Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
By ALAN SOBLE
Vol. 25, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 06-01-1995, pp 192.
Alan Soble is a professor and a research professor of philosophy at the
University of New Orleans. He is the author of The Structure of Love (Yale,
1990) and Pornography. Marxism, Feminism and the Future of Sexuality (Yale,
1986), and he has edited The Philosophy of Sex (Rowman and Littlefield,
1980/1991) and Eros, Agape and Philia (Paragon House, 1989). Another book in
this area, Investigating Sex, is to be published by New York University Press.
Feminist science critics, in particular Sandra Harding, Carolyn Merchant,
and Evelyn Fox Keller, claim that misogynous sexual metaphors played an
important role in the rise of modern science. The writings of Francis Bacon
have been singled out as an especially egregious instance of the use of
misogynous metaphors in scientific philosophy. This paper offers a defense of
Bacon.
What a man had rather were true he more readily believes. Therefore he
rejects difficult things from impatience of research.
Novum Organurn, Book I, aph. 49
I. SCIENCE AND RAPE
In an article printed in the august pages of The New York Times, Sandra
Harding (1989) introduced to the paper's readers one of the more shocking
ideas to emerge from feminist science studies:
Carolyn Merchant, who wrote a book called "Death of Nature," and Evelyn
Keller's collection of papers called "Reflections on Gender & Science" talk
about the important role that sexual metaphors played in the development of
modem science. They see these notions of dominating mother nature by the good
husband scientist. If we put it in the most blatant feminist terms used today,
we'd talk about marital rape, the husband as scientist forcing nature to his
wishes.
Harding asserts elsewhere, too., that sexual metaphors played an important
role in the development of science (e.g., 1986,112,113,116; 1991, 43, 267).
But here she understates the point by referring to "marital rape," and so does
not convey it in the most blatant terms, because her own way of making the
point is usually to talk about rape and torture in the same breath, not
mentioning marriage. (I do not mean that marital rape is less vicious or more
excusable than non-marital rape. But the connotations of rape adjoined to
torture are stronger than those of marital rape.) For example, Harding (1986)
refers to "the rape and torture metaphors in the writings of Sir Francis Bacon
and others (e.g., Machiavelli) enthusiastic about the new scientific method"
(113). By associating rape metaphors with science, Harding is trying to
accomplish what metaphor itself does; she wants the unsavory connotations of
rape to spill over, with full moral condemnation, onto science:
Understanding nature as a woman indifferent to or even welcoming rape was .
. . fundamental to the interpretations of these new conceptions of nature and
inquiry. . . . There does . . . appear to be reason to be concerned about the
intellectual, moral, and political structures of modern science when we think
about how, from its very beginning, misogynous and defensive gender politics
and the abstraction we think of as scientific method have provided resources
for each other. (113, 116)
I dare not hazard a guess as to how many people read Harding's article in
the Times; how many clipped out this scandalous bit of bad publicity for
science and put it on the icebox; or how many still have some vague idea tying
science to rape. But the belief that vicious sexual metaphors were and are
important in science has gained some currency in the academy.[1] This is
unfortunate, not only for the reputations of those who engage in or extol
science, but also for our understanding of its history.
II. CONTEMPORARY SEXUAL METAPHORS
In Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? (WS?WK?), Harding (1991) proposes that
we abolish the "sexist and misogynistic metaphors" that have "infused" science
and replace them with "positive images of strong, independent women,"
metaphors based on "womanliness" and "female eroticism woman-designed for
women" (267, 301). Harding defends her proposal by claiming that "the
prevalence of such alternative metaphors" would lead to "less partial and
distorted descriptions and explanations" and would "foster the growth of
knowledge":
If they were to excite people's imaginations in the way that rape, torture,
and other misogynistic metaphors have apparently energized generations of male
science enthusiasts, there is no doubt that thought would move in new and
fruitful directions. (267)
What are the misogynistic metaphors that "energized" science? In a
footnote, Harding sends us to Chapter 2 of WS?WK? There we find a section
titled "The Sexual Meanings of Nature and Inquiry" (1991, 42-6), which
contains four examples of metaphors in the writings of two philosophers
(Francis Bacon, Paul Feyerabend), one scientist (Richard Feynman), and the
unnamed preparers of a booklet published by the National Academy of Sciences.
In the passage from Feynman's Nobel Lecture quoted by Harding, which she
interprets as an example of "thinking of mature women as good for nothing but
mothering" (1986,112), the physicist reminisces about a particular theory in
physics as if it were a woman with whom he long ago fell in love, a woman who
has become old, yet had been a good mother and left many children (1986, 120;
1991, 43-4). From the NAS booklet, Harding quotes: "The laws of nature are not
. . . waiting to be plucked like fruit from a tree. They are hidden and
unyielding, and the difficulties of grasping them add greatly to the
satisfaction of success" (1991, 44). Here, says Harding, one can hear
"restrained but clear echoes" of sexuality. Perhaps the metaphors used by
Feynman and the NAS are sexual, but they are hardly misogynistic or vicious,
anti I wonder why Harding thinks they deserve to be put on display. In fact,
Harding only claims that in Bacon, of her four examples, is there a rape
metaphor. But let us examine her' treatment of Feyerabend first, for there are
significant connections between them.
Harding quotes the closing lines of a critique of Kuhn and Lakatos by
Feyerabend, who closes his long technical paper with the joke that his view
"changes science from a stem and demanding mistress into an attractive and
yielding courtesan who tries to anticipate every wish of her lover. Of course,
it is up to us to choose either a dragon or a pussy cat for our company. I do
not think I need to explain my own preferences" (1970, 229).[2] In WS?WK?,
Harding exhibits, but barely comments on, this passage. Her gripe cannot be
that Feyerabend (or Feynman, or the NAS) employed a sexual metaphor, for we
know that In WS ?WK?, Harding condones "alternative" sexual images reflecting
"female eroticism woman-designed for women." Feyerabend's metaphor- -science
is a selfish shrew who exploits us or she is a prostitute who waits on us hand
and foot--must therefore be the wrong kind of sexual metaphor, even if not of
rape. Harding quotes the same passage in her earlier The Science Question in
Feminism (SQIF), givIng it as an example of how gender is attributed to
scientific inquiry (120). In her view, the passage conveys, as does Feynman's,
a cultural image of "manliness." Feynman depicts "the good husband and
father," while Feyerabend's idea of manliness, says HardIng, is "the sexually
competitive, locker-room jock" (1986, 120). Thus science, in Feyerabend's
metaphor, is an accommodating, sexually passive woman, and the scientist and
the philosopher of science are the jocks she sexually pleases. I do not see
how portraying science as a courtesan implies that the men who visit her,
scientists and philosophers, are locker-room jocks. The fancy word
"courtesan," if it implies anything at all, vaguely alludes to a debonair and
educated Hugh Hefner puffing on his pipe, not: to a Terry Bradshaw swatting
bare male butt 'with a wet towel. [3]
Harding concludes her discussion of Feyerabend by claiming that his
metaphor, coming as it does strategically at the end of his paper, serves a
pernicious purpose. He depicts "science and its theories" as "exploitable
women," and the scientist as a masculine, manly man, in order to tell his
(male) audience that his philosophical "proposal should be appreciated because
it replicates gender politics" of the sort they find congenial (1986, 121). In
WS?WK?, Harding similarly asserts that this metaphor is the way Feyerabend
"recommended" his view (1991, 43). I agree that a woman reading Feyerabend's
paper would probably not empathize with the metaphor, even if she fully
concurred with the critique of Kuhn that precedes it; but she could, if she
wished, ignore it as irrelevant to Feyerabend's arguments. (Had Bacon employed
rape metaphors, Harding [1986] would be right that "it is . . . difficult to
imagine women as an enthusiastic audience" [116]. Still, had there been any
women in Bacon's audience, they could have disregarded his metaphors and
accepted, or rejected, the rest on its own merits.) Further, asserting that
the men in Feyerabend's audience would be, in part, persuaded by this appeal
and that Feyerabend thought that he could seduce them with his "conscientious
effort . . . at gender symbolism" (Harding, 1986, 120) is insulting to men.
Some men readers undoubtedly prefer strict to submissive women. Would
Feyerabend' s contrary preference for kittens tend to undermine for them his
critique of Kuhn because it does not match their own taste?
III. HARDING ON BACON
According to Harding (1991), vicious sexual metaphors were infused into
modern science at its very beginning, were instrumental in its ascent, and
eventually became "a substantive part of science" (44). She thinks Francis
Bacon (1561-1,626) was crucial in this process. 4 What Harding (1986) says
about Feyerabend, that he hoped his view would "be appreciated because it
replicates gender politics" (121), is what Harding (1991) claims about Bacon,
although in more extreme terms: "Francis Bacon appealed to rape metaphors to
persuade his audience that experimental method is a good thing" (43).
This is a damning criticism. Bacon is not depicted as a negligible
Feyerabend making silly jokes about science the old whore. Harding is claiming
that Bacon drew an analogy between the experimental method and rape, and tried
to gain advantage from it (see also 1986, 116), as Merchant had claimed before
her that Bacon drew an analogy between the experimental method and torture
(1980, 168, 172). Conjure up the image: Bacon wants to convince fellow
scholars to study nature systematically, by using experimental methods that
elicit changes in nature, rather than study nature by accumulating specimens
and observing phenomena passively. In order to champion experimentalism, Bacon
says to them: think of it as rape; think of it as forcing apart with your
knees the slender thighs of an unwilling woman, pinning her under the weight
of your body as she kicks and screams in your ears, grabbing her poor little
jaw roughly with your fist to shut her mouth, and trying to thrust your penis
into her dry vagina; that is what the experimental method is all about.
What did Bacon write to provoke Harding into this accusation? Here is the
whole text she offers as evidence for her reading:
For you have but to hound nature in her wanderings, and you will be able
when you like to lead and drive her afterwards to the same place again.
Neither ought a man to make scruple of entering and penetrating into those
holes and corners when the inquisition of truth is his whole object. (1991,
43)[5]
I suppose that a man who made no scruple of penetrating holes (and
corners?) might be a rapist, but he also might be a proctologist or billiard
player. And to "hound" nature could be seen as raping her, but the spirited
student who storms my office and too often sits down next to me in the
cafeteria, hoping for some words of wisdom- -no more than that--is hounding
me. Why could that not be Bacon's point, that a student of nature must be
willing to sit for prolonged periods on the floor in the hall, outside her
office, waiting for her reluctant nod? It is unlikely, then, that the rape
metaphor Harding perceives here is located entirely in "hound," unless she has
in mind Robin Morgan's definition of rape (1977):
Rape exists any tittle sexual intercourse occurs when it has not been
initiated by the woman, out of her own genuine affection and desire. . . . How
many millions of times have women had sex "willingly" with men they didn't
want to have sex with? . . . How many times have women wished just to sleep
instead or read or watch the Late Show? . . . most of the decently married
bedrooms across America are settings for nightly rape. (165-66; Harding's
italics)
In Morgan's view, a man who pesters his wife for sex, when she prefers to
watch TV, has committed rape if she caves in under his pressure. But Bacon's
audience would never have recognized this prosaic sexual phenomenon as rape.
Nor would most of us today--reasonable men and women alike--judge it to be
rape. We could do so, of course, but that would require many other changes in
our moral and legal concepts, probably more than a good Quinean could endure,
and would make trivial the accusation that Bacon traded in rape metaphors.
Looking at Keller might help us discern a rationale behind Harding' s
reading of Bacon's De Augmentis. In her essay "Baconian Science, " Keller
(1985) quotes the first of the two sentences quoted by Harding, in order to
illustrate her own claim that, even though, for Bacon, "Nature may be coy,"
she can still "be conquered":
For you have but to follow and as it were hound nature in her wanderings,
and you will be able, when you like, to lead and drive her afterwards to the
same place again. (36)
What "leads to [this] conquest," in Keller's view, is "not simple
violation, or rape, but forceful and aggressive seduction" (37). Now, the fact
that Keller interprets this passage from De Augmentis as a rape-free zone does
not mean there is no rape image there. So Harding, when reading Keller, might
have concluded--with a slight push from Keller (1985), for whom "the
distinction between rape and conquest sometimes seems too subtle" (37)--that
Keller had been too cautious, that the "conquest" of nature Keller found in
"hound" and "drive" together is more accurately described as rape. Harding's
rape-interpretation of Bacon, taken as deriving from Keller, will then depend
on (1) Keller' s being right in finding even the conquest of nature in "hound"
and "drive," a conquest that must be sexual,[6] and (2) eradicating the
difference--also for Bacon, since his mens rea is at stake--between rape and
seduction. Bacon, of course, recognizes this difference, and advises that
science would be more successful by patiently wooing nature than by raping
her:
Art . . . when it endeavours by much vexing of bodies to force Nature to
its will and conquer and subdue her . . . rarely attains the particular end it
aims at. . . . men being too intent upon their end . . . struggle with Nature
than woo her embraces with due observation and attention. ("Erichthonius,"
Myth 20, Wisdom of the Ancients; Robertson, 843)
There is reason to think, then, that Keller is right not to perceive rape
in Bacon, although the seduction, here at least, seems considerate and
delicate, not "forceful and aggressive."[7]
Something else can be gleaned from Keller. Compare the one sentence Keller
takes from Bacon's De Augmentis with the first sentence that Harding
attributes to Bacon. The sentence as quoted by Keller correctly includes the
words "follow and as it were" (Works IV, 296), which are missing from Harding.
I think there is some difference between Bacon's nuanced "follow and as it
were hound" nature and the crude "hound" her. which dilution makes a rape
metaphor more difficult to discern. I do not want to make much of this error,
despite the fact that students of Harding who read only WS?WK? will be
misguided, because five years earlier, in SQIF, Harding quotes this De
Augmentis passage twice, almost correctly.[8] Here is one instance:
To say "nature is rapable"--or, in Bacon's words: "For you have but to
follow and as it were hound nature in her wanderings, and you will be able
when you like to lead and drive her afterward to the same place again. . . .
Neither ought a man to make scruple of entering and penetrating into those
holes and corners when the inquisition of truth is his whole object"--is to
recommend that similar benefits can be gained from nature if it is
conceptualized and treated like a woman resisting sexual advances. (1986, 237;
ellipsis and italics are Harding's)
Harding seems not to see "follow and as it were" as a sturdy qualification.
But "penetration" need not be taken as having "strong sexual implications"
(contra Merchant 1980, 168); and even if "penetration" is sexual (was it for
Bacon?), it does not per se entail rape. Perhaps Harding construes the
unscrupulous (= immoral) penetration of holes to be an allusion to rape.[9]
But this reading makes sense only by wrenching "scruple" out of context.
Bacon's point, which he repeats elsewhere, is that any scientist determined to
find the truth about nature should be prepared to get his hands dirty; when
truth is the goal, everything must be investigated, even if, to prissy minds,
the methods employed and the objects studied are foul. (Think about Freud or
Kinsey justifying the study of sex.) Thus a few lines after "scruple" in De
Augmentis, Bacon bemoans that "it is esteemed a kind of dishonour . . . for
learned men to descend to inquiry or meditation upon matters mechanical"
(Works IV, 296; see also Advancement, Works III, 332). Parts of De Augmentis
(whose title begins De Dignitate) and Novum Organum are intended to establish
the dignity, despite dirty hands, of engaging in science to improve the human
condition (see also Parasceve, Works IV, 257-9). Novum Organum is especially
clear on this. In one aphorism, Bacon condemns "an opinion . . . vain and
hurtful; namely, that the dignity of the human mind is impaired by long and
close intercourse with experiments" (Works IV; Book I, aph. 83;[20] see also
Cogitata et Visa, in Farrington 1964, 82). Bacon returns to this theme later
in Novum Organum:
And for things that are mean or even filthy, . . . such things, no less
than the most splendid and costly, must be admitted into natural history Nor
is natural history polluted thereby; for the sun enters the sewer no less than
the palace, yet takes no pollution. . . . For whatever deserves to exist
deserves also to be known, for knowledge is the image of existence; and things
mean and splendid exist alike. Moreover as from certain putrid
substances--musk, for instance, and civet--the sweetest odours are sometimes
generated, so too from mean and sordid instances there sometimes emanates
excellent light and information. But enough and more than enough of this; such
fastidiousness being merely childish and effeminate. (120; see also 121)
Bacon is, like Calvin, a rascal. He would much rather dissect bugs and
chase snakes than play house or have an afternoon tea with Susie.
Bacon's two sentences from De Augmentis make yet another appearance in
Harding's SQIF:
Bacon uses bold sexual imagery to explain key features of the experimental
method as the inquisition of nature: "For you have but to follow and as it
were hound nature in her wanderings, and you will be able when you like to
lead and drive her afterward to the same place again. . . . Neither ought a
man to make scruple of entering and penetrating into those holes and comers,
when the inquisition of truth is his whole object. . . . " . . . this is
Bacon's way of explaining the necessity of aggressive and controlled
experiments in order to make the results of research replicable! (1986, 116;
first ellipsis is Harding's)
But it is not obviously true that Bacon, with the phrase "to the same
place," is referring to replicability. Nor is Keller's idea obviously correct,
that Bacon here asserts that nature can be "conquered." William Leiss (1972)
suggests, in The Domination of Nature, an alternative reading: "having
discovered the course leading to the end result, we are able to duplicate the
process at will" (59). This reading makes sense, because, in the immediately
preceding sentence, Bacon had written: "from the wonders of nature is the most
clear and open passage to the wonders of art," and then by way of explaining
or defending this idea, that nature teaches us how to fabricate artificial
devices, Bacon now writes "For you have but to follow." To learn how to
achieve one of nature's effects (to use my own anachronistic example, the
overcoming [conquering] of bacterial infection), we must study how nature
accomplishes it (we follow nature by pestering her in the lab); once we
discover Nature's Way (the various mechanisms of the immune system) we can
then copy, modify, and rearrange its main ingredients (develop "artificial"
devices, vaccinations, that elicit antibodies) to "lead" nature "to the same
place again." Bacon is modifying a point appearing elsewhere in his writings
(e.g., A Description of the Intellectual Globe, Works V, 507) and that he has
made just a page before in De Augmentis:
The artificial does not differ from the natural in form or essence, but
only in the efficient. . . . Nor matters it, provided things are put in the
way to produce an effect, whether it be done by human means or otherwise. Gold
is sometimes refined in the fire and sometimes found pure in the sands, nature
having done the work for herself. So also the rainbow is made in the sky out
of a dripping cloud; it is also made here below with a jet of water. Still
therefore it is nature which governs everything. (Works IV, 294-95)
In the Cogitata et Visa (in Farrington 1964), Bacon goes so far as to say
that phenomena found in nature (he praises silk spun by a worm), and from
which we can learn, "are such as to elude and mock the imagination and thought
of men" (96). Bacon's example in De Augmentis of obtaining a rainbow from a
spray of water is serene, even lovely, and makes it improbable that he viewed
experimental manipulations as nothing but mere acts of aggression.
Furthermore, Bacon's affirmation that nature "governs everything"--the ways of
nature are responsible even for the artificial rainbow we make with a spray of
water--is reason to doubt that he conceives of the relationship between
science and nature principally as that between man the master and dominated
woman. At the very beginning and at the very end of the first book of Novum
Organum, as well as in "The Plan" of The Great Instauration (Works IV,
32)--that is, often and in prominent places--Bacon writes that science is "the
servant and interpreter of Nature" (Novum Organum, 1) and "Nature to be
commanded must be obeyed" (3; see also 129).
Harding (1986) introduces the De Augmentis passage by saying that it
contains "bold sexual imagery,"[11] but after the quote she escalates the
charge: experimentalism, the "testing of hypotheses," is "here formulated by
the father of scientific method in dearly sexist metaphors" (116). Harding
straightaway takes the next step: "Both nature and inquiry appear
conceptualized in ways modeled on rape and torture- -on men's most violent and
misogynous relationships to women--and this modeling is advanced as a reason
to value science" (116). Of course, if the passage contains no rape metaphor,
Harding's thesis (see also 1986, 237; 1991, 43) that Bacon employs a rape
metaphor to recommend experimentalism falls apart. But even if the passage
contains a rape metaphor, why think that Bacon uses it to promote
experimentalism? Examine the two sentences Harding quotes from the 1623 De
Augmentis, as they appeared in the 1605 English predecessor of this text:, The
Advancement of Learning:
For it is no more but by following and as it were hounding Nature in her
wanderings, to be able to lead her afterwards to the same place again. . . .
Neither ought a man to make scruple of entering into these things for
inquisition of truth. (Works III, 331)
The three purported offenders., "drive," "penetrate," and "holes," are
missing. Which of these texts is more momentous for Bacon's program? In
Advancement, written soon after the accession of James I, Bacon was surely
trying to win over his king; when writing De Augmentis, the older Bacon had
already been stripped of his official positions and was writing for posterity.
In which situation should we expect Bacon to use harsh (or soft) language to
do the persuading? This is treacherous terrain; at least, the contrast between
the Advancement and De Augmentis should give us pause.
Furthermore, in Novum Organum (and elsewhere), Bacon argues on behalf of
science in terms more likely to convince his audience: it will improve the
human condition (81, 129; see De Augmentis, Works IV, 297), and so the works
of science are works of love (Valerius Terminus, Works III, 221-2; "Preface"
to The Great Instauration, Works IV, 21; see Farrington 1964, 28-9). At the
end of the first book of Novum Organum (129), Bacon reminds his audience that
science fulfills the Biblical command (Gen. 1:26) for humans to rule the
universe (see Leiss 1972, 53). These themes in Bacon are typical and
familiar.[12] Why conjecture that Bacon also appeals to a rape metaphor, as if
that were the icing on the cake of his vindication of science? Perhaps Harding
assumes that, from the fact that the text contains a rape metaphor, it follows
that the metaphor must have been used to convince the audience to embrace his
philosophy. It would be a mistake to conclude, however, solely from the
presence of a rape metaphor, that it is intended to have a specific
perlocutionary force. This mistake is similar to one made about erotica,
namely, arguing solely from the presence in a text of a photographic: or
linguistic depiction of a certain sexual act that the text recommends or
endorses the depicted act.[13]
My mentioning erotica hem is not inappropriate. Harding (1986) titles the
section of SQIF in which she first quotes Bacon "Should the History and
Philosophy of Science Be X-Rated?" "This question is only slightly antic,"
because (previewing her comments on Bacon and Feyerabend) "we will see
assumptions that . . . the best scientific activity and philosophical thinking
about science are to be modeled on men's most misogynous relationships to
women" (112). That is, Harding thinks that science, its history and philosophy
should be rated "x"; it contains, in her view, explicit and nasty sex. But I
cannot perceive, as she does, the sexually aggressive locker-room jock in
Feyerabend's metaphor, nor can I perceive, as she does, the rape metaphor in
Bacon. So perhaps it is Harding's story itself that should be rated "x": she
injects sex where there is none to begin with. Consider the NAS metaphor: the
laws of nature are "not waiting to be plucked like fruit from a tree [but] are
hidden and unyielding." Harding finds here a "clear echo" of sexuality (1991,
44). But these few words can be read, without effort, as innocent and
nonsexual; so it is Harding, like the person who feels squeamish at the sight
of uncovered piano legs, who has infused the sex into them. Further, if
Harding's own psychology is uncommonly sensitive to the nuances of language
and so enables her to extract a rape metaphor out of "hound" and "holes," or
if the metaphor is one that mostly or only women could sense, that would
undermine Harding's claim that Bacon used a rape metaphor to persuade his
audience. [14]
One more example: Bacon's portrayal of inquiry as a "disclosing of the
secrets of nature" (Works IV, 296; see Novum Organum, 18, 89). We could
construe the language of discovering, or uncovering, the hidden secrets of
nature as alluding to a quest for carnal knowledge of a deeply concealed
female sexuality that is not keen on being exposed (for whatever reason, be it
prudish modesty, girlish self-doubt, lazy reluctance). We might interpret such
language this way in order to suggest that this is the deeper, hidden meaning
of the philosophical claim that underneath the appearances of things and
events are unobservable structures and forces about which we can have no
direct knowledge and about which we will remain ignorant unless we diligently
investigate, experimentally, their phenomenal manifestations. But the sexual
metaphor, if we insist on digging it out, is tame; there is no rape and no
need to compel or twist the metaphor, against its will, to be rape.
IV. MERCHANT ON BACON
According to Harding, rape is Bacon's metaphor for the experimental method;
for the historian Carolyn Merchant (1980), "the interrogation of witches" by
torture is Bacon's "symbol for the interrogation of nature" (172):
Much of the imagery he used in delineating his new scientific objectives
and methods . . . treats nature as a female to be tortured through mechanical
interventions [and] . . . strongly suggests the interrogations of the witch
trials and the mechanical devices used to torture witches. In a relevant
passage, Bacon stated that the method by which nature' s secrets might be
discovered consisted in investigating the secrets of witchcraft by
inquisition, referring to the example of James I. (168)
In which "relevant" passage does Bacon "state" such a thing? Merchant calls
on De Augmentis (Works IV, 296) to substantiate her assertion:
For you have but to follow and as it were hound nature in her wanderings,
and you will be able when you like to lead and drive her afterward to the same
place again. Neither am I of opinion in this history of marvels, that
superstitious narratives of sorceries, witchcrafts, charms, dreams,
divinations, and the like, where there is an assurance and clear evidence of
the fact, should be altogether excluded. . . . howsoever the use and practice
of such arts is to be condemned, yet from the speculation and consideration of
them . . . a useful light may be gained, not only for a true judgment of the
offenses of persons charged with such practices, but likewise for the further
disclosing of the secrets of nature. Neither ought a man to make scruple of
entering and penetrating into these holes and corners, when the inquisition of
truth is his whole object--as your Majesty has shown in your own example.
(1980, 168; ellipses and italics are Merchant' s)[15]
I do not perceive the torture metaphor. The two sentences Merchant
italicizes (the two in which Harding finds rape) do not, if my arguments in
section III are sound, bear that interpretation; nor do the sentences that
fall between.
Nowhere does Bacon state what Merchant says he states. In referring to
James I in this passage, Bacon is not, contra Merchant, alluding to his
methods of inquisition, but rather pointing out that James is willing to get
his hands dirty (by studying witchcraft). What James "show[ed] in [his] own
example,'" says Bacon, is that everything in nature is an appropriate object
for scientific study (one of Bacon' s principles, recall), not that science
should torture nature as if a witch. The text provides no reason to think that
"Bacon's recommendation that experimental method should characterize the new
science was couched in terms of the method James I had successfully used to
'expose' witches" (Nelson 1990,353, n. 137). Further, note that by 1622, when
De Augmentis was being written, James had already changed his mind about
witches and had intervened to save some of the accused from execution.[16]
Thus Bacon could not have been appealing here to a beloved pastime of James in
devising a metaphor for experimentalism. Bacon might have had better luck
appealing to a torture-the-witch metaphor in the 1605 Advancement, right after
James's Statute of 1604; but, as I have pointed out, the language of that
version of De Augmentis is not very provocative.
If we reinsert into this passage from De Augmentis the words Merchant
deletes (indicated by italics), we can more clearly appreciate Bacon' s point:
Neither am I of opinion in this history of marvels, that superstitious
narratives of sorceries, witchcrafts, charms, dreams, divinations, and the
like, where there is an assurance and clear evidence of the fact, should be
altogether excluded. For it is not yet known in what cases, and how far,
effects attributed to superstition participate of natural causes; and
therefore howsoever the use and practice of such arts is to be condemned, yet
from the speculation and consideration of them (if they be diligently
unravelled) a useful light ,nay be gained, not only for a true judgment of the
offenses of persons charged with such practices, but likewise for the further
disclosing of the secrets of nature.
Bacon is not recommending that witches or nature be tortured; instead, he
is telling his audience to pay attention to the distinction between the
context of discovery and the context of justification: regardless of the
source or origin of certain claims ("narratives"), their content might very
well be true, and this can be known only by investigating them scientifically
This is what Harding (1991) calls the "desirable legacy" of modem philosophy
of science, the notion that "we should be able to decide the validity of a
knowledge claim apart from who speaks it" (269).
This passage from De Augmentis is the first and longest quoted by Merchant
in making her case; it is her best shot, and it misses the mark. There are, of
course, other passages, mostly scattered words and partial sentences, that
Merchant quotes in rounding out her argument. I cannot deal with them all. But
there is a frequent reference to Proteus in Bacon's works that deserves
discussion. Introducing one of them, Merchant (1980) claims that Bacon draws
an analogy between the "inquisition" of nature and "the torture chamber"
(169). Here are his words:
For like as a man's disposition is never well known or proved till he be
crossed, nor Proteus ever changed shapes till he was straitened and held fast;
so nature exhibits herself more clearly under the trials and vexations of art
than when left to herself. (De Augmentis, Works IV, 298, Merchant's italics;
see also Advancement, Works III, 333)
I agree that force is here applied to Proteus, in particular. But if we
take seriously Bacon's analogy between nature and Proteus, the implication is
that we must be smart enough to outfox and comer nature in order to get a
hearing for our questions. Then, as we are trying to hold fast to nature,
nature will almost always escape, by changing unpredictably and
uncontrollably, slithering or leaping away or disappearing as a gas, and we
will not get an answer. Thus our attempts to bind her will be largely
fruitless. The Proteus image, then, is a tribute to the sagacity and subtlety
of nature (see Novum Organum, 10, 24). Now, if we do not take the analogy
literally, we can be content with the core of Bacon's idea, which has nothing
to do with torture: a person left alone might never expose the greed (or love)
that lies deeply buried in her heart, but if she is tempted by a stuffed
wallet on the ground (or moved by the televised sight of the faces of starving
children), she might respond, revealing those secret parts of her character.
Merchant (1980) quotes another Proteus passage (171); perhaps it will be
thought that this one more strongly supports her reading:
The vexations of art are certainly as the bonds and handcuffs of Proteus,
which betray the ultimate struggles and efforts of matter. (Parasceve, Works
IV, 257)
"Bonds and handcuffs" look damning when equated with "vexations of art"
(i.e., experimental techniques). But we know that these devices are being
applied to Proteus, the supreme Houdini, in which case we need not be so
anxious about his safety. What does Bacon mean by the less than transparent
"betray the ultimate struggles and efforts of matter"? In the very next
sentence (not quoted by Merchant), Bacon explains: "For bodies will not be
destroyed or annihilated; rather than that they will turn themselves into
various forms." Here Proteus stands for matter; so, no matter how much we bind
matter, says Bacon, it is indestructible. Bacon is not issuing a normative
claim, as if urging us to bind matter to prevent it from behaving perversely
(Merchant's reading, 171; see also Bordo 1987, 109); he is making the
ontological point that no amount of binding will allow us to annihilate
matter. Bacon states the idea quite nicely in Wisdom of the Ancients:
if any skilful Servant of Nature shall bring force to bear on matter, and
shall vex it and drive it to extremities as if with the purpose of reducing it
to nothing, then will matter (since annihilation or true destruction is not
possible except by the omnipotence of God) finding itself in these straits,
turn and transform itself into strange shapes, passing from one change to
another till it has gone through the whole circle. ("Proteus," Myth 13;
Robertson, 838)
--just as Proteus in the Odyssey (Book Iv), at the hands of Menelaus and
his crew, goes through the whole cycle and is never destroyed. Note that Bacon
speaks here again of the scientist as "servant of nature." Also note that, in
his mind, there is some distinction between nature and matter--so that to
"vex" matter is not necessarily to vex nature.[17]
Let us, then, look at another feature of some of these passages -- Bacon's
frequent use of "vex" anti its congeners. Merchant (above) italicizes
vexations in De Augmentis, and both Leiss (1972, 59, 138) and Keller (1985,
36) highlight vex as conveying sexual aggression. Even though Bacon's use of
vex is occasionally strong (e.g., in relation to imperishable matter, in
Thoughts on the Nature of Things, Works V, 427-8), I am not convinced that vex
in Bacon always or usually carries a noxious connotation; I tend to think of
vex along the lines of Bacon's "hound" and my "pester." For example, in Novum
Organum Bacon writes:
For even as in the business of life a man's disposition and the secret
workings of his mind and affections are better discovered when he is in
trouble than at other times; so likewise the secrets of nature reveal
themselves more readily under the vexations of art than when they go their own
way. (98; see also a variant of these lines in " The Plan" of The Great
Instauration, Works IV, 29, which is the vex passage Keller calls attention
to)
This mature and polished statement of his philosophy contains no rape, no
torture, no bondage, just the thought that, to know nature, it is not enough
to watch her; she must be provoked into showing us her inner workings. I find
nothing to complain about in this thought, especially when I consider how much
of my knowledge of human nature I never would have acquired had not my family
friends, and colleagues, let alone myself, been crossed and thereby goaded
into exposing features of our personalities we do not ordinarily broadcast.
V. KELLER ON BACON
In order to make the case that Bacon deliberately used rape or torture
metaphors to persuade his audience of the virtues of experimental science, the
metaphors (1) should clearly be in his texts, (2) should be located in vital
places, (3a) should appear in several passages yet (3b) not indiscriminately,
and (4) should not have their thrust diluted by other contrasting images. If
Feyerabend had likened not only science but also such disparate things as
television, poetry. and champagne to a kitten, or if at one point he called
science a kitten but elsewhere a stem mistress, we would not be inclined to
take his metaphors seriously Similarly, to the extent that Bacon applied his
images to a wide assortment of items, or used diverse, even contradictory,
metaphors, it would be implausible to claim that he appealed to them to do the
important job of vindicating his science.
Evelyn Fox Keller's work on Bacon is, for this reason, important. Her key
idea is that Bacon's sexual imagery involves a more "complex sexual dialectic"
than usually recognized (1980, 302; 1985, 35); in Bacon's language, the
scientist both aggressively dominates and is "subservient" and "responsive" to
nature (1985, 36-7). Thus her title, "Baconian Science: The Arts of Mastery
and Obedience" (1985, 33): science is both master of and obedient to nature.
Keller's essay is, in effect, a reply to Leiss (1972), who says about Bacon's
"famous formula"--we command nature by obeying her--that "some commentators
have claimed that it sounds a note of humility in man's attitude toward
nature. But this interpretation . . . invents inconsistencies which do not
really exist in Bacon's work" (58-9). I think Keller is right to find
inconsistency in Bacon's metaphors, but wrong in what she makes of it.
In arguing for one side of the inconsistency, that Baconian science is
"aggressive" in its "conquest" of nature, Keller (1985) assembles together
seven passages (36). The first is from Bacon's Refutation of Philosophies:
"Let us establish a chaste and lawful marriage between Mind and Nature."[18]
The metaphor looks benign, as does that of a "chaste, holy and legal wedlock"
(the second passage, from The Masculine Birth of Time, in Farrington 1964,
72), but Keller thinks of marital imagery in Bacon as aggressive (1985, 19).
There is no need to. Bacon uses marriage imagery promiscuously in his
writings, with no hint of aggression; see "Preface" to The Great Instauration,
in which Bacon speaks about the "true and lawful marriage" he is attempting to
effect "between the empirical and the rational faculty" (Works IV, 19), and
Novum Organum, in which Bacon criticizes those who would "deduce" Christianity
from the principles of philosophy, thereby "pompously solemnising this union
of sense and faith as a lawful marriage" (89). In the marriage passages quoted
by Keller, there is no intimation of aggression at all; Bacon immediately
proceeds to say (typical for him; e.g., "The Plan" of The Great Instauration,
Works IV, 27) that the marriage will issue in "wholesome and useful inventions
. . . to bring relief" from "human necessities" (Refutation, in Farrington
1964, 131) and "will overcome the immeasurable . . . poverty of the human
race" (Masculine Birth, in Farrington 1964, 72). Still, for Keller, the
marital image in Bacon "constitutes an invitation to the 'domination of
nature' "(1978, 429, n. 5; 1985, 91, n. 6) because it "sets the scientific
project squarely in the midst of our unmistakably patriarchal tradition"
(1978, 423) in which the wife is under the thumb of the husband. Hence when
Bacon writes in Masculine Birth (the third passage), "I am come in very truth
leading to you Nature with all her children to bind her to your service and
make her your slave" (1985, 36; see also 48; in Farrington 1966, 62), Keller
sees a wedding announcement in which nature is fingered as the bride; she is a
slave, since that will be her married lot. The image here of binding nature as
a slave is an ugly one,[19] but it has nothing to do with marriage.
Keller cites four additional passages in her account of the aggression
toward nature in Bacon's images. In one, from the "Preface" to Novum Organum,
Bacon writes of trying to "penetrate further" and "find a way at length into
her inner chambers" (Works IV, 42), which is hardly pushy. Keller then turns
to the De Augmentis "hound . . . and drive" passage I have already examined,
which (contra Keller) contains no conquest, sexual or otherwise. Keller also
refers to Bacon's theme (also discussed above) that more can be learned about
nature by vexing her than by observing her in freedom.
The remaining lines cited. by Keller are from Cogitata et Visa (1607;
published 1653; Farrington 1964, 57). Bacon says, about (according to Keller
[1985]) "the discipline of scientific knowledge, and the mechanical inventions
it leads to" (36), that they do not "merely exert a gentle guidance over
nature's course; they have the power to conquer and subdue her, to shake her
to her foundations."[20] Apparently, this is crude aggression. But our
judgment of Bacon will be improved by realizing three things. First, Bacon is
in part referring here not to mechanical devices in general, but to "Printing,
Gunpowder, and the Nautical Needle," which he thinks had more effect on "human
affairs" than any "empire," "school," or "star" (in Farrington 1964, 93).
Bacon expresses his point hyperbolically--that these exemplary inventions are
the kind of thing that can conquer and shake nature to her foundations--but
given his point, the sentence is a prime candidate for being read generously.
Second, Cogitata et Visa is a polished work, even though unpublished during
Bacon's life, and, except for this one line., tranquil throughout. Much of the
Cogitata went right into Novum Organum; it contains one questionable sentence
that was not destined to join its sisters there and upon which Keller pounces.
Third, in the later 1612 Description of the Intellectual Globe (Works V, 506),
Bacon repeats this line but softens it: he warns us against making the "subtle
error," one that causes "despair," of thinking that science has "no power to
make radical changes, and shake her in the foundations." Both conquer and
subdue are gone. In an analogous passage in the late De Augmentis (1623),
Bacon altogether redeems himself linguistically by advising against the
"subtle error" of thinking, with "premature despair,." that science has "by no
means [the power] to change, transmute, or fundamentally alter nature" (Works
IV, 294). Now the rest, shaking the foundations, is gone. (Still, how can one
hope for a science that will alter nature "fundamentally," when nature
"governs everything"?)
Guided into Bacon by Harding, Merchant, and Keller, one expects to find his
work cluttered with scandalous metaphors. But Keller unveils only one clearly
ugly line out of thousands of pages of Bacon's life work, and this, "make her
your slave," occurs in a tiny fragment of a manuscript written at the dawn of
his philosophical career and never meant for publication (the 1603 Masculine
Birth, first published posthumously in 1653; Farrington 1964, 57). Further,
"shake her to her foundations" (Cogitata) is either expunged from, or revised
in, Bacon's later writings. In "Feminism and Science," a paper widely
reprinted,[21] Keller (1982) bizarrely reproduces these two lines, and only
these two, in order to discredit the new science (598).[22] To poke through
these essays and parade their meanest two lines as the truth about Bacon and
the new science is uncharitable and hostile.
In arguing, on behalf of the other side of the inconsistency, that Bacon's
images sometimes express a different attitude, Keller mentions the well-known
passages I cited above in which Bacon speaks about the scientist as the
servant of nature and as obeying her. So Keller (1985) finds a "puzzle" in
which the "ambiguities" of Bacon's images "become contradictions." Science is
"aggressive yet responsive, powerful yet benign, masterful yet subservient,
shrewd yet innocent" (37). Keller solves the problem by sensing, in Masculine
Birth, that Bacon views the human mind as hermaphroditic (1985, 38; see also
1980, 304, and its subtitle). As she interprets Bacon:
To receive God's truth, the mind must be pure and clean, submissive and
open. Only then can it give birth to a masculine and virile science. That is,
if the mind is pure, receptive, and submissive in its relation to God, it can
be transformed by God into a forceful, potent, and virile agent in its
relation to nature. Cleansed of contamination, the mind can be impregnated by
God and, in that act, virilized: made potent and capable of generating virile
offspring in its union with Nature.
There is as little in the extremely brief Masculine Birth to support
Keller's elaborate reading of Bacon as there is in De Augmentis to support
Harding's perception of rape. The fragments of this essay are themselves a
puzzle and not to be entrusted with the task of clarifying vexatious passages
in Bacon's mature works. Further, Keller's idea does not obviously represent
progress in understanding Bacon. To say that Bacon's model of the mind is
hermaphroditic, that for Bacon, the knowing or scientific mind is sometimes a
virile male and sometimes a receptive female, is only to repeat or redescribe
what we already know, that for science Bacon uses images both of "masculine"
domination over, and "feminine" submission to, nature. This abundance of
contrary images suggests to me that gender images in Bacon are less
interesting and deep than Keller's elaborate reading makes them out to be.
The incoherence of Bacon's images goes beyond the one contrast Keller
exhibits. Consider, for example, how indiscriminately, in Novum Organum alone,
Bacon uses bondage imagery. In one passage, he bemoans that "men's powers"
have been "bound up" by the "enchantments of antiquity" (84). In another, he
criticizes logical demonstrations on the grounds that they "make the word the
bond-slave of human thought, and human thought the bond-slave of words" (69).
Lest we get the impression that nature is the only object of bondage, Bacon
recommends that the human mind be bound--it will do us some good. For the sake
of the improvement of knowledge, scientists should "bind themselves to two
rules" (130) and "the understanding must not . . . be supplied with wings, but
rather hung with weights, to keep it from leaping and flying" (104). To say
that the mind is, for Bacon, an appropriate object of beneficial bondage quite
because the mind is sometimes, or partially, female, is a stretch. Another
example: the effect of matter on the course of nature is, almost
incomprehensibly, more dramatic and graphic, in Bacon's language, than what
science does, or can do, to nature ("hound" and "drive"). Bacon writes in De
Augmentis (see also Parasceve, Works IV, 253) that nature
is either free, and follows her ordinary course of development; . . . or
she is driven out of her ordinary course by the perverseness, insolence, and
frowardness of matter, and violence of impediments; as in the case of
monsters; or lastly she is put in constraint, moulded, and made as it were new
by art and the hand of man; as in things artificial. (Works IV, 294)
The contrast is somewhat sharper in Description of the Intellectual Globe:
For nature is either free . . . or again she is forced and driven quite out
of her course by the perversities and insubordination of wayward and
rebellious matter, and by the violence of impediments; . . . or lastly, she is
constrained, moulded, translated, and made as it were new by art and the hand
of man. (Works V, 505-6)
Constraint of nature by the human hand need not be vicious, violent, a bit
of torture, perverse. A bush--as natural a piece of nature as one can
imagine--can be gently pruned, thereby constrained, "made as it were new by
art," watered and fed; and, as a result, it will both thrive and bring us
pleasure.
There is another inconsistency in Bacon's images or, perhaps, a dualism in
his attitude toward nature. On the one hand, nature is profoundly wise and
subtle, so discovering Nature's Ways requires not just diligence but shrewd
intelligence. Similarly, in Bacon's world--he and his peers are gentleman, not
barroom bruisers--women are wooed with poetry, or bribed, or promised a love
that will not be forthcoming. Comprehending the secrets of nature might be
like uncovering the secrets of a woman, but it is the brain, not brawn, that
yields the joys of science and sex. On the other hand, nature is also, for
Bacon, one tough cookie, whose floods and hurricanes and famines and
pestilences kill us and destroy our property. No wonder, then, that Bacon
speaks about constraining and forcing nature. But neither image in this
dualism--nature is smart but, with luck and skill, can be seduced; nature is
cruel but, with luck and skill, we can avoid the worst of it--is obnoxious.
Bacon' s mistake is similar to Feyerabend's, who conceives of women only as
kittens or stem mistresses, which imagery excessively narrows the modes of
existence possible for them. Bacon's dualism is not the same as Feyerabend's,
but maybe both Baconians and Feyerabendians can be prodded into avoiding these
mildly sexist polarities and to think, instead, in terms of an equal
relationship with an independent and capable woman of substance. If we are to
believe Harding, this could only "foster the growth of knowledge."
I suggest, given the wide variety of Bacon's metaphors, that we not take
them very seriously as attempts at deliberate manipulation of his audience or
as the smoke signals of his seething unconscious. They are more plausibly
"literary embellishments" than a "substantive part of science" (contra Harding
1991, 44) and, as Bacon says in Description of the Intellectual Globe,
irrelevant to his message:
If any one dislike that arts should be called the bonds of nature, thinking
that they should rather be counted as her deliverers and champions, because in
some cases they enable her to fulfil her own intention by reducing obstacles
to order; for my part I do not care about these refinements and elegancies of
speech; all I mean is, that nature, like Proteus, is forced by art to do that
which without art would not be done; call it what you will,--force and bonds,
or help and perfection. (Works V, 506)
As we are rightly rereading the canon through feminist lenses, let us take
care lest we succumb to the "impatience of research." Otherwise in our
investigations, be they philosophical, scientific, or historical, we will
discover precisely that which we hoped to discover, and we will project into
the canon horrors that are not there.
Received November 1, 1994
In memoriam: Thomas D. Perry
Assistance was provided by the University of New Orleans and its College of
Liberal Arts, through the release tire of a research professor appointment,
and by the Research Support Scheme of the Open Society Institute, formerly of
the Central European University (grant 1520/706/94). Edward Johnson was a
patient sounding board for my ideas and in numerous ways facilitated the
essay's progress; Lynn Hankinson Nelson encouraged the project from the start;
and Mariam Thalos read the essay thoroughly and spotted some mistakes. The
anonymous referees of this journal made some useful suggestions and sent me to
additional passages in Bacon. I am also grateful for the comments of Feher
Marta, Bendl Julia, Benedek Andras, Forrai Gabor, Margitay Tihamer, and others
at the Philosophy Institute of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences, where an
ancestor of this paper was presented in May 1994. (Travel to Budapest was made
possible by grants from the International Research and Exchanges Board and
Hungarian Ministry of Culture and Education.) The main idea for this version
was arrived at on Hoff Street, in Philadelphia, PA, August 1994.
NOTES
1. See Bordo (1987, 107-8); Longino (1988, 563; 1990, 205); Nelson (1990,
213, 353 n. 136); Tuana (1990, 62)--all under the influence of Harding,
Merchant, and Keller.
2. I quote from Feyerabend because Harding (1991) gives, as the last
sentence, "I think I do not have to explain my own, preferences" (43). In her
1986 book, Harding quotes it correctly (120).
3. Although Harding takes his metaphor as being about "science and its
theories" (1986, 121), and Feyerabend agrees (1970, 229), it makes equal sense
to read it as being about the nature of the reality that lies beyond science.
We should not view Nature as a stern and demanding mistress, which it is for
Popper and Lakatos: their Nature screams "False!" or "Incompatible!" when it
does not like our scientific theories. Instead, Nature is an indulgent
courtesan, one who lets us do whatever we want--in theory construction. It is
Nature that whispers "Anything goes, big guy," not Science.
4. For an overview of Bacon's life and philosophy, see Thomas Macaulay' s
1837 essay on Bacon and John Robertson's critical reply (1905, vii- xvi).
5. The two sentences are from Bacon's 1623 Of the Dignity and Advancement
of Learning, Works IV, 296; hereafter, De Augmentis. Harding takes the passage
not from Bacon but from Merchant (1980, 168), who takes it from Works IV.
6. Keller also argues (1978, 412-3, 429; 1985, 91) that the Baconian
scientist is asexual; even though he dominates a female nature, the marriage
they have is chaste, cold, distant, detached. This sits uneasily with Bacon's
"conquest" of nature being forceful sexual seduction, let alone rape.
7. Rossi suggests that Bacon, in "Erichthonius," expressed his view that to
be successful with nature, science has to "humbly beg her assistance" (1968,
101; see also "humble respect," 105). Keller (1985, 37) quotes Rossi, but not
this phrase, creating the impression that he agrees with her "forceful and
aggressive seduction" reading.
8. Harding quotes these two De Augmentis sentences three times in two
books, always informing us that her source is Merchant's The Death of Nature
(1980, 168). Merchant includes the five missing words. In addition to failing
to mark an ellipsis in the first of Bacon's two sentences, Harding makes a
second mistake in WS? WK?: ellipsis points belong between the two sentences,
since Harding omits a large chunk. Any hint of rape created by the
juxtaposition of these sentences in WS? WK? is therefore artificial. There are
other errors (cf. Works IV, 296). In Merchant, we correctly find "these
holes," while in Harding, "those." Merchant and Harding write "whole object,"
but both are wrong, "sole object" is correct. Merchant, and Harding in SQIF,
gives "drive her afterward," but both are wrong, in WS?WK?, Harding got
"afterwards" right.
9. See also Bordo's (1987) remark on this sentence from De Augmentis,
apparently provoked by Keller and Merchant: it illustrates "the famous
Baconian imagery of sexual assault" (107-8).
10. Henceforth I supply for Novum Organum only the Book I aphorism number.
11. This is reminiscent of Merchant on Bacon's experimentalism: "Here, in
bold sexual imagery, is the key feature of the modern experimental
method--constraint of nature in the laboratory" (1980, 171).
12. Bacon is no blind optimist he recognizes that science done poorly will
go wrong. See, for example, "Daedalus" (Myth 19) in Wisdom of the Ancients
(Robertson, 842-43).
13. See my (1985), at 73-4.
14. Similarly, it will not help Harding to claim that her experiences and
social location as a feminist or woman grant her an epistemic advantage--in
this case, they make her an especially perceptive reader of early
seventeenth-century texts (see her 1991, 121-33, 150-51, and my [1992] and
[1994]). Harding's reading of Bacon is a politically inspired reading that
goes wrong, and so subverts her claim that feminist scholarship is better
because it is deliberately political.
15. Merchant's "a" true judgment should be the. See note 8, above.
16. Robbins (1959, 278-79). He suggests--sounding a contemporary note-
-that James's realization that children had been "falsely charging people as
witches" was crucial for his change of mind.
17. See Farrington (1964, 48-9).
18. Keller (1978, 413; 1980, 301; 1985, 36) took this sentence from Leiss
(1972, 25), who took it from Farrington's translation (1964, 131). Redargutio
Philosophiarum is not translated from the Latin in Works III (557-85) and was
not published until 1734 (Farrington 1964, 57).
19. In "Atalanta," Myth 25 of Wisdom of the Ancients (Robertson, 847- 48),
Bacon says, "Art remains subject to Nature, as the wife to the husband." It
seems that Bacon is reversing his purportedly favorite misogynous analogy;
instead of the husband science dominating his woman nature in a patriarchal
marriage, science is the unfortunate wife who is dominated by nature the man.
But his point here has nothing to do with gender; he is saying that science
(Atalanta) will not win the race with nature (Hippomenes) if she allows
herself to be distracted by baubles--impatiently, quickly gained research
results that eventually prove worthless. Bacon uses the Atalanta-and-apples
story often, without any obfuscating marital or gender image; see Novum
Organum, 70, 117, and "The Plan" of The Great Instauration (Works IV, 29).
20. In her 1980 essay (308, n. 11), and its revision in Reflections (1985,
36), Keller claims to have taken this passage from Spedding' s Description of
the Intellectual Globe, Works V, 506; it is not there. In her 1982 essay (598,
n. 22), she again says that it is from Description of the Intellectual Globe
but now cites p. 506 of Robertson's collection instead of Sped-ding's Works.
On that page, however, is De Augmentis, Book V, chap. 2. The passage is in
Farrington's translation of Cogitata et Visa (Thoughts and Conclusions; 1964,
93). See also Leiss (1972, 58, 216 n. 18).
21. Harding and O'Barr (1987, 233-46; Boyd et al. 1991, 279-88).
22. Merchant mentions the slave passage twice in the space of two pages
(1980,169, 170); and see Bleier (1984, 204-5), who condemns Bacon by
reproducing only the slave passage, which she took from Keller (1982).
REFERENCES
Bacon, E 1857-1874. The works of Francis Bacon, vols. I-XIV. Edited by J.
Spedding, R. L. Ellis, and D. D. Heath. London: Longman. Reprinted 1962-1963.
Stuttgart: Verlag.
Bleier, R. 1984. Science and gender. New York: Pergamon.
Bordo, S. 1987. The flight to objectivity. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Boyd, R., E Gasper, and J. D. Trout, eds. 1991. The philosophy of science.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Farrington, B. 1964. The philosophy of Francis Bacon. Liverpool: Liverpool
University Press. Reprinted 1966. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Feyerabend, E 1970. Consolations for the specialist. In Criticism and the
Growth of Knowledge, edited by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave, 197-230. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Harding, S. 1986. The science question in feminism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
-----.1989. Value-free research is a delusion. New York Times, October 22,
E24.
-----. 1991. Whose science? Whose knowledge? Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Harding, S., and J. E O'Barr, eds. 1987. Sex and scientific inquiry.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Keller, E. E 1978. Gender and science. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary
Thought 1:409-33.
-----. 1980. Baconian science: A hermaphroditic birth. Philosophical Forum
11:299-308.
-----. 1982. Feminism and science. Signs 7:589-602.
-----. 1985. Reflections on gender and science. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Leiss, W. 1972. The domination of nature. New York: George Braziller.
Longino, H. 1988. Review essay. Science, objectivity, and feminist values.
Feminist Studies 14:561-74.
-----.1990. Science as social knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Macaulay, T. B. 1967. Francis Bacon. In Critical and historical essays,
Vol. 2, 290-398. New York: Dutton.
Merchant, C. 1980. The death of nature. New York: Harper & Row.
Morgan, R. 1977. Going too far. New York: Random House.
Nelson, L. H. 1990. Who knows. From Quine to a feminist empiricism.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Robbins, R. H. 1959. The Encyclopedia of withcraft and demonology. New
York: Crown.
Robertson, J. M., ed. 1905. The philosophical works of Francis Bacon.
London: Routledge.
Rossi, E 1968. Francis Bacon. From magic to science. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Soble, A. 1985. Pornography: Defamation and the endorsement of degradation.
Social Theory and Practice 11:61-87.
-----. 1992. Review of Harding's Whose science? Whose knowledge? in
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6:159-62.
-----. 1994. Gender, objectivity, and realism. Monist 77:509-30.
Tuana, N. 1990. Review of Harding and O'Barr's Sex and scientific inquiry,
in American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy
89:61-2.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone