Website Sections
- Home Page
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Transhuman News Blog
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
News Categories
- Artificial Intelligence
- Astronomy
- Cyborg
- Eugenics
- Freedom
- Futurism
- Futurist
- Liberty
- Nanotechnology
- NASA
- Spirituality
- Transhuman
- Mesothelioma
Egalitarian Fiction and Collective Fraud
Social science today condones and perpetuates a great falsehood - one that undergirds much current social policy. This falsehood, or "egalitarian fiction," holds that racial-ethnic groups never differ in average developed intelligence (or, in technical terms, g, the general mental ability factor). While scientists have not yet determined their source, the existence of sometimes large group differences in intelligence is as well-established as any fact in the social sciences. How and why then is this falsehood perpetrated on the public? What part do social scientists themselves play, deliberately or inadvertently, in creating and maintaining it? Are some of them involved in what might be termed "collective fraud?" Intellectual dishonesty among scientists and scholars is, of course, nothing new. But watchdogs of scientific integrity have traditionally focused on dishonesty of individual scientists, while giving little attention to the ways in which collectivities of scientists, each knowingly shaving or shading the truth in small but similar ways, have perpetuated frauds on the scientific community and the public at large. Perhaps none of the individuals involved in the egalitarian fiction could be accused of fraud in the usual sense of the term. Indeed, I would be the first to say that, like other scientists, most of these scholars are generally honest. Yet, their seemingly minor distortions, untruths, evasions, and biases collectively produce and maintain a witting falsehood. Accordingly, my concern here is to explore the social process by which many otherwise honest scholars facilitate, or feel compelled to endorse, a scientific lie.
The Egalitarian Fiction
It is impossible here to review the voluminous evidence showing that racial-ethnic
differences in intelligence are the rule rather than the exception (some groups
performing better than whites and others worse), and that the well-documented
black-white gap is especially striking. All groups span the continuum of intelligence,
but some groups contain greater proportions of individuals that are either gifted
or dull than others. Three facts regarding these group differences are of particular
importance here for together they contradict the claim that there are no meaningful
group differences. Racial-ethnic differences in intelligence are real. The large
average group differences in mental test scores in the United States do not
result from test bias, which is minuscule overall, as even a National Academy
of Science panel concluded in 1982. Moreover, intelligence and aptitude tests
measure general mental abilities, such as reasoning and problem solving, not
merely accumulated bits of knowledge - and thus tap what experts and laymen
alike view as "intelligence."
Regardless of how we choose to construe them, differences in intelligence are
of great practical importance. Overall they predict performance in school and
on the job better than any other single attribute or condition we have been
able to measure. Intelligence certainly is not the only factor that affects
performance, but higher levels of intelligence greatly increase people's odds
of success in many life settings. Group disparities in intelligence are stubborn.
Although individuals fluctuate somewhat in intelligence during their lives,
differences among groups seem quite stable. The average black-white difference,
for example, which appears by age six, has remained at about 18 Stanford-Binet
IQ points since it was first measured in large national samples over seventy
years ago. It is not clear yet why the disparities among groups are so stubborn
- the reasons could be environmental, genetic, or a combination of both - but
so far they have resisted attempts to narrow them. Although these facts may
seem surprising, most experts on intelligence believe them to be true but few
will acknowledge their truth publicly.
Misrepresentation of Expert Opinion
The 1988 book The IQ Controversy: The Media and Public Policy, by psychologist-lawyer
Mark Snyderman and political scientist Stanley Rothman provides strong evidence
that the general public receives a highly distorted view of opinion among "IQ
experts." In essence, say Snyderman and Rothman, accounts in major national
newspapers, newsmagazines, and television reports have painted a portrait of
expert opinion that leaves the impression that "the majority of experts
in the field believe it is impossible to adequately define intelligence, that
intelligence tests do not measure anything that is relevant to life performance,
and that they are biased against minorities, primarily blacks and Hispanics,
as well as against the poor." However, say the authors, the survey of experts
revealed quite the opposite: On the whole, scholars with any expertise in the
area of intelligence and intelligence testing ... share a common view of [what
constitute] the most important components of intelligence, and are convinced
that [intelligence] can be measured with some degree of accuracy. An overwhelming
majority also believe that individual genetic inheritance contributes to variations
in IQ within the white community, and a smaller majority express the same view
about the black-white and SES [socioeconomic] differences in IQ.
Unfortunately, such wholesale misrepresentation of expert opinion is not limited
to the field of intelligence, as Rothman has shown in parallel studies of other
policy-related fields such as nuclear energy or environmental cancer research.
However, the study of IQ experts revealed something quite surprising. Most experts'
private opinions mirrored the conclusions of psychologist Arthur Jensen, whom
the media have consistently painted as extreme and marginal for holding precisely
those views. As Snyderman and Rothman point out, the experts disclosed their
agreement with this "controversial" and putatively marginal position
only under cover of anonymity. No one, not even Jensen himself, had any inkling
that his views now defined the mainstream of expert belief. Although Jensen
regularly received private expressions of agreement, he and others had been,
as Snyderman and Rothman note, widely castigated by the expert community for
expressing some of those views. Several decades ago, most experts, among them
even Jensen, believed many of the views that the media now wrongly describe
as mainstream - for example, that cultural bias accounts for the large black-white
differences in mental test scores. While the private consensus among IQ experts
has shifted to meet Jensen's "controversial" views, the public impression
of their views has not moved at all. Indeed, the now-refuted claim that tests
are hopelessly biased is treated as a truism in public life today. The shift
in private, if not public, beliefs among IQ experts is undoubtedly a response
to the overwhelming weight of evidence which has accumulated in recent decades
on the reality and practical importance of racial-ethnic differences in intelligence.
This shift is by all indications a begrudging one, and certainly no flight into
"racism."
Snyderman and Rothman found that as many IQ experts as journalists and science
editors (two out of three) agreed with the statement that "strong affirmative
action measures should be used in hiring to assure black representation."
Fully 63 percent of the IQ experts described themselves as liberal politically,
17 percent as middle of the road, and 20 percent as conservative - not much
different than the results for journalists (respectively, 64, 21, and 16 percent).
Moreover, as Snyderman and Rothman suggest (and as is consistent with personal
accounts by Jensen and others), many of the surveyed experts, while agreeing
with Jensen's conclusions, may disapprove of his expressing these conclusions
openly. Consistent with this, when queried about their respect for the work
of fourteen individuals who have written about intelligence or intelligence
testing, the IQ experts rated Jensen only above the widely but apparently unjustly)
vilified Cyril Burt. Despite the fact that most agreed with Jensen, they rated
him far lower than often like-minded psychometricians who had generally stayed
clear of the fray. Jensen even received significantly lower ratings than his
vocal critics, such as psychologist Leon Kamin, whose scientific views are marginal
by the experts' own conclusions. By contrast, the experts in environmental cancer
research behaved as one would expect; they gave higher reputational ratings
to peers who are closer to the mainstream than to high-profile critics. Snyderman's
and Rothman's findings therefore suggest that a high proportion of experts are
misrepresenting their beliefs or are keeping silent in the face of a public
falsehood. It is no wonder that the public remains misinformed on this issue.
Living Within a Lie
IQ experts feel enormous pressure to "live within a lie," to use
a phrase by Czech writer and leader Vaclav Ravel characterizing daily life under
communist rule n Eastern Europe. Ravel argued, in The Power of the Powerless,
that, by living a lie, ordinary citizens were complicit in their own tyranny.
Every greengrocer, every clerk who agreed to display official slogans not reflecting
his own beliefs, or who voted in elections known to be farcical, or who feigned
agreement at political meetings, normalized falsification and tightened the
regime's grip on thought. Each individual who lived the lie, who capitulated
to "ideological pseudo-reality, " became a petty instrument of the
regime. As many commentators have noted, Americans may not speak certain truths
about racial matters today. To adapt a phrase, there is a "structured silence."
Social scientists had already begun subordinating scientific norms to political
preferences and creating much of our current pseudo-reality on race by the mid-1960s.
Sociologist Eleanor Wolf, in a 1972 article in Race, for example, detailed her
distress at how fellow social scientists were misusing research data to support
particular positions on civil rights policy: presenting inconclusive data as
if it were decisive; lacking candor about "touchy" subjects (such
as the undesirable behavior of lower-class students); blurring or shaping definitions
(segregation, discrimination, racism) to suit "propagandistic" purposes;
making exaggerated claims about the success of favored policies (compensatory
education and school integration) while minimizing or ignoring contrary evidence.
As a result, social science and social policy are now dominated by the theory
that discrimination accounts for all racial disparities in achievements and
well-being. This theory collapses, however, if deprived of the egalitarian fiction,
as does the credibility of much current social policy. Neither could survive
intact if their central premise were scrutinized.
No wonder, then, that IQ researchers find themselves under great professional
and institutional pressure to avoid not only engaging in such scrutiny but even
appearing to countenance it. The scrutiny itself must be discredited; the egalitarian
fiction must be raised above serious scientific question. Scientists must at
least appear to believe the dogma. As was the case in Ravel's communist-dominated
Eastern Europe, in American academe feigned belief in the official version of
reality is maintained largely by routine obeisance of academics as they pursue
their own ambitions.
Scholars realize their scholarly ambitions primarily through other scholars.
Peer recognition is the currency of academic and scientific life. It is crucial
to a scholarly reputation and all the steps toward status and success - publications,
professional invitations and awards, promotion, tenure, grants, fellowships,
election to professional office, appointment to prestigious panels. One's ability
even to carry out certain kinds of research, funded or not, may be contingent
upon peer recognition and respect - for instance, getting collaborators, subjects,
or cooperation from potential research sites. Just as in personal life, a high
professional reputation depends upon a sustained history of "appropriate"
behavior, and it may be irreparably damaged by hints of scandal or impropriety.
Similarly, the reputations of scientists and their organizations are enhanced
or degraded by those for whom they show regard and approval. Associating oneself
with highly regarded individuals or ideas enhances, even if slightly, one's
own status.
Awarding an honor to a luminary can enhance the reputation of one's own organization,
especially if the recipient accepts the honor with genuine appreciation. By
the same token, one risks "staining" one's reputation by associating
with, honoring, defending, or even failing to condemn the "wrong"
sort of individual or idea. In short, how one gives or withholds one's regard
is important for one's professional reputation because it affects the regard
one receives. Such a social system enhances the integrity of science and is
furthered by personal ambition when the members of the community base their
regard on scholarly norms, such as competence, creativity, and intellectual
rigor. However, such . a system breeds intellectual corruption when members
systematically subordinate scientific norms to other considerations -money,
politics, religion, fear. This is what appears to be happening today in the
social sciences on matters of race and intelligence. As sociologist Robert Gordon
argues, social science has become "one-party science."
Democrat or Republican, liberal or conservative, virtually all American intellectuals
publicly adhere to, if not espouse, the egalitarian fiction. And many demonstrate
their party loyalty by enforcing the fiction in myriad small ways in their academic
routine, say, by off-handedly dismissing racial differences in intelligence
as "a racist claim, of course," criticizing authors for "blaming
the victim," or discouraging students and colleagues from doing "sensitive"
research. One can feel the gradient of collective alarm and disapproval like
a deepening chill as one approaches the forbidden area. Researchers who cross
the line occasionally face overt censorship, or calls for it. For example, one
prominent (neoconservative) editor rejected an author's paper, despite finding
it scientifically sound, because there are social "considerations"
which "overweigh the claims of social science." Another eminent editor,
after asking an author to soften the discussion in his article, recently published
the revised paper with an editorial postscript admonishing scientists in the
field to find a "balance" between the need for free exchange of research
results on intelligence and the (presumably comparable) "need" that
"no segment of our society...feel threatened" by it.
Covert and Overt Censorship
Whether motivated by a sincere concern over supposedly "dangerous"
ideas or by a desire to distance themselves publicly from unpopular ideas, editors
who use such non-academic standards discourage candor and stifle debate. They
deaden social science by choking off one source of the genuine differences of
opinion that are its lifeblood. Overt censorship of research is uncommon, probably
because it is an obvious affront to academic norms. Less striking forms of censorship
directly affect many more academics, however, and so may be more important.
Easier to practice without detection and to disguise as " academic judgment,
" they serve to keep scholars from pursuing ideas that might undermine
the egalitarian dogma.
A less obvious form of censorship, which has become somewhat common recently,
is indirect censorship. It is accomplished when academic or scientific organizations
approve some views but repudiate or burden others on ideological grounds. Sometimes
the ideological grounds are explicit Campus speech codes are a well-known example
which, had they been upheld in the courts, would have made repudiation of the
egalitarian fiction a punishable offense on some campuses. The earlier (unsuccessful)
attempt to include possible "offense to minority communities" as grounds
for refusing human subjects approval is another example.
Gordon reports yet others, including the National Institutes of Health's new
extra layer of review for politically "sensitive" grant proposals
and the University of Delaware's recent policy (reversed by a national arbitrator)
of banning a particular funding source because, so the university claimed, it
supports research on race which "conflicts with the university's mission
to promote racial and cultural diversity." Gordon also outlines in detail
- as political scientist Ian Blits has done - the covert application of ideological
standards to facilitate expression of some views but burden others. This form
of indirect censorship, also falling under the rubric of "political correctness,"
occurs when university administrators, faculty, or officers of professional
associations disguise as "professional judgment" an ideological bias
in their enforcing of organizational rules, extending faculty privileges, protecting
faculty rights, and weighing evidence in faculty promotions and grievances.
Recently, some American universities have invoked "professional judgment"
as a pretext for reclassifying "controversial" scholarly publications
in their annual merit reviews as "non-research," to misrepresent outside
peer reviews in evaluating controversial professionals up for promotion, and
to limit student access to these professors. Such thinly veiled bias publicly
demonstrates the officials' own adherence to the prescribed institutional attitudes
and their willingness to enforce them, not only protecting those officials from
protest but also encouraging fellow members of the institution to toe the line.
Covert censorship is far more common than overt or indirect censorship. It consists
of bias in the application of scientific norms when reviewers evaluate their
peers' work for funding, publication, presentation, or dissemination. Individual
ideological biases are found in all fields, of course, but the hope is that
such biases remain small and will cancel each other out over the long run -
hence the importance of a free and open exchange of data, theories, and results.
What I have in mind is systematic bias and a pervasive double standard which
impedes one line of research and accords another undeserved hegemony. In one-party
science, the disfavored line of work is subjected to intense scrutiny and nearly
impossible standards, while the favored line of work is held to lax standards
in which flaws are overlooked (called "oversight bias" in the psychological
literature). Similarly, the disfavored idea is rejected unless it is "balanced"
by including proponents of the favoapplication of scientific norms when reviewers
evaluate their peers' work for funding, publication, presentation, or dissemination.
The broader circle of critics in the social sciences often implicitly dismisses
the legitimacy of research on intelligence itself by arguing that "intelligence"
is undefinable or unmeasurable - as if the critics' own favored constructs (social
class, culture, self-concept, anxiety, and so on) were as well validated and
operationalized. Others now also seek to deny IQ researchers (but not themselves)
use of the concept "race" because, they assert, race is not a biological
condition, but is socially constructed. The double standards can even ricochet
back and forth, depending on the particular question being considered. Gordon
recalls how sociologists failed to criticize sociologist James Coleman for omitting
student ability from his analyses of school integration (which led to overstating
the impact of integrated schools on black achievement-for sociologists a favorable
outcome), but how they criticized him roundly for the very same omission in
analyses of private versus public schools, (which led to overstating the impact
of private schools on black achievement - an unfavorable outcome). In short,
in one-party science, scientific regard flows like political patronage to loyal
and active party members, who can demonstrate their loyalty by being alert to
hints of dissidence. Like all one-party political systems, one-party science
becomes intellectually corrupt and arrogant as it gains confidence in its power.
The most insidious corruption to which one-party science leads is pervasive
self-censorship, what involved researchers generally prefer to regard as "prudence"
or "avoiding unnecessary trouble." Coleman has drawn particular attention
to the problem of "self-suppression" - "the impulse not to ask
the crucial question" - in research on race. In an example from his own
research for the influential "Coleman Report," he describes his failure
to conduct important analyses that might have produced embarrassing findings
about the abilities of black teachers. Another way of avoiding unwanted results
is to ignore certain data, subjects, or variables. Or unwanted results can be
omitted, buried in footnotes, explained away, or simply ignored in one's conclusions.
The most subtle form of self-censorship is deliberate avoidance of making crucial
connections, or denying them. Psychologist Richard Herrnstein has noted that
it was his drawing out the implications of one such connection, namely, that
some portion of (white) social class differences in intelligence is genetic,
that sparked his public excoriation in the 1970s.
Normally, scholars are eager to explicate illuminating connections between sub
specialties. They are reluctant to do so, however, when these connections put
in question the egalitarian dogma on race. Virtually all sociologists and economists
ignore the literature on intelligence despite its central importance to core
issues in their disciplines, such as inequalities in occupation and income.
Many psychometricians, especially those working for large testing organizations,
avoid referring to "intelligence" and often seem reluctant to say
much about the practical or theoretical meaning of the racial differences they
observe on unbiased tests. But even remaining within one's sub field is often
not enough, for the field of intelligence itself is widely suspect. Hence some
scholars explicitly disavow unpopular connections that critics might attribute
to them. For example, they will argue in favor of the importance of intelligence
for scholastic performance but then assure their readers, over-optimistically,
that the racial gap "!seems to be closing rapidly." The tenor of these
preemptive disclaimers is clear. While researchers in any field may lightly
dismiss the credibility of key connections regarding race and intelligence,
no one ever lightly endorses their credibility with impunity. Even those of
us committed to candor are exceedingly cautious when expressing informed opinions
on certain topics, especially the genetics of race. Thus, publicly stated opinions
of researchers about matters outside their sub fields tend in one direction
-to dispute or undercut the facts necessary for toppling the egalitarian fiction.
What may be tolerable behavior at the individual level becomes intolerable bias
at the aggregate level. Censorship - even self-censorship - requires justification,
or at least apparent justification. On the whole, those who would squelch open
inquiry of the egalitarian fiction base their justification on two assertions:
1) Research on racial differences in intelligence has already been scientifically
"discredited." 2) Inquiry into racial differences is immoral.
Point one asserts that the egalitarian premise is absolute truth and hence beyond
scientific scrutiny. Point two is indifferent to its truth. Both counsel outrage
at the very thought of the research. The claim that the research has been discredited
rests largely on extensive misrepresentation that is often embarrassingly crude
or casual - for example, contradicting arguments an author never made, while
ignoring what was actually stated; attributing policy preferences to an author
which are opposite of what the author actually expressed; or simply alleging
fraud or gross incompetence without any substantiation whatsoever. The claim
that the research is immoral rests squarely on the view that, regardless of
the truth, the study itself can only be harmful. In fact, some critics assert
(mostly privately) that the greater the truth, the greater the danger it poses
to lower-scoring groups, and thus the greater the need to suppress it.
Despite their differences, both justifications for censorship often take the
form of demonizing open inquiry by labeling it (and the people who practice
it) as "dangerous," "fascist," "ideological,"
or "racist." The study of race and intelligence is something, they
tell us, that no decent person - let alone a serious scientist - would ever
do and that every decent person and serious researcher would oppose. Thus, in
a kind of Orwellian inversion, marked by what Gordon calls "high talk and
low blows," the suppression of science presents itself as science itself.
Intellectual dishonesty becomes the handmaiden of social conscience, and ideology
is declared knowledge while knowledge is dismissed as mere ideology. Neither
social policy, nor science, nor society itself is served well by scientific
silence on racial differences in intelligence.
Enforcement of the egalitarian fiction has tragic consequences, especially for
blacks. The outcomes are even worse than researchers of intelligence predicted
two decades ago. The falsehood, because it tries to defy a reality that has
conspicuous repercussions in daily life, is doing precisely what it was meant
to avoid: producing pejorative racial stereotypes, fostering racial tensions,
stripping members of lower-scoring groups of their dignity and incentives to
achieve, and creating permanent social inequalities between the races. Enforcement
of the lie is gradually distorting and degrading all institutions and processes
where intelligence is at least somewhat important (which is practically everywhere)
but especially where it is most important (in public schools, higher education,
the professions, and high-level executive work). The falsehood requires that
there be racial preferences and that their use be disguised, wherever intelligence
has at least moderate importance. Society is thus being shaped to meet the dictates
of a collective fraud. The fiction is aiding and abetting bigots to a far greater
degree than any truth ever could, because its specific side-effects - racial
preferences, official mendacity, free-wielding accusations of racism, and falling
standards - are creating deep cynicism and broad resentment against minorities,
blacks in particular, among the citizenry.
Enforcement of the egalitarian fiction is not a moral or scientific imperative;
it is merely political. It is terribly short-sighted, for it corrupts both science
and society. However, just as the fiction is sustained by small untruths, so
can it be broken down by many small acts of scientific integrity. This requires
no particular heroism. All that is required is for scientists to act like scientists
- to demand, clearly and consistently, respect for truth and for free inquiry
in their own settings, and to resist the temptation to win easy approval by
endorsing a comfortable lie.