Website Sections
- Home Page
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Transhuman News Blog
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
News Categories
- Artificial Intelligence
- Astronomy
- Cyborg
- Eugenics
- Freedom
- Futurism
- Futurist
- Liberty
- Nanotechnology
- NASA
- Spirituality
- Transhuman
- Mesothelioma
Partners
The Attack on The Bell Curve By Richard Lynn
This paper originally appeared in Personality and Individual Differences 26
B. DevUn, S.E. Fienberg, D.P. Resnick and K. Roeder (Eds). Intelligence, Genes and Success: Scientists Respond
to The Bell Curve, Springer-Yerlag, New York (1997), ISBN 0-387-94986-0, 376 pp.
C.S. Fischer, M. Hoot, M.S. Jankowski, S.R. Locas, A. Swidler and K. Yoss (Eds), Inequality by Design: Cracking
The Bell Curve Myth, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ (1996). ISBN 0-691-02899-0, 318 pp.
It is doubtful whether any book in the entire history of psychology has been so extensively attacked as The
Bell Curve
by the late Richard Herrnstein and Charles Murray (1994). The book has been the subject of several hundred critical
reviews, a number of which have been collected in edited volumes, some of whose very titles such as Measured
Lies (Kincheloe, Steinberg and Gresson, 1996) betray the emotional strength of the hostility the book has evoked.
However, many of the initial attacks on The Bell Curve fell wide of the mark. Now we have two more serious
books, both of which examine the arguments of The Bell Curve and find then deficient. They contain contributions
from geneticists, psychologists, sociologists and statisticians, and they attempt to refute all the essential arguments
made in The Bell Curve.
Before considering how well they succeed, it will be useful to summarise H and M's major points. These are (1)
the social structure of the United States is to some degree genetically stratified by intelligence and has at its
apex a 'cognitive elite' of professionals and senior executives who are genetically superior to the rest of the
population; this situation has come about relatively recently through social mobility, by which those with high
IQs have risen in the social hierarchy and those with low IQs have fallen; (2) this social stratification by IQ
has increased in recent decades as a result of greater equality of opportunity through which those with high IQs
are increasingly securing entry to elite universities and occupations, where they are meeting and marrying people
like themselves and having elite children; this has been producing a widening intelligence gap between the social
classes and this is likely to continue, leading to a caste society with increasingly genetically differentiated
social classes; (3) for this to be taking place, intelligence must have a reasonably high heritability, which H
and M estimate as lying between 40-80 percent; (4) intelligence is socially important and is a significant determinant
of educational attainment, social status and incomes; (5) low intelligence is a significant determinant of a variety
of social pathologies including poor educational attainment, chronic unemployment, long term welfare dependency,
crime, single motherhood and poverty; (6) these social evils would be reduced if the intelligence of the population
could be increased and it would be desirable if this could be accomplished; (7) there is little chance of being
able to do this because the things that have been tried as improving education and headstart programs have little
or no impact on intelligence; (8) the situation is getting worse because the genetic component of intelligence
is deteriorating through the process of dysgenesis or dysgenics resulting from the tendency of the
intelligent to have fewer children than the unintelligent, for the generation length to be shorter for the less
intelligent, and through the large scale immigration of those with low intelligence; (9) blacks have on average
lower intelligence than whites and Asians and this contributes to the over-representation of blacks in respect
of the social pathologies of poor educational attainment, single motherhood, crime, etc.; the low average IQ of
blacks probably has some genetic basis; the social condition of blacks is likely to deteriorate in the future because
dysgenics is greater among blacks than among whites and this will lead to a widening of the intelligence gap between
blacks and whites; (10) nothing much can be done about any of this; the United States will become increasingly
like South America, with high IQ whites and Asians living in fortified enclaves protected by high fences and armed
guards from 'the menace of the slums below' (p. 518); (11) the future is consequently pretty bleak and the best
that can be done is to try to return to a simpler small town America of yore in which the unintelligent could be
usefully employed doing cognitively undemanding jobs and the local cognitive elite could exercise stronger social
controls over those who step out of line by punishing them more swiftly and effectively than is done in the megalopises
of the contemporary world..
Nearly all of these propositions are challenged in the two books under review. In the first of these, Daniels,
Fienberg, Devlin and Rhoeder dispute the genetics of H and M. They argue that the heritability of IQ is much lower
than that proposed by H and M, that dysgenesis/dysgenics is not taking place and that there is no persuasive evidence
for a genetic component to the black-white IQ difference. On the heritability issue, they argue that H and M should
have distinguished between narrow and broad heritability (the heritability due to additive genes only, and that
due to additive genes plus dominants and recessives). They say that only additive genes are transmitted reliably
from parents to children and could become stratified by social class, that hence only narrow heritability should
be considered in the emergence of the genetic congitive elite thesis; that the narrow heritability of IQ is only
0.34; and that this is too low to produce agenetic cognitive elite.
There are several errors in this argument. First, contrary to the authors' statements, dominant and recessive genes
are transmitted reliably from parents to children and are frequently disproportionately represented in certain
populations. For instance, the dominant gene for myotonic dystrophy has an exceptionally high prevalence in the
population of the Saguenay-Lac-Saint-Jean region of Quebec, where it is more than 100 times more frequent than
is typical for Caucasian populations (Veillette et al., 1992). Similarly, recessive genes for sickle cell anaemia
are almost entirely confined to black populations and the recessives for Tay-Sacks disease are carried with much
greater frequency among Ashkenazi Jews than among gentiles. There is no reason whatever why the dominant and recessive
genes for high intelligence should not have become disproportionately represented among the cognitive elite and
those for low intelligence disproportionately represented in the underclass and it is virtually certain that this
has in fact occurred.
Second, in estimating the narrow heritability of intelligence at 0.34, Devlin et al. make the mistakes of (a) using
the data for all age groups; it has become well known since Bouchard (1993) analysed the data that the heritability
of intelligence is quite low among young children, becomes progressively greater among older children and reaches
its peak among adults. Probably the explanation for this is that the environment provided by parents exerts effects
on young children which wash out by the time they become adult, or that there are genes for intelligence which
do not become active until adolescence. Whatever the explanation, the important figure for heritability is that
derived from adults and this, according to recent estimates, is around 0.80 (Finkel et al., 1995; Petrill et al.,
1998); (b) a second error made by Devlin et al. is that they fail to correct the familial correlations for IQ for
measurement error; this should have been done and the effect is to increase the heritability by around 12%. These
two mistakes put the heritability estimates made by Devlin et al. way off target. If any criticism is to be made
of H and M on their heritability estimate it is that they erred on the side of caution in placing it between 40-80%.
The correct figure for adults is around 80%.
Devlin et al. also criticise H and M's conclusion that genetic deterioration for intelligence is taking place through
the process of dysgenics. H and M demonstrated an inverse association between intelligence and numbers of children
from the National Longitudinal Study of Youth data, from which they inferred the presence of dysgenics. Devlin
et al. object that the data are for 25-33 year olds who have not completed their fertility, that higher IQ women
tend to have their children later, that only data for completed fertility can be used to establish the existence
of dysgenics and that 'insofar as we are aware, there is nothing but anecdotal evidence for dysgenics' (p.61).
The extent of their awareness of the evidence on this issue is seriously deficient. It is true that completed fertility
needs to be assessed to establish the presence , of dysgenics but they fail to note that three studies carried
out in the 1980's and 1990's fulfilled this condition on large representative samples of Americans and all three
found completed fertility is dysgenic (Vining, 1995; Van Court and Bean, 1985; Retherford and Sewell, 1988). H
and M summarise these three studies, but Devlin et. al. have failed to notice this. There is in addition a large
amount of evidence from censuses and other surveys showing an inverse association between completed fertility and
educational level (a proxy for intelligence), and between socio-economic status and intelligence (another proxy
for intelligence), summarised in Lynn (1996). The evidence for dysgenic fertility is far from anecdotal. It is
securely established. Furthermore, Devlin et al. do not address the dysgenic impact of shorter generation length
among the less intelligent, nor that of immigration, for both of which H and M provide evidence.
Devlin et al. turn next to the possibility of a genetic component to the back-white difference in IQ. They reject
this by citing three studies showing that the IQs of black-white hybrids are not related to their amount of Caucasian
ancestry. They fail to cite the 18 studies of the relation of skin colour to IQ summarised by Shuey ( 1966), of
which 16 found that light skin colour, a measure of the amount of Caucasian ancestry, is positively related to
IQ. They assert that adoption studies show the malleability of IQ but fail to note that the leading study of this
question by Waldman, Scarr and Weinberg (1992) showed that as young adults blacks adopted by white families showed
no IQ gains (Lynn, 1994) and that the authors of this study have conceded that their evidence indicates a genetic
component to the low black IQ (Waldman, Weinberg and Scarr, 1994). Finally, Devlin et al. write that 'it is not
clear to us why IQ would be positively selected in Caucasians but not in Africans' (p.62). They are apparently
unaware of the theory that Caucasians were subjected to the cognitively demanding selection pressures of survival
in cold winter environments for around 100,000 years, to which Africans were not exposed, a theory which also explains
the high IQs of East Asians, and which now commands wide assent as the evolutionary explanation for the genetically
based high mean IQ of Caucasians and East Asians (Lynn, 1991; Miller, 1995; Rushton, 1995; Levin, 1997; Jensen,
1998).
Two later chapters discuss the nature of intelligence and the issue of whether H and M were justified in treating
intelligence as a single entity called Spearman's g. Carroll is generally supportive of H and M and says that the
scores on tests of various abilities (reasoning, verbal, spatial, etc.) can legitimately be summed to give a single
measure which can be called general intelligence. Hunt opposes the concept of general intelligence and prefers
the multiple intelligences model. However, he agrees that these are positively intercorrelated and can for practical
purposes be summed to give a measure of general intelligence, and concludes that H and M's general intelligence
is 'not exactly inaccurate but is simplified in an important way'. This conclusion is not seriously damaging to
H and M's case. Everyone from Spearman onwards has accepted that g is a simplification and that there is more to
intelligence than g. Simplification of the real world is precisely what science is about.
The book turns next to the importance of intelligence for earnings and other social phenomena. Cawley, Conneely,
Heckman and Vytlacil examine the NLSY data for the relation between intelligence and earnings. They calculate that
in different subsamples of males and females and of blacks, whites and Hispanics, IQ accounts, for between 0.12
and 0.17 of the variance in earnings, implying correlations of between 0.34 and 0.41. They conclude that H and
M were wrong in their contention that IQ is an important determinant of earnings. There are two defects in their
analysis. First, they omitted both the unemployed, who have low IQs and no earnings, and college students, who
have high IQs and will in time have high earnings. These omissions reduce the correlations between IQs and earnings
and adjustments should have been made for them. Second, corrections should have been made for the unreliability
of the measures of both IQ and earnings. If these adjustments had been made they would have increased the contribution
of IQ to earnings and the authors would have reached a different conclusion.
Cavallo, EI-Abbadi and Heeb consider sex and race differences in the contribution of IQ to earnings. They find
that the black-white difference in earnings is largely due to IQ differences and that controlling for IQ, black
males earn 96% of the earnings of whites, while black females earn 15% more than white females. They do not attempt
to explain the reasons for these differences but fault H and M for not breaking down their analysis by sex. The
sex difference they reveal is interesting, but it hardly dents H and M's case that the earnings of blacks and whites
are pretty much the same once IQ is controlled. In fact, black females earn more than would be predicted from their
IQs, possibly because they benefit more than black males from affirmative action.
Winship and Korenman discuss the effects of education on intelligence and argue that it is greater than H and M
allow. They analyse the NLSY data and calculate that each year ofeducation increases the IQ by 2.5 IQ points. Wahlsten
also argues that education raises IQ. They fault H and M for being too pessimistic about the scope for raising
IQs by improving and increasing education. The weakness of this argument is that many intelligence tests consist
of cognitive tasks taught in schools, such as arithmetic and language problems, and this is particularly true of
the AFQT used in the NLSY. Scores on such tests do improve with education but this is not necessarily the same
thing as increasing intelligence, which consists of many thousands of cognitive skills not taught in schools. The
scope for raising intelligence by increasing education is much less securely established than these critics argue.
The relation between intelligence, crime and race is considered by Manolakes. She accepts H and M's contention
that among whites IQ is negatively associated with crime. H and M did not consider this relationship among blacks.
Manolakes faults them for this and finds that among blacks in the NLSY sample IQ is positively associated with
crime. She criticises Hand M for not discovering this themselves, failing to note that Hand M were not primarily
concerned with race differences. She has certainly made a remarkable discovery considering the large research literature
showing that crime is predominantly committed by the less intelligent. Before taking this result too seriously
it should be noted that the data consist of self-reported crime and people do not invariably report their crimes
truthfully. Nevertheless her apparent discovery that IQ is positively related to crime among blacks certainly deserves
further research.
The remainder of the book consists of chapters by Glymour, a philosopher who asserts that The Bell Curve
is pseudoscience; Zigler and Styfco, who agree that head start programs do not raise IQs but believe they may have
other useful effects; and Lemann, a journalist who doubts whether there is a cognitive elite in America except
in the professions of law, medicine and business consultancy. The book ends with a summary by Resnick and Fienberg,
respectively a historian and statistician, who endorse the generally tendentious and frequently erroneous arguments
of the contributors. The academic disciplines of these authors belie the book's subtitle Scientists Respond
to The Bell Curve. Of the twenty five writers in this book, there is scarcely one who could properly be called
a scientist.
Poor as Intelligence, Genes and Success is, it is no-where near so bad as Inequality by Design. This
is a joint effort produced by six members of the sociology department at Berkeley. Their basic argument is that
intelligence, earnings and socio-economic status are wholly environmentally determined. Their model (p.74) is that
the family and neighborhood environment determine schooling and the cognitive skills of intelligence and educational
attainment, that these determine inequality of earnings, which in turn determine the social problems of chronic
unemployment, welfare dependency, single motherhood, crime, etc. Since intelligence is determined by the environment
and by schooling, it could be increased by providing better environments and better schooling and this would reduce
poverty and its associated ills. This should be done by raising the taxation of those with high and middle incomes
and distributing the proceeds to the poor.
In order to establish their case that IQ is solely determined environmentally, the authors would have to show that
all the twin and adoption studies indicating that intelligence has a moderate" to high heritability are flawed,
but they make no attempt to do this. They should have considered Taubman's (1976) work on the similarity of the
incomes of twins showing that income has a heritability of around 50%. They should also have considered the evidence
that intelligence measured in young children remains fairly stable over subsequent years and predicts later educational
attainment. For instance, it has been shown that the IQ of 5 year olds predicts their performance in an examination
in mathematics taken at the age of 16 at a correlation of.72 (Yule, Gold and Busch, 1982). All this evidence is
ignored. The authors of this deplorable book stand squarely in the tradition of sociological ostriches who have
for so long averted their eyes from evidence they prefer not to see.
In the early and middle decades of the century sociologists largely ignored the role of genetics and intelligence
as determinants of earnings, socioeconomic status, poverty and other social conditions. In the early 1970's a valiant
attempt was made by the sociologist Christopher Jencks (1972) to remedy this blindness of sociological analysis.
Jencks presented a path model linking genes to intelligence to social outcomes which was a forerunner of the analysis
presented in The Bell Curve. Jencks seriously underestimated the strength of these causal links because
he understated the heritability of intelligence and failed to correct for measurement unreliability but he made
a major contribution by formulating the right model. It appears that, so far as the faculty of the sociology department
at Berkeley is concerned, he wasted his time.
There is nothing in either of these two books that makes any serious case against the conclusions of The Bell
Curve. With the exceptions of the chapters by Carroll and Hunt in the first book, the authors systematically
distort the data and ignore the relevant evidence. Just what mix of ideology and sheer ignorance is responsible
for the positions the authors of these two books adopt is difficult to assess. Whatever the explanation, these
two books represent the benighted environmentalist timewarp in which much of contemporary social science is still
enmeshed.
Richard Lynn
University of Ulster
Department of Psychology
Coleraine
Co Londonderry, N Ireland BT52 1 SA
UK
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone
More News
- Aerospace
- Astro Physics
- Beaches
- Eco System
- Gene Therapy
- Genetic Engineering
- Genetic Medicine
- Health Care
- Human Genetics
- Islands
- Libertarian
- Libertarianism
- Medical School
- Medicine
- Mind Upload
- Molecular Medicine
- Moore's Law
- Nano Engineering
- Nano Medicine
- Planetology
- Red heads
- Space Flight