egalitarian states to mesh smoothly, the victim must
trade places with his tormentors.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone