Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
Caring for Posterity
Alan McGregor
Institute for the Study of Man
BEYONDISM: RELIGION FROM SCIENCE
Raymond B. Cattell Praeger, New York
Author Raymond B. Cattell, a member of the editorial advisory board of
this journal, has sometimes been called "Mr. I.Q. Test" because of his role in
developing IQ and Personality tests. His Sixteen Personality Factor test is a
standard tool in educational circles to this day. His contribution to
scholarly knowledge is impressive when measured by volume alone, totalling as
it does over forty books and more than 450 scholarly papers published to date.
More recently his concern has turned to the problem of survival facing
mankind, dependent as mankind is on the preservation of an appropriate
heredity.
Cattell's long history of psychological research has enabled him to
demonstrate that mankind is not in any way different from other biological
organisms so far as the significance of heredity is concerned. Science is
rooted in causality, and the limits of the behavioral potentiality of every
individual are largely set by heredity at the time of conception.
Environmental life-history will influence the subsequent behavior of the
living organism, and some scientists have attempted to evaluate the relative
importance of environment and heredity in terms of statistical figures. Such
figures relate only to specific concepts, specific situations and specific
groups, such as the ability of diverse individuals and groups to perform
effectively in response to a battery of intelligence or personality tests.
This can cause less rigorous thinkers to assume that heredity and environment
are two forces which are in opposition to each other. This is not the case.
Heredity determines the way the human machine is constructed, and environment
operates upon the machine and influences what it will do, or even how long it
will survive. One might use the simile of a computer. What can be done with a
computer depends upon the way it is constructed. But what you can get out of
it will depend upon what data is fed into it.
In consequence of his profound consciousness of the role of heredity in
determining the human potential, Cattell has for many years been concerned
that the quality of the genes that are handed on to future generations of
mankind should be high. Such a statement often leads to immediate criticism on
the grounds that "high quality" implies an objective scale of values against
which we may measure human ability. It brings us into the realm of ethics and,
of course, religion.
Conscious of the fact that any argument favoring eugenic concepts or
stressing the importance of what is colloquially called "good inheritance"
involves an excursion into the realm of ethics, Cattell attempts in this
impressive work to penetrate the field of ethical philosophy and as a good
scientist he asks: what can science tell us about ethics? How can we derive an
ethic of human behavior, a scale of values which might direct human
enterprise, from scientific knowledge? Clearly, science has given us the power
to understand many things, and to modify our environment even ourselves - in
ways hitherto unimaginable. But in what way should this knowledge be used? How
can science help us to create a sound ethical system which will enable us to
act for the benefit of all those generations yet to come, to shape the future
world "beyond" the span of our own lifetime? Cattell's initially rather
surprising title for this book, Beyondism, is derived from that one important,
over-riding ideal - if we are truly concerned with the good of the greatest
number, he argues, let us remember that we should be asking how our actions
will influence the future of all those generations yet to be born. We should
think beyond the horizons of our own life-span, and constantly bear in mind
the welfare of posterity. Our prime concern is that we should leave to future
generations a healthy genetic heritage, including a high level of intelligence
combined with a set of ancillary inherited qualities, not excluding
personality, which will best enable the unborn generations of future men and
women to tackle the problems that will inevitably confront them, many of which
we cannot even envisage at this present time. Thus "the greatest good for the
greatest number" means the greatest good for the future of humanity, for
mankind 'beyond' the limits of our own short selfish life-spans.
Cattell defines "Beyondism" as a system "for discovering and clarifying
ethical goals from a basis of scientific knowledge and investigation by the
objective research procedures of scientific method."
On what objective "realities" can science seek to base morality? Cattell
answers as follows:
"However, it is in the realm of interpretation that Beyondism demands an
act of faith by which it may seem to stand or fall. The Berkeley-Descartes
issue we are content to answer with "The universe exists." What Beyondism
requires in addition is the interpretation that "Evolution exists as a
paramount fact within this universe." Thus, if we wish to be as tightly
logical as a Euclidean proposition - which we need if we claim our position to
be logically sound - we have to recognize these two assumptions or
presuppositions."
Since we assume the reality of the universe, and the findings of science,
we must conclude from our understanding of evolution that species and
subspecies, although changing through time, are more real in the sense of
being durable, of persisting, than are individuals. In fact, individuals are
little more than links in the ongoing, intergenerational chain that is life.
Individuals are important in that they hold in trust the genes of the
subspecies, and they are also important in that the future potential for the
subspecies depends upon which individuals live and reproduce successfully, and
which die without offspring. The reproductive fate of individuals shapes the
future of the group!
"The selection has finally to operate, literally, on individuals, but
often the results are well summarized and understood by considering the effect
on groups either as (1) a species, interbreeding and having common
characteristics, or (2) an organized group. with roles, rules, and social
structure - say a nation."
For life to survive, and for our own kind of life form in particular to
survive, it must maintain and develop further the ability to cope with
changing environmental conditions. In the case of mankind, the key to survival
is increased intelligence, involving selection at both the individual and the
group level.
"In organized groups, as, for example, in primate and human societies, the
possible relations and results are somewhat more complex. Thus, although all
survival ultimately takes place as survival of individuals, it is overconcrete
and unsubtle thinking to overlook that it is nevertheless the ultimate
interactive properties of the species or group as suchthat greatly determine
evolution. The concrete view would say that the death of an individual, for
example, is nothing more than the death of a lot of cells, yet obviously
something more important than the cell dies. The individual cell contains the
plan of the whole body, but when the body dies all cells must die. In the
analogue of the whole social body this is only approximately true, but close
enough to find a considerable reduction in the population type when a culture
dies.
Natural selection is going on simultaneously between groups and
individuals within groups. As we shall see, within-group selection has to
conform to the demands of between-group selection. This was not understood
when Darwin and Wallace first put forward the theory of evolution by natural
selection, for people thought it rested principally on conflict among
individuals Some philosophers and even some scientists have argued that
humankind has now evolved to a point in history at which group selection is no
longer relevant, and that only individual selection will henceforth be
operative. But Cattell disagrees:
"With the second objection - that we know what progress is and can
accordingly abolish group natural selection - Beyondism is in fundamental
disagreement. We can peer ahead a little way, with the help of historical
perspective and reasoning - and even penetrate the fog a little farther when a
truly potent social science is built up - but the wisest never could, and
probably never will, be able to foresee the ultimate effect of inventions and
social legislations. Evolution is no more a straight line than the course of a
ship sounding its way through uncharted channels. History books could be and
have been, filled with the untoward and ludicrous results of labors of
well-intentioned but unimaginative social reformers, who "know what's best."
Thus Cattell places importance on internal group collaboration to ensure
the survival of the group in its prevailing environment. He also perceives
that that "environment" includes competing populations and subspecies:
"What we have to make clear here is the relation of natural selection
among individuals to that among groups. The contribution between group and
individual is a two-way affair. In an obvious sense, a group cannot exist
without individuals, and it has been argued that an individual who is to come
to fullest use in progress cannot exist without a group. It is thus true that
we have a causal chain in what systems theorists call a "feedback" action, in
which individuals help shape the group and the group helps shape the
individual. (One says "helps" because both individual and group get part of
the shaping from the physical environment). This statement of course applies
to both cultural and genetic shaping, recognizing that different genetic
predispositions will respond differently to schooling. It follows from the
above that we do not have a complete symmetry where natural selection comes
in. It the genetic and cultural shaping of individuals must yield a viable
group, then that shaping has to be something that fits the survival of the
group in its interactions with other groups and the environment. The
conditions of survival of the group must determine the conditions for survival
of the individual - not vice versa.
The environment of any group, such as a nation or a business corporation
or a religious sect, is partly (a) the collection of other groups and (b) the
physical universe. Putting aside variance due to size, natural resources,
etc., we shall accept here and elsewhere, from the evidence of correlations in
modern nations and of history, that nations, tribes, and other groups tend to
rank in the same order in (1) competing with other groups and (2) in their
mastery of their environment. This is not merely because mastery of the
environment gives better economic and military weapons, but because the
general intelligence that begets one tends to beget the other."
At earlier levels of evolution, when the hominid population was less
numerous, group competition was between tribes and even smaller groups, known
as bands. In he modern world, although Cattell does not ignore the any lesser
subdivisions that divide nations into smaller breeding groups, he sees the
major competing groups still as nations - possibly because nations share a
common language and a common territory or breeding ground:
"Those organized groups tend to be nations. As Sir Arthur Keith
summarizes, "Most of my colleagues regard a nation as a political unit, with
which anthropologists have no concern, whereas I regard a nation as an
'evolutionary unit' with which anthropologists ought to be greatly concerned.
The only live races in Europe today are its nations." The great size of the
nation, relative to the small familial tribes along which the evolution of
group qualities formerly took place, slows up the natural selective process,
but that is necessary to produce the "large group" characters we now need."
Technology and culture have always played a prominent role in determining
success in a conflict between hominid groups. But while both tend to be linked
to genetics, in the long term it is the genetic heritage which is the most
precious, as culture depends on its genetic base, and once the genetic base
decays so must the culture:
"....but though Man is extreme in the proportions of behavior influenced
by culture, it is a colossal mistake to ignore the genetic forces in his
culture. And as Havelock Ellis long ago reminded us, 'there is nothing so
fragile as civilization, and no high civilization has long withstood the
manifold risks it is exposed to.' The genetic survives."
Not only does civilization depend upon a sound genetic basis for its
survival, but continued technological achievement of the calibre that may be
required for the survival needs of future generations may necessitate further
genetic evolution. The problem facing the West today is that the prevailing
ethical system is blind to science, and pays no regard to evolutionary
reality. A culture can destroy a people if it loses touch with reality, and
Western ethical teaching has in general lost touch with evolutionary reality.
The ancient civilizations of early Republican Rome and early Greece, even of
the pre-Christian Germanic peoples, did reveal some comprehension of the
causal reality that governs living organisms. It was no accident that science
flourished in pre-Christian pagan Greece, when men like Archimedes,
Pythagoras, Aristotle and Plato had inquiring minds, or that all early Greeks
believed implicitly in inequality and in the superiority of genetics - of the
"blood line." But all this changed with the coming of Christianity, which
preached not only the equality of all God's children but also the moral
superiority of blind unquestioning obedience to the "revealed truths" of the
prophets as preserved by the church leaders. It was the Byzantine Christian
emperors who finally closed Plato's ancient academy, because to them even to
question Church doctrine was heresy. Cattell himself does not say all this,
but he warns against "revealed" religions and it is clear that he believes the
prevailing morality of the West is not merely scientifically irrelevant but
positively harmful. That is why he believes that the most important objective
remaining after his many distinguished accomplishments is to awaken the West,
and indeed, all humankind, to the need for ethical values to be brought into
line with the frontiers of scientific thought.
Thus, Cattell complains, contemporary Western ethical theory condemns
"inequality," and yet biological inequality is the very stuff from which
evolution is made. Clearly, the prevailing prejudice against any and all forms
of inequality (as distinct from solely legal inequality) is a threat to the
future of the West, and individually to all humankind:
"The most common rhetorical reaction to inequality is that it is "unjust."
Indeed, in much of the popular media one could easily conclude that the terms
inequality and injustice are synonymous! Here we run again on to the confusion
over "rights" discussed elsewhere. Our society today declares that all have a
right to equal opportunity, while our religions, including Beyondism, declare
that all have equal spiritual worth and rights, i.e., the rights to the
dignity of an unknown potential. Rights have to be contracts, and so far as an
individual signs himself into a state or church, his rights are to the
equalities just indicated. But biologically he has no contract to equality,
and, if we suppose some supreme being to have designed the universe, it would
seem that such rights were never intended. One has then only the right to
variation and adventure on the course of evolutionary advance.
As for the relation of inequality to injustice, some common-sense citizens
have, as we have seen, added the viewpoint that "injustice is the equal
treatment of unequals." It is clear that if we take off from the premise that
the group has, if possible, to survive, then equal treatment of unequals is
unethical. One would not spend large resources of physical education funds to
train a man of diminutive physique for the Olympic shot-put competition, or
endow university scholarships for individuals of, say, I.Q. 80 or less.
Confusion over the meanings of equality, justice, and freedom have caused
much bloodshed, and threaten all real social progress."
So what positive values does Cattell attribute to those who are concerned
with the future of mankind "beyond" the limits of their own life-span?
Essentially these are summed up in what he calls a Beyondist catechism - a
very lengthy but highly persuasive list of principles and arguments. This may
be briefly summarized as follows: Evolution is the prime process visible in
the universe, and to survive mankind must develop a strategy, a culture or an
"ethic," if you will, which is in harmony with this basic set of conditions.
Evolution proceeds by selection between individuals and between groups. A
genetic panmixia for humanity would not only be dangerous - being contrary to
evolutionary principles - it is questionable, in fact, whether it ever could
be achieved.
Groups are genetic realities and are in competition for genetic survival
and proliferation. Groups which adopt an evolutionary-positive ethic have a
far better chance than those which select an evolutionary-negative ethic - who
have no long term chance of surviving by definition. In addition, groups which
adopt a positive evolutionary ethic, and reinforce this by a strong sense of
group identity and a high level of in-group Cooperation and loyalty, have a
better chance of surviving than those which adopt the universalist ethic
characteristic of "revealed" religions.
Finally, even successful groups must still accept the idea that they must
continue to evolve, and that inequality between individuals within the group
is a biological and evolutionary reality of positive significance. Such groups
must be prepared to orient their lives according to social systems which will
reinforce the ethical priority of providing future generations with the best
possible genetic armory with which to face the unimaginable variety of
challenges which lie hidden from contemporary vision by the veils which
obscure the future.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone