Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
Based on an original essay by Alain de Benoist, translated
and interpreted by Tomislav Sunic, Juniata College Alain de Benoist is a
French philosopher and the editor of the Quarterly Krisis. He is the author of
several books, including Comment peut-on etrepaien Tomislav Sunic is a
professor of political science who is currently affiliated with the Ministry
of Foreign Affairs, Croatia, and is the author of The European New Right (New
York, Peter Lang, 1990).
Vol. 34, Mankind Quarterly,
04-01-1994, pp 263.
Peaceful modern societies which respect the individual evolved from
age-old familistic ties. The transition from band-type societies, through clan
and tribal organizations, into nation-states was peaceful only when
accomplished without disruption of the basic ties which link the individual to
the larger society by a sense of a common history, culture and kinship. The
sense of "belonging" to a nation by virtue of such shared ties promotes
cooperation, altruism and respect for other members. In modern times,
traditional ties have been weakened by the rise of mass societies and rapid
global communication, factors which bring with them rapid social change and
new philosophies which deny the significance of the sense of nationhood, and
emphasize individualism and individualistic goals. The cohesion of societies
has consequently been threatened, and replaced by multicultural and
multi-ethnic societies and the overwhelming sense of lost identity in the mass
global society in which Western man, at least, has come to conceive himself as
belonging.
Sociologically, the first theorist to identify this change was the Arab
scholar, Ibn Khaldun (1332-1406), who emphasized the tendency for mass urban
societies to break down when the social solidarity characteristic of tribal
and national societies disappeared. Ibn Khaldun saw dramatically the contrast
between the morality of the nationalistic and ethnically unified Berbers of
North Africa and the motley collation of peoples who called themselves Arabs
under Arabic leadership, but did not possess the unity and sense of identity
that had made the relatively small population of true Arabs who had built a
widespread and Arabic-speaking Empire. Later it was Ferdinand Tonnies
(1855-1936) who introduced this thought to modern sociology. He did so in his
theory of gemeinschaft and gesellschaft (Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft, 1887).
This theory revealed how early tribal or national (gemeinschaft) societies
achieved harmonious collaboration and cooperation more or less automatically
due to the common culture and sense of common genetic and cultural identity in
which all members were raised. This avoided major conflicts concerning basic
values since all shared a common set of mores and a common sense of destiny.
However, as history progressed, larger multi-ethnic and multi-cultural
societies began to develop, and these Tonnies described as being united by
gesellschaft ties. These were not united by any common set of values or
historical identity, and collaboration was only maintained due to the need to
exchange goods and services. In short, their existence came to depend on
economic relations, and as a result of the diversity of cultural values, the
lack of any "family feeling," and the emphasis on economic exchange and
economic wealth, conflict over wealth and basic values was likely to disrupt
the harmony of such societies at any time. In political terms, liberalism
developed to eulogize the freedom of individuals from claims to national
loyalty and support for national destiny, while Marxism grew out of the
dissatisfaction felt by those who were less successful in achieving wealth and
power, which now came to represent the primary goals of the individuals who
were left at the mercy of the modern mass gesellschaft society. Nationalism
and any sense of loyalty to the nation as a distinct ethnic, kinship unit came
to be anathomized by both liberals and Marxists.
"A specter is haunting Europe - a specter of communism" wrote Marx in the
preface of The Manifesto. A century later this specter became a mere phantom,
with liberalism the dominant force. Over the last several decades, liberalism
used communism as a scarecrow to legitimize itself. Today, however, with the
bankruptcy of communism, this mode of "negative legitimation" is no longer
convincing. At last, liberalism, in the sense of the emphasis on the
individual above and even against that of the nation, actually endangers the
individual by undermining the stability of the society which gives him
identity, values, purpose and meaning, the social, cultural and biological
nexus to which he owes his very being.
Fundamentally, classical liberalism was a doctrine which, out of an
abstract individual, created the pivot of its survival. In its mildest form it
merely emphasized individual freedom of action, and condemned excessive
bureaucratic involvement by government. But praiseworthy though its defense of
individual freedom was, its claim that the ideal system is that in which there
is the least possible emphasis on nationhood leads to situations which in fact
endanger the freedom of the individual. In its extreme form, classical
liberalism has developed into universal libertarianism, and at this point it
comes close to advocating anarchy.
From the sociological standpoint, in its extreme form, modern
internationalist liberalism defines itself totally in terms of the
gesellschaft society of Tonnies. It denies the historical concept of the
nation state by rejecting the notion of any common interest between
individuals who traditionally shared a common heritage. In the place of
nationhood it proposes to generate a new international social pattern centered
on the individual's quest for optimal personal and economic interest. Within
the context of extreme liberalism, only the interplay of individual interests
creates a functional society - a society in which the whole is viewed only as
a chance aggregate of anonymous particles. The essence of modern liberal
thought is that order is believed to be able to consolidate itself by means of
all-out economic competition, that is, through the battle of all against all,
requiring governments to do no more than set certain essential ground rules
and provide certain services which the individual alone cannot adequately
provide. Indeed, modern liberalism has gone so far along this path that it is
today directly opposed to thee goals of classical liberalism and
libertarianism in that it denies the individual any inalienable right to
property, but still shares with modern liberalism and with libertarianism an
antagonism toward the idea of nationhood. Shorn of the protection of a society
which identifies with its members because of a shared national history and
destiny, the individual is left to grasp struggle for his own survival,
without the protective sense of community which his forebears enjoyed since
the earliest of human history.
Decadence in modern mass multi-cultural societies begins at a moment when
there is no longer any discernable meaning within society. Meaning is
destroyed by raising individualism above all other values because rampant
individualism encourages the anarchical proliferation of egotism at the
expense of the values that were once part of the national heritage, values
that give form to the concept of nationhood and the nation state, to a state
which is more than just a political entity, and which corresponds to a
particular people who are conscious of sharing a common heritage for the
survival of which they are prepared to make personal sacrifices.
Man evolved in cooperating groups united by common cultural and genetic
ties, and it is only in such a setting that the individual can feel truly
free, and truly protected. Men cannot live happily alone and without values or
any sense of identity: such a situation leads to nihilism, drug abuse,
criminality and worse. With the spread of purely egotistic goals at the
expense of the altruistic regard for family and nation, the individual begins
to talk of his rights rather than his duties, for he no longer feels any sense
of destiny, of belonging to and being a part of a greater and more enduring
entity. He no longer rejoices in the secure belief that he shares in a
heritage which it is part of his common duty to protect - he no longer feels
that he has anything in common with those around him. In short, he feels
lonely and oppressed. Since all values have become strictly personal,
everything is now equal to everything; e.g., nothing equals nothing.
"A society without strong beliefs," declared Regis Debray in his interview
with J.P. Enthoven in Le Nouvel Observateur, (October 10, 1981), " is a
society about to die." Modern liberalism is particularly critical of
nationalism. Hence, the question needs to be raised: Can modern liberal
society provide strong unifying communal beliefs in view of the fact that on
the one hand it views communal life as nonessential, while on the other, it
remains impotent to envision any belief - unless this belief is reducible to
economic conduct?
Moreover there seems to be an obvious relationship between the negation
and the eclipse of the meaning and the destruction of the historical dimension
of the social corpus. Modern liberals encourage "narcissism;" they live in the
perpetual now. In liberal society, the individual is unable to put himself in
perspective, because putting himself in perspective requires a clear and a
collectively perceived consciousness of common heritage and common adherence.
As Regis Debray remarks, "In the capacity of isolated subjects men can never
become the subjects of action and acquire the capability of making history."
(Critique de la raison politique, op. cit. p. 207). In liberal societies, the
suppression of the sense of meaning and identity embedded in national values
leads to the dissolution of social cohesion as well as to the dissolution of
group consciousness. This dissolution, in turn, culminates in the end of
history.
Being the most typical representative of the ideology of equalitarianism,
modern liberalism, in both its libertarian and socialist variants, appears to
be the main factor in this dissolution of the ideal of nationhood. When the
concept of society, from the sociological standpoint, suggests a system of
simple 'horizontal interactions,' then this notion inevitably excludes social
form. As a manifestation of solidarity, society can only be conceived in terms
of shared identity - that is, in terms of historical values and cultural
traditions (cf., Edgar Morin: "The communal myth gives society its national
cohesion.") By contrast, liberalism undoes nations and systematically destroys
their sense of history, tradition, loyalty and value. Instead of helping man
to elevate himself to the sphere of the superhuman, it divorces him from all
'grand projects' by declaring these projects 'dangerous' from the point of
view of equality. No wonder, therefore, that the management of man's
individual well-being becomes his sole preoccupation. In the attempt to free
man from all constraints, liberalism brings man under the yoke of other
constraints which now downgrade him to the lowest level. Liberalism does not defend
liberty; it destroys the independence of the individual. By eroding
historical memories, liberalism extricates man from history. It proposes to
ensure his means of existence, but robs him of his reason to live and
deprives him of the possibility of having a destiny.
There are two ways of conceiving of man and society. The fundamental value
may be placed on the individual, and when this is done the whole of mankind is
conceived as the sum total of all individuals - a vast faceless proletariat -
instead of as a rich fabric of diverse nations, cultures and races. It is this
conception that is inherent in liberal and socialist thought. The other view,
which appears to be more compatible with man's evolutionary and
socio-biological character, is when the individual is seen as enjoying a
specific biological and culture legacy - a notion which recognizes the
importance of kinship and nationhood. In the first instance, mankind, as a sum
total of individuals, appears to be "contained" in each individual human
being; that is, one becomes first a "human being," and only then, as by
accident, a member of a specific culture or a people. In the second instance,
mankind comprises a complex phylogenetic and historic network, whereby the
freedom of the individual is guaranteed by the protection of family by his
nation, which provide him with a sense of identity and with a meaningful
orientation to the entire world population. It is by virtue of their organic
adherence to the society of which they are a part that men build their
humanity.
As exponents of the first concept we encounter Descartes, the
Encyclopaedists, and the emphasis on "rights"; nationality and society emanate
from the individual, by elective choice, and are revokable at any time. As
proponents of the second concept we find J.G. Herder and G.W. Leibniz, who
stress the reality of cultures and ethnicity. Nationality and society are
rooted in biological, cultural and historical heritage. The difference between
these two concepts becomes particularly obvious when one compares how they
visualize history and the structure of the real. Nationalists are proponents
of holism. Nationalists see the individual as a kinsman, sustained by the
people and community. which nurtures and protects him, and with which he is
proud to identify. The individual's actions represent an act of participation
in the life of his people, and freedom of action is very real because, sharing
in the values of his associates, the individual will seldom seek to threaten
the basic values of the community with which he identifies. Societies which
lack this basic sense of national unity are inherently prone to suffer from
repeated situations wherein the opposing values of its egotistical members
conflict with each other.
Furthermore, proponents of nationhood contend that a society or a people
can survive only when: a) they remain aware of their cultural and historical
origins; b) when they can assemble around a mediator, be it individual, or
symbolic, who is capable of reassembling their energies and catalyzing their
will to have a destiny; c) when they can retain the courage to designate their
enemy. None of these conditions have been realized in societies that put
economic gain above all other values, and which consequently: a) dissolve
historical memories; b) extinguish the sublime and eliminate subliminal
ideals; c) assume that it is possible not to have enemies.
The results of the rapid change from national or tribal-oriented societies
to the modern, anti-national individualism prevalent in contemporary
"advanced" societies have been very well described by Cornelius Castoriadis:
"Western societies are in absolute decomposition. There is no longer a vision
of the whole that could permit them to determine and apply any political
action . . . Western societies have practically ceased to be [nation] states .
. . Simply put, they have become agglomerations of lobbies which, in a myopic
manner, tear the society apart; where nobody can propose a coherent policy,
and where everybody is capable of blocking an action deemed hostile to his own
interests." (Liberation, 16 and 21 December, 1981).
Modern liberalism has suppressed patriotic nationhood into a situation in
which politics has been reduced to a "delivery service" decisionmaking process
resembling the economic "command post," statesmen have been reduced to serving
as tools for special interest groups, and nations have become little more than
markets. The heads of modern liberal states have no options but to watch their
citizenry being somatized by civilizational ills such as violence,
delinquency, and drugs.
Ernst Junger once remarked that the act of veiled violence is more
terrible than open violence. (Journal IV, September 6, 1945). And he also
noted: "Slavery can be substantially aggravated when it assumes the appearance
of liberty." The tyranny of modern liberalism creates the illusion inherent in
its own principles. It proclaims itself for liberty and cries out to defend
"human rights" at the moment when it oppresses the most. The dictatorship of
the media and the "spiral of silence" appear to be almost as effective in
depriving the citizenry of its freedom by imprisonment. In the West, there is
no need to kill: suffice it to cut someone's microphone. To kill somebody by
silence is a very elegant kind of murder, which in practice yields the same
dividends as a real assassination - an assassination which, in addition,
leaves the assassin with good conscience. Moreover, one should not forget the
importance of such a type of assassination. Rare are those who silence their
opponents for fun.
Patriotic nationhood does not target the notion of "formal liberties, " as
some rigorous Marxists do. Rather, its purpose is to demonstrate that
"collective liberty," i.e., the liberty of peoples to be themselves and to
continue to enjoy the privilege of having a destiny, does not result from the
simple addition of individual liberties. Proponents of nationhood instead
contend that the "liberties" granted to individuals by liberal societies are
frequently nonexistent; they represent simulacra of what real liberties should
be. It does not suffice to be free to do something. Rather, what is needed is
one's ability to participate in determining the course of historical events.
Societies dominated by modern liberal traditions are "permissive" only in so
far as their general macrostability strips the populace of any real
participation in the actual decision-making process. As the sphere in which
the citizenry is permitted to "do everything" becomes larger, the sense of
nationhood becomes paralyzed and loses its direction.
Liberty cannot be reduced to the sentiment that one has about it. For that
matter, both the slave and the robot could equally well perceive themselves as
free. The meaning of liberty is inseparable from the founding anthropology of
man, an individual sharing a common history and common culture in a common
community. Decadence vaporizes peoples, frequently in the gentlest of manners.
This is the reason why individuals acting as individuals can only hope to flee
tyranny, but cooperating actively as a nation they can often defeat tyranny
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone