Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
Eugenics: Economics for the Long Run
By Edward M. Miller, PhD This paper originally appeared in
Research in Biopolitics, Vol. 5, Steven A. Peterson and Al Somit, Eds.,
Greenwich, Connecticut; JAI Press, 1997, p. 391-416.
Paper requested for Recent Explorations in Biology and
Politics.
Al Somit & Steven A. Peterson, Ed. JAI Press
Eugenics: Economics for the Long Run
by Edward M. Miller, PhD
Department of Economics and Finance University of New Orleans
New Orleans, La. 70148 April 8, 1997
There is a simple economic argument for eugenics. Eugenics is defined as
efforts to improve the gene pool in a particular population. Standard
micro-economic theories of wages hold that a worker's wage equals the marginal
product of his working time. Much textbook discussion of his marginal product
focus on the quantities of cooperating factors: capital, land, and natural
resources which labor has to work with. However, another important determinant
is the worker's attributes and abilities. There is evidence that these are
strongly affect by his genes (see below). It follows that efforts to maximize
a nation's standard of living should try to improve its citizens' genetic
quality, especially with regard to intelligence and other economically
important traits. Improving the genetic quality of citizens calls for having
those carrying the genes for desirable traits (as evidenced by their
possession of the traits themselves) producing more than their proportionate
share of that nation's children. A secondary economic goal is to minimize the
externalities in the economy resulting from the activities of one citizen
affecting another citizen. An example would be minimizing the amounts that
must be expended on welfare for those unable to earn the socially established
minimum standard of living. Such people may be on welfare because of disease
and handicaps, because low intelligence or personality problems make it hard
to find and retain jobs, or because of drug addiction and alcoholism. Many of
these conditions have an important genetic component.
Another important externality is criminal activity. Again it is known that
from adoption studies and other sources that criminality has a significant
genetic component (Rowe & Osgood, 1984; Lynn, 1996). As a result, an eugenics
program can hope to reduce crime rates.
Notice the above arguments hold regardless of whether the intelligence of
the population is believed to rising, falling, or remaining constant. If the
intelligence is falling and expected to continue falling, it does follow that
eventually something must be done or the maintenance of a modern industrial
civilization will prove impossible. The available evidence is that those of
higher IQ (who typically have genes that make for higher IQs) are having
smaller families than those of lower IQ's (Herrenstein & Murray, 1994; Lynn,
1996; Miller, 1997a).
If a program of eugenics is to be introduced into modern countries, it will
most likely be as a byproduct of births being restricted to restrain
population growth. Thus, it will be argued below that in the long run society
is faced with a choice between having the population restrained by misery, and
having it restrained by conscious restrictions of births. Once the idea of
preventing some births is accepted, it will then be natural to discuss the
question of which births. It is then very likely that decisions will be based
at least partially on preventing the births that are most likely to result in
what that society regards as low quality citizens. This will be a eugenics
program, although as will be pointed out some of the gains may arise from
insuring that those children born are born into the families that provide
better environments.
Consequence of Unrestrained Fertility
To introduce the case for eugenics consider Diagram 1. [Not available. Ed.]
There is a simple income distribution on it with income increasing from left
to right. Also shown is a certain level of income below which people fail to
reproduce themselves. This is shown as a straight line. However, in practice
it is probably a band, with women slightly below the line having only slightly
less than two children surviving to adulthood. Women far below the line have
relatively few children surviving to adulthood. Above the line the differences
in survival to adulthood probabilities are probably small. But in the
interests of simplicity, these complexities can not be shown.
What are the conditions for long run equilibrium? The first condition is
that the population be stable. Obviously a continually growing population
eventually exceeds the resources of the earth, or of the home country. This is
not the place to get into debates about just what these limits are, or exactly
when the world as a whole or particular country will come up against these
limits. The purpose here is to show how societies will differ depending on how
the state of zero population growth is achieved, and whether it is done by
misery of the Malthusian type, or by eugenics.
It is important that the world is asymmetric, such that being far above the
line probably does less for childhood survival than being below it. The
diagram shows how with unrestrained fertility, the more unequal the income
distribution, the higher the average income. The reason is that for population
growth to be constrained by poverty to zero, there must be many below the
poverty line. A given level of misery among those whose reproduction is being
restrained by poverty is consistent with many different standards of living
for those above the line. A more unequal distribution of income permits the
average to be further above the line, consistent with any given amount of
poverty, including that amount of poverty needed to keep the population
stable.
If the distribution of income is to be completely equal, the average woman
has to be at the poverty line, such that poverty prevents her from raising
only slightly more than a single female offspring to reproductive age. It
takes extreme poverty to achieve this outcome. Even in many poor third world
countries the population is growing, and the typical woman much more than
reproduces herself.
If income becomes more unequal, it becomes possible for most of the
population to be far above the poverty line, while still allowing a high
enough fraction of the population to be far enough below the poverty line to
prevent population growth. This leads to the very unpleasant conclusion that
for a nation to enjoy a high average income is consistent with that nation
having a stable population only if that income is unevenly distributed. Only
with high inequality will enough of the population be far enough below the
poverty line to prevent population growth.
Without birth control, any attempt to raise the poor's living standard
merely increases their children's survival rates, increases the population,
and pulls the average standard of living back down. If income is redistributed
from the rich to the poor, one predictable effect is that the rich live less
well. Another is that the poor increase in number until rising misery returns
the population growth rate to zero. This rather unpleasant vision is the
standard Malthusian one.
Unfortunately, in the long run, without population control, attempts to
eliminate poverty merely increase the population and reintroduce poverty. The
obvious solution is to replace misery as a device for controlling population
growth with some other program for limiting the birth rate and stabilizing
population. While there is certainly something very intrusive about the
government acting to limit births, it seems preferable to allowing population
growth to be limited by poverty.
If there is to be some family size limitation, at least among certain
families, perhaps we should be asking what criteria should be used to decide
who should have children, and who should be prevented or discouraged from
having children?
The Role of Genes
This may be a good point to refer to the evidence that many humans traits
are strongly influenced by genes (Rowe 1994; Lynn 1996; Miller, 1997a). This
evidence come from the science of behavior genetics. The first testable
predication of a theory that variability in a trait is genetically influenced
is that the trait will run in families. However, traits can also run in
families because they are environmentally influenced, and each generation
creates for their children an environment similar to the one they themselves
were raised in. Thus, it is necessary to look for situations where
environmental theories and genetic theories make different predictions.
One such situation is in adoptions, where the environment is created by the
family of adoption, and the genes come from the biological parents. If there
is no genetic influence, there will be zero correlation between the children's
traits and those of the biological parents. To the extent the environment of
rearing is influential, the adoptee's traits will be correlated with the
family of rearing, while to the extent that genes are influential (or prenatal
conditions) it will be correlated with the family of genetic origin. Another
method is twin studies. Here findings that monozygotic twins are more alike
than dizygotic twins provides evidence of genetic effects. This is an example
of a more general effect, in which, by examining the extent to which those who
differ in genetic relationships resemble reach other, one can model the role
of genetic factors. Especially impressive are the studies of separated twins
that were raised apart. These frequently grow up to be quite similar in
personality and intelligence (Bouchard, Lykken, McGue, Segal, & Tellegen,
1990; Pederson, Plomin, McClearn, & Friberg, 1988).
Due to space limitations, this is not the place to present all the evidence
for the importance of genetic factors in intelligence and personality.
However, there is strong evidence that most traits are genetically influenced
(see for instance Rowe 1994 for summary evidence on the large number of traits
for which genetic influences have been shown). Even what appear to be social
attitudes have been shown to be affected by genes (Eaves, Eysenck, & Martin,
1989). In general, the evidence for the role of genes in so many factors
raises the possibility of controlling who bears children to influence the
traits found in succeeding generations. This makes it useful to begin to
discuss how eugenic policies might be carried out
Non-Eugenic Discouragement of Population Growth
In the short run, population growth can be restrained by encouraging
smaller families by various voluntary means. By lecturing about the dangers of
population growth and the environmental problems of a large population, some
people may be persuaded to choose smaller families. However, these are likely
to be the most responsible people. With each generation, the fraction of such
responsible people is likely to decline. There is evidence that altruism
(Rushton, 1980) is affected by genes. A voluntary program selects against such
genes. Eventually this method will fail.
Because women that have many opportunities for high prestige jobs
(professors etc.) frequently take them and choose to have few children, a
common proposal for reducing the birth rate is to increase women's access to
such jobs (Hoffman, 1975). Rhetorically this makes it easy to be both feminist
and concerned about population growth.
For instance, in America the number of children per women 35-44 (when women
have virtually completed their child bearing) is 1.6 for women with 16 years
or more of education (college graduates usually), while it is 2.6 for those
with 0-11 years of education (usually non-high school graduates), with those
with in-between levels having 1.9 children for some college, and 2.0 children
for high school graduates (Herrnstein & Murray, 1994). Presumably the college
graduates delay the start of childbearing to complete their education (which
may continue into graduate and professional school), and then frequently
choose an interesting career over staying at home for child rearing. If these
effects are caused by the education (rather than a common cause, such as a
desire for a career causing the education), it would follow that providing
more education for females would reduce population growth. If the whole
population of the world had the US pattern of female education and birthrates,
overpopulation would not be a threat.
Observations like the above lead many to argue that the solution (or at
least a major part of it) for excessive population growth is to educate women,
and to increase their opportunity to play high prestige roles in society.
Women will then choose these roles over child bearing and rearing.
However, there are problems with this policy proposal (besides the obvious
ones of whether the education is really causing the low birth rates, and how
poor countries could afford to educate their women so well).
Unfortunately, the evidence is that much of what determines whether women
will have access to high paying, high prestige jobs is genetic, notably the
genes for intelligence (Jensen 1981; Herrnstein & Murray, 1994; Seligman,
1992, Storfer, 1990). Educating women and encouraging them to take up jobs
that reduce their childbearing will work for the first few generations, but it
will gradually lower the intelligence level of the population.
Herrnstein & Murray (1994) show that the average IQ of female college
graduates was 111, versus 81 for the women who did not finish high school. The
others were in between (103 for those with some college, and 95 for high
school graduates). If we try to control population growth by encouraging the
more intelligent women to choose careers over childbearing, in the long run
the average intelligence must decline. This occurs because of the high
heritability for intelligence. Because the intelligent women usually marry
intelligent men, discouraging reproduction by intelligent women also reduces
reproduction by intelligent men. Thus, this apparently desirable method for
controlling population growth, so consistent with modern feminism, lacks long
run viability.
However, there are other problems with any voluntary method for controlling
population growth. It is likely that the drives for fatherhood or motherhood
run in families for either cultural or genetic reasons. Those with weaker
drives to be parents will be more readily persuaded to forgo parenthood.
However, efforts to persuade people to voluntarily forgo parenthood merely
assure that in the next generation will come disproportionately from those
with stronger drives for parenthood. Thus, a voluntary program will eventually
eliminate those who are easily persuaded to forgo parenthood. Those left will,
for either genetic or cultural reasons (including religious ones), be
unwilling to forgo parenthood. This is similar to the argument made above for
appealing to the citizen's altruism to limit population growth. After the
altruistic have been persuaded to limit their reproduction, and to gradually
eliminate themselves, who is left that can voluntarily be persuaded to limit
their births?
It is also true that some ethnic groups have higher birth rates than other
(most likely for cultural reasons). If these differences persist, the
mathematics insure that eventually the nation's growth rate will equal the
growth rate of its fastest growing ethnic components. To use an extreme
example, Hutterites (a sect that does not believe in birth control) may be the
fastest growing group in a nation. If other groups can be persuaded to
restrict their birth rates, given enough time the Hutterites will become any
nation's dominant group. Then that nation's population growth rate will be
that of the Hutterites.
Thus, eventually, population must stabilize and the alternatives are:
1. That this is done by restricting births by government coercion
2. This is done by poverty.
For the type of society that can result from poverty see Scheper-Hughes
(1992) description of everyday life in Northeastern Brazil. She paints a
disturbing picture in which most families live in poverty and infant mortality
is very high, high enough so that parents become reconciled to losing
children. Indeed, it appears as if they are subconsciously deciding to let
some children die of malnutrition. Yet as bad as the situation described is,
the population is still growing. The typical poor women still manages to more
than reproduce herself. A even higher degree of misery would be required to
limit population growth. Besides limiting population growth rates, there is
one other advantage to limiting family size. Right now the poorest families
are the largest (Lynn 1996: Herrenstein & Murray, 1994). Mathematically, this
implies that the percentage of the nation's children that are raised in
poverty exceeds the percentage of the adults that are poor. In the US, child
advocacy groups regularly point out the high fraction of the nation's children
who are being raised in poverty. They consistently fail to point out how
restricting the birth rates among the poor would help to solve this problem.
The effect would be partially by lowering the percentage of children who are
born into poor families. If this resulted in lowering family size among the
poor, the low income families could spread their resources out more among
their children.
Spreading the family's resources among fewer children would increase the
per child amounts not only for economic resources such as money, but also of
non-economic resources. It also permits (but does not guarantee) more parental
time per child, and more supervision, which is usually believed to be good.
For instance, it is know that children raised in large families more often
grow up to be criminals, and in mainstream criminology this is attributed to
such children receiving less parental supervision (Lynn, 1996)
Possible Eugenic Goals
If the government is to decide who is to have children, they may wish to
decide on some rational criteria, so as to improve the gene pool or to
accomplish other goals.
Admittedly, some might try to restrict population growth by an across the
board restriction, thus apparently avoiding hard decisions about who should be
allowed to reproduce. For instance, families might be somehow limited to two
or three children (China now has a limit of one). However, for a stable
population, two is too few, and three too many. In theory, one might alternate
restriction of two with those of three for different generations (two children
per family in several generations, and then a generation permitting three
children per couple to rebuild the population). Likewise, if the number
required for a stable population was 2.2, one might randomly assign certain
families to the three child category, thus avoiding having to make choices on
a rational basis. However, either of these procedures for avoiding making hard
choices seems to forgo the advantages of selectivity for little reason.
If parental time for child rearing is very important, or if most adults
want strongly to be parents, the goal might be families approximately equal in
size. Any limits would then be to two or three children per family, and the
selectivity would be limited to deciding on some basis which families would be
allowed to have three children rather than two.
If the emphasis is more on insuring that children are born with the best
possible genes, a greater degree of variability in family size might be
considered desirable. Each family might be allowed a minimum of one child to
give them the pleasures of parenthood, and possibly to provide society with
whatever benefits may result from adults being parents (more conservative
behavior among males for instance). The desired average of a little more than
two children per family could then be achieved by having the selected parents
have at least three children, and possibly more.
While different policies have implications for the percentages of the
children that have occupied different birth orders, there is not now strong
evidence that would justify preferring children of any particular birth order
(Ernst & Angst, 1983). Clearly different strategies could change the
percentage of middle children relative to first and last borns. Sulloway
(1995, 1996) has presented evidence that first born are more conservative and
later born more likely to be rebels, but it is not obvious which society
should pick when it can choose. Of course, if the goal is to provide an even
more rapid genetic improvement while still retaining traditional family
structures, those couples with the worse genetic endowment would be prevented
from reproducing. The deficit would be made up for by much larger families
among the couples with the better genes (however defined). This would require
that many of these families have four or more children. Since there is no real
evidence that large families are bad for children, this would seem to be an
acceptable alternative.
Of course, if one is willing to explore unconventional family structures
such as making more use of artificial impregnation, even where the wife has a
husband who could father her children, or where the potential mother lacks a
husband (as with single women or lesbian couples), there is scope for more
rapidly spreading desirable genes. One might even consider cloning now that
this has been shown to be possible in mammals (Specter, 1997).
Eugenic Aspects of Non-Eugenic Policies
Anything that slows the reproduction of those with genetic traits society
does not want to perpetuate may be an eugenic policy. These aspects are not
always discussed.
For instance, prison visits of wives for sexual purposes may encourage
births by those carrying genes for criminality. Yet the discussions of this
typically consist of the opponents saying that prison should be as unpleasant
as practical, and that it is inconsistent with punishment to provide sexual
access. On the other side, those in favor of conjugal visits typically argue
they help to hold marriages together, prevent the spouse from being penalized,
and perhaps help in managing the prisoners. Mention of any genetic effect
seems to be missing.
It is sometimes proposed that rapists be castrated. This is generally
proposed merely as punishment, but yet it should reduce the births of those
with personality traits (possibly poor impulse control) that lead to rape and
other crimes (for a discussion of the role of genes in rape see Ellis, 1989)..
Castration seems to work. Recidivism rates have been found to be 0 to 7.4% in
a study of 2,055 European rapists (Bradford, 1990), which is far lower than
the US recidivism rates, which have been reported to be as high as 40%. Given
that castration is likely to be far cheaper than years of imprisonment, it
might be used.
Perhaps even more effective in reducing rapes might be surgery that
prevented erections by cutting relevant nerves. This would eliminate the
reinforcing effects of fantasies accompanied by masturbation, probably
reducing the motivation for rape and other sex crimes. This is purely a
speculative proposal at this stage, but one that should be the subject of some
discussion. In principle, castration might be used for other violent crimes
also. It has the attraction of being relatively low cost. If there is a
substantial genetic basis for most crimes, and the evidence is that there is
(Lynn, 1996), castration would reduce the number of offspring left by such
criminals. If it is desirable to reduce the rate of population growth for
other reasons, as was argued above, criminals would seem to be good ones to
deprive of the benefits of fatherhood. Of course, castration of criminals
might deprive their wives or girl friends of parenthood. It is likely in many
case they would become pregnant even without artificial insemination. However,
with the availability of artificial insemination, they would be expected to
frequently choose artificial insemination rather than remaining childless. The
result would be replacing the sperm of a criminal with what could be a very
high quality sperm. Obviously that would tend to reduce the frequency of the
genes most closely related to criminal activity.
One side benefit of such a program would probably be selection against low
intelligence. It is known that arrested criminals tend to have below average
intelligence. For instance, Herrenstein & Murray (1994, p 248) found that 12%
of the male whites in the very dull category were in a correctional facility
when interviewed versus 3% for the whole sample.
Population Control via Incentives: Eugenic Aspects
There are a number of ways people might be induced to limit births that
would not involved coercion (other than to pay the taxes to finance the
programs). Most such programs would probably have an eugenic effect since
those with lower incomes or shorter time horizons would probably find any
given incentive program more attractive.
Payments for sterilization might be offered, say $5,000 or $10,000. These
sums would be attractive to those who have a weak desire to leave descendants.
Very likely such programs would select for other desirable traits such as a
tendency to weight income in the distant future less than in the present.
Banfield (1974) has argued that a greater desire for current pleasure (related
to the economist's concept of time preference) lies behind many of the inner
city problems. For instance, if one needs $20 for a date tonight the easiest
way to obtain it is to snatch someone's purse. Admittedly, repeated purse
snatching is likely to end in a jail sentence, but that is sometime in the
distant future. At a high enough interest rate, stealing the purse becomes
rational.
Likewise, drug taking brings immediate pleasure even if at the cost of
future addiction. Sex brings immediate pleasure even if the cost is unwed
motherhood, or for the father, financial responsibility for children. Watching
TV is more pleasant than studying, but studying has long run returns in higher
income. Maintaining real estate takes time, but over the long run it makes for
a more comfortable home. Saving (and forgoing use of credit) reduces current
consumption, but increases future consumption. Creating a small business often
means putting in long hours and doing without many pleasures. However,
eventually, the small business may succeed. One can imagine many such
examples. There is very little solid research on whether time preference has a
genetic basis. It is known to vary with ethnic background. For instance, in
Trinidad children of Indian descent (ancestors from India) are less willing to
accept a small piece of candy now rather than a larger piece of candy in the
future than those of African descent (Mischel & Metzer, 1962). However, since
most personality traits are strongly affected by genes with a substantial
heritability, it is very likely that the ability to defer gratification is a
trait with a genetic component.
If a desire for immediate gratification plays a role in criminality, as it
appears to (Wilson & Herrnstein, 1985), it is to be expected that restraining
the reproduction of convicted criminals would also tend to restrict the
reproduction of those with a short time preference.
It is very likely that many modern methods of birth control select for a
desire for immediate gratification. Consider for instance the simple condom.
Using this for birth control requires stopping the sequence of events (often
seduction) that lead to impregnation to put a condom on. Those who have a
strong desire for immediate gratification are much less likely to do this. The
same argument applies to inserting a diaphragm, coitus interruptus, or using
sponges. Even using birth control pills requires obtaining the pills in
advance, and remembering to take them at the right time.
A significant fraction of births represent failures of birth control (Van
Court, 1983). For the United States, the Kost & Forrest (1995) analysis of the
National Survey of Family Growth reported that 36% of births were unplanned.
For those with less than twelve years of education, 58% of the births were
unplanned versus only 27% among college graduates. Besides the obvious
dysgenetic effect on intelligence, these probably have a dysgenic effect in
that the families that who have children through birth control failure are
probably less willing to defer gratification, and have a lower ability to plan
ahead. Also, it is very likely that inability to defer gratification goes with
a lower intelligence. Incidentally, the high fraction of births that are
unplanned suggests that improved methods of birth control that are easier may
have a significant eugenic effect.
One other trait that may go with accidental pregnancies is drinking
alcohol. Many people are inhibited about sex and loosen up with alcohol (or
are plied with alcohol by their potential sex partners). Alcohol in general
lowers inhibitions. These lower inhibitions are both towards having sex, and
towards having unprotected sex. In the modern world, where most children born
are raised to sexual maturity, the fact that birth control methods are readily
available to most everyone to be used or not, may act as a selective agent for
alcohol consumption. The reason is that people who are drunk, or merely under
the influence of alcohol are less likely to use birth control, and are
therefore more leave offspring with the same propensity for alcohol
consumption. However, this desire for alcohol also goes along with alcoholism,
and this makes a mate less desirable (and intoxication can make the sex act
harder for males). Boulding (1969) has proposed transferable licenses for
child bearing, each couple to get 2.2 licenses. They could then be bought or
sold. Those who valued children most would have the larger families (probably
a good in itself). In practice, many poor people and those with short time
horizons would sell their licenses for the money. This would have a desirable
eugenic effect. Barry (1969) has proposed payments for potential parents who
have no more than two children, such payments to be proportional to income. He
bases the proposal to make the payments proportional to income on a desire to
have the upper and middle classes restrict their fertility as much as the
lower classes. His rationale for trying to restrict fertility as much in the
upper and middle classes is to maintain the opportunity for upward mobility
for the poor. Interestingly, this paper, although appearing in a journal
stating on the cover that is was formerly the Eugenics Quarterly, displays no
awareness that restriction of fertility among the lower classes would increase
the genetic quality of the population. However, his explicit rationale for
trying to avoid disproportionate fertility restriction among the lower classes
does point out a possible disadvantage to eugenics programs. If fertility is
disproportionately restricted among the lower classes as a successful eugenics
program would do, there is likely to be more social downward mobility, with
more of the population feeling they were ranked lower than their parents (and
they will be correct). If moving downwards in the social hierarchy makes
people feel bad (and it does), this is a disadvantage to an eugenics program.
Any plan that offers large sums of cash for sterilization, or for
restricting child bearing, would reduce the birth rates most among those with
a strong desire for current consumption. Such large cash payments would be
especially attractive to drug addicts who often need money to purchase drugs.
There could be expected to be effects on future rates of drug abuse from such
an eugenics program.
If it were politically possible, one might even trade drugs for
sterilization or implantation of a birth control device, or at least provide
enough drugs so that there would not be withdrawal problems around the time of
the sterilization. Since crack, alcohol, (and probably other drugs) affect the
fetus, there would be strong social savings if these addicted women could be
prevented from having children. It could also slow down the spread of AIDS,
which is frequently transmitted from mother to child. Notice that such
benefits are environmental in nature.
Welfare and Birth Control
An obvious idea is to tie the receipt of welfare to using a drug which
prevents having additional children while on welfare, such as Norplant. Given
the correlation of being on welfare with low intelligence, and probably with
other undesirable genetic traits, such a proposal would improve the nation's
genetic stock. Given the difficulty of knowing whether promises to use birth
control are being observed, tying receipt of welfare to using most methods of
birth control is probably infeasible. Penalizing mothers for having babies
after they promised not to would either end up penalizing the children, or
force the mothers into having abortions.
It is to be expected that any measure that reduces the pool of low IQ,
uneducated individuals would reduce the competition for the jobs such people
can do. Such a program should reduce the unemployment rate, and raise incomes
among the low IQ part of the population.
The final outcome of such birth control would be to reduce inequalities by
two mechanisms.
1 Reducing the number of those with traits leading to low income (low IQ,
short time preference, etc.) in the society. This raises the weighted average
skill level.
2. By raising the wages rates for unskilled labor. It is a standard
prediction of economic models that reducing the supply raising the price. It
follows that reducing the supply of low wage labor would raise the wage rates
for such services.
Public support
Although the word eugenics is very unpopular among intellectuals, there may
not be as much opposition among the ordinary voters.
One Texas legislator in an informal poll found 3,533 to 2,604 in favor of
sterilization for welfare moms with 3 or more children. (Reilly, 1991, p.161).
The Boston Globe found, in a call in telephone poll, that 49% supported
sterilization of the mentally ill.
China has apparently adopted a sterilization law targeting mentally
retarded parents in one province (Reilly, 1994, p. 164). While China is
politically quite different from the United States, this still shows that such
actions may be possible.
Singapore has announced eugenic programs aimed at promoting births by the
better educated (Chan, 1987), and in particular by graduate women. There was
also announced a program to reward low income families under 30 with less than
two children for being sterilized with US$4,000 as a down payment for a
government low cost apartment.
Arguments Against Eugenics
Of course, there are arguments against eugenics programs. Government power
over private citizen's lives is always subject to abuse. So history teaches.
US state run programs seem to have had problems with some sterilizations that
were not for good eugenic reasons (Reilly, 1991). Any government program is
going to make numerous mistakes and possibly suffer from some corruption.
Certainly it has not always been known which traits were genetically
influenced, and there were some sterilizations done under the various laws
that probably do not contribute to improving the genetic stock. For instance,
there is a case of a woman who was the offspring of incest, but apparently
otherwise unhandicapped, being sterilized.
Currently, we are far from having much knowledge of which genes influence
particular traits, or from knowing all the traits that are subject to genetic
influences. If we were given complete copies of the genetic sequences for two
individuals we could not tell which one we preferred. That is true. However,
such a high level of knowledge is not needed for a useful eugenics program. It
is generally known that many traits are genetically influenced (see above) and
people generally agree on which direction is good. For instance:
1. High intelligence is good.
2. Self control is good.
3. Criminality and rape are bad.
4. Most diseases are bad.
The above provides a basis for deciding whose reproduction to encourage. At
this point we could proceed with a start on programs, hoping to improve
knowledge in the future.
One theoretical concern is that many traits may be influenced by pleitropic
genes such that selecting for a desirable trait also selects for another trait
that is undesirable. Thus there could be unintended consequences from an
eugenics program.
To illustrate the type of problem that is theoretically possible consider
myopia. This is widely considered to be a genetically influenced condition. It
is known to run in families, and twin studies show it to have a high degree of
heritability (Curtin 1985). However, it is also known that high intelligence
and myopia go together (Teasdale, Fuchs, & Goldschmidt, 1988; Rosner & Belkin
1987; Benbow & Benbow 1984, p. 484 and 1986). High intelligence is also known
to be a partially genetic trait. The evidence is that the two genetic traits
are pleitropic, with one gene affecting both (Cohn, Cohn, & Jensen, 1988). One
possibility is that the close work that results from reading and studying
leads to myopia. Another, which the writer has proposed, is that a single gene
(or gene complex) affects both brain size and the size of the eyeball (which
is embryologically derived from the same tissue as the brain) and this
produces the correlation (Miller 1992, 1996d).
Now, if someone tried to discourage those with myopia from reproducing, a
byproduct would be selection for lower intelligence. This would be
unfortunate, since myopia is relatively easily handled with corrective
glasses. Of course, enough is known so that the above mistake appears
unlikely. About the only way it could be made would be for a version of
political correctness to make selection for intelligence impossible, while
selection against genetic disease related conditions was promoted.
A slightly more difficult problem is the possibility that genes that
promote certain forms of mental illness are also genes that contribute to
genius or originality. There is some evidence for this proposition (Eysenck
1995; Goodwin & Jamieson, 1990; Karlsson, 1991). Efforts to discourage
reproduction by those with manic-depressive illness or schizophrenia, both of
which have been shown to have a genetic component in twin studies, might
produce adverse effects on creativity.
One can also imagine other unanticipated genetic problems. Many
polymorphisms are believed to protect against one disease but to increase
vulnerability against another. They survive in the population over the long
run because whenever a particular allele become more common, the diseases it
makes for vulnerability to become more common, and the allele making for
vulnerability is selected against.
It must be admitted there is a chance that this could happen. If we knew
that a particular allele made for vulnerability to a particular
well-publicized disease, say AIDS, there might be pressure to discourage
reproduction by carriers of such an allele. Indeed, a mutation that appears to
protect against AIDS has been recently found (Kolata, 1996). This could
increase vulnerability to another disease where the effect was not known, or
just possibly a new disease would then emerge that could then spread more
rapidly. It is also conceivable that a gene for a desirable trait may also
increase vulnerability to a disease.
Another theoretical argument that is sometimes heard is that genetic
diversity is needed for further evolution and that eugenic programs might
reduce this diversity, eliminating a desirable allele. The analogy is
sometimes made with certain crops where the genetic diversity may have been
greatly reduced, increasing the vulnerability to certain diseases.
However, in any one generation any realistic program will make only minor
changes in the gene pool. This will give plenty of time to reverse direction
if unintended consequences emerge. Desirable genes are unlikely to be
eliminated from the gene pool by a feasible short-term eugenics programs. Any
appreciable reduction in diversity is so far in the future that little concern
is needed for now.
Eugenics when the Problem is Partially Environmental in Origin
Frequently those who object to eugenics programs to reduce births in
families suffering from a particular problem assert that the targeted social
problem is environmental in origin. For instance, if it is proposed to raise
average intelligence levels by reducing the number borne to parents with low
intelligence, it may be argued that low intelligence is of environmental
origin. It is definitely true that there is an environmental component to most
social problems, including low intelligence and poverty.
However, it does not follow that eugenics programs cannot reduce problems
caused by social causes. Whenever a problem is known to run in families,
reducing the number of children in families with the problem should reduce any
problem's incidence. Suppose low intelligence was caused by a unknown type of
bad parenting that was in certain families, with each child as an adult
copying its own parents' bad parenting. Increasing the fraction of children in
the families that practiced good parenting (which might be determined by the
parents themselves being of high intelligence) would still increase
intelligence in the next generation. An environmentally caused problem whose
exact mechanism is unknown can be handled by decreasing the fraction of births
in certain families, just as a genetically caused problem can be handled. In
most cases the policy implications of environmentally and genetically caused
low IQ are the same as far as who is encouraged to have children. The key
question for predicting the effects of a program is the correlation between
the IQ's of parents and children. Knowing the causes of this correlation is
not critical. There are a few cases of low IQ known to be due to environmental
causes (say an accident that injured the brain) where there would be no
eugenic objection having children. However, such cases are rare. Even in these
cases, one might feel that it was best for the child not to have a low IQ
parent and wish to discourage childbearing.
Eugenic programs that work by manipulating family size can be expected to
work, although slowly and over a period of generations. If there are
unrecognized environmental factors being transmitted from parents to children,
such programs will also increase the percentage of children exposed to such
positive environmental effects.
Westman (1994), convinced that bad parenting leads to most problems has
written a book which proposes licensing parents. Some of his proposals would
probably end up having eugenic effects. Those who could not get licensed as
parents would probably be of genetically low intelligence, and the proposal
would end up having positive eugenic effects.
Admittedly, if it were known that there existed a particular environmental
factor that affected intelligence, an obvious alternative would be to deal
directly with the factor. For instance, if it turned out that rocking children
to sleep promoted intelligence (the reference is to speculations in Storfer
1990), it would still be true that we could increase the percentage of
intelligent children in the next generation by encouraging parents who were
intelligent (who had probably been rocked to sleep themselves). Even more
efficient would be to encourage those who planned to rock children to sleep to
have large families. Of course, if we did have knowledge that such a simple
intervention raised intelligence, we would not choose to exploit it by
manipulating family size depending on their proclivity to rock children to
sleep. Instead we would have a program to teach mothers to rock their children
to sleep, or perhaps we would discover that mothers themselves had already
read the research results and were rocking their children to sleep.
However, as of now we know of few environmental interventions that do much
for children's intelligence, or that improve other aspects of their
personality. Spitz (1986) has traced the history of efforts to raise
intelligence by environmental means. There is a long series of episodes in
which some intervention was proposed, received much favorable publicity, and
was then found to have little permanent effect. The most recent such episode
has involved early childhood programs of the Head Start type. These were found
to temporarily raise intelligence scores. However, once removed from the
program the children were found to gradually return to the low level of
performance of those who had never been in such programs.
That there is little hope for environmental manipulation in raising IQ is
shown by adoption studies in which even the intervention of putting children
into whole new environments seems to have little effect on their adult
intellectual performance, although some effect on childhood performance is
seen. For instance, Loehlin, Horn, & Willerman (1989) found that unrelated
adopted siblings, when tested at 13-24 years of age, had essentially no
resemblance to each other (r=-.01). Scarr and Weinberg (1978) studied children
aged between 16 and 22 in adopted and biological families. In the adopted
families the correlations were .16 between adopted father and child, .09
between mother and child, and -.03 between siblings. Children who were raised
from infancy together differ as much as unrelated pairs of children. This
provides powerful evidence that the environment of rearing has little impact
on adult intelligence. If the massive intervention of changing the family of
rearing (which also affects things like schooling) has little impact, the
chances seem small that more modest interventions that affect only schooling,
housing, health, or a similar variable will have much impact.
The same study showed correlations between siblings of .35 when raised in
biological families, and .40 between father and child, and .41 between mother
and child. Since it was argued above that the family of rearing had relatively
little impact, most of these similarities must be because parents, children,
and sibling share genes. This, of course, is evidence for genetic effects.
However, regardless of what is causing the resemblance between parents and
children in biological families (which are the vast majority of families), the
fact of such resemblance suggests that increasing the percentage of children
borne into high IQ families will raise the intelligence of the next
generation. One should not hope for a massive rate of improvement, but the
potential for improvement is there.
It is here that one finds the chief political problem with eugenic
programs. At best one can hope for only slow increase in the frequency of
genes for a trait. If a politician is looking for something he can announce
that will plausibly make a difference by the next election, or even by when he
retires, eugenic programs will seldom appeal. Given the ease of confusing
correlation with causation, and the large number of variables that can be
correlated with social outcome variables, there will virtually always be some
intervention that can be plausibly argued to have the potential for having a
quicker impact. Some may even be plausibly claimed to capable of solving the
problem, eliminating the need for a eugenics program. Since there is usually
significant prestige and money associated with sponsoring such an
intervention, there can be expected to be partisans for one or more such
interventions arguing for them. For a politician looking for a program he can
announce that will plausibly be dealing with a serious social problem, there
will usually be several candidate programs supported with at least
correlational evidence (even if no one has yet done a well controlled
intervention study).
How are such partisans to be defeated, or how is one going to determine
whether they should be defeated (since there is a small chance that one of
their interventions will indeed prove very effective)? It is probably wise to
press for actual experimental evidence (from studies with adequate controls)
that such programs work. A problem is that partisans are likely to be so
convinced that their programs work that they will argue that it is unethical
to deprive some citizens of the program in order to provide a control group.
Yet this must be done if we are to know which, if any, interventions work.
When the interventions take the form of providing poorer children with what
the educated prosperous families already enjoy, the evidence from the low
correlations of adopted children with siblings can be used to suggest the
programs will not work. Eugenic type programs are unlikely to be adopted
because of arguments that they are solutions for social problems. They work
too slowly to be attractive for this alone. They are likely to be adopted when
there is agreement that birth rates are too high, and that some will have to
forgo child bearing. This then forces consideration of the question of who
should forgo childbearing. One can then argue that the parents which do not
exhibit the traits that society values, and (who are likely to be carrying
undesirable genes), are those that should forgo child bearing.
The biggest political problem with eugenics now is its association with
Nazi Germany and the claim that the extermination of the Jews was part of
their eugenics program (see Kuhl, 1994). While there is not space here for a
full answer, it appears the Nazi Anti-Semitism was why they tried to
exterminate the Jews (see Saetz, 1985). Given the strength of that drive, the
outcome would have been the same regardless of their views on eugenics.
The Racial Obstacle
The other major political problem is that desirable genes are distributed
unequally among the racial groups, as is the socioeconomic status and
phenotypic traits that would be used as surrogates for the possession of
desirable traits. The trait that is most economically important is
intelligence (Herrenstein and Murray, 1994; Seligman 1992). There is no real
dispute that races differ in measured intelligence, and not much dispute among
experts on intelligence that the difference is real in the sense that it is
reflected in unequal school and job performance. There is more debate as to
what causes it. Even in the 1980's the experts were divided three to one in
favor of explaning for black/white differences in IQ by both genetic and
environmental causes (Snyderman and Rothman, 1988).
Perhaps the most powerful evidence for a difference in the frequency of
genes affecting intelligence is provided by the outcomes of the experiment of
adopting black children into white households, where at age 17 the gap between
black and white adoptees was approximately that which is found when children
of each race are raised in families of their own race (Levin, 1994; Lynn,
1994). Among the recent pieces of evidence that at least part of the racial
difference is genetic is the Jensen & Johnson finding (1994) that the
black/white difference in head size in children disappeared when intelligence
was controlled for. Jensen (1994) also found that the extent of the g loading
on a test (roughly how well the test measures only intelligence) was
significantly related to the correlation of the test with head size.
There are numerous other reasons for believing that the genes affecting
many socially important traits differ in frequency between the races (Miller
1994b, c, d, 1995a, b, 1996a, b, 1997b, 1997c; Rushton 1995).
It follows that any eugenics program in the United States that does not
contain special provisions for blacks will restrict the reproduction of blacks
more than it does of whites. In the current environment, such a program would
be denounced strongly as racist. This alone would prevent such a program from
being adapted. Of course, programs could be designed to provide quotas for
different racial groups, or to make other special provisions. On the other
hand, if the program offers voluntary payments for sterilizations or for
having Norplant inserted, blacks and other low income groups would receive a
disproportionate proportion of the financial incentives. However, this is
unlikely to keep the current black leadership from objecting vehemently to
such programs.
Forces for Eugenics
However, in the developed world of the US, Europe, and Japan there does not
seem to be the compelling need to restrict family sizes. Birth rates are near,
and often below, that needed to keep the population from growing. In these
circumstances, the power elites will see eugenic programs as restricting their
freedoms and are unlikely to be supportive. This leaves one with the somewhat
pessimistic conclusion that a slow deterioration in the genetic quality of the
developed world's population is likely to continue. What could change this?
Probably the most likely thing to change is the state of scientific knowledge.
As time passes, more and more knowledge of genetics accumulates. More
importantly, the molecular genetics revolution makes it likely that someday
the working of the relevant genes will be discovered at the molecular level.
It is also possible that the biology behind intelligence and certain forms of
behavior will come to be understood well enough so that it will seem very
plausible that genes are determinative.
For instance, Tu & Israel (1995) have found that alcohol consumption by
Orientals in North America is predicted largely by a single gene. Berman &
Noble (1995) have found reduced visuospatial performance in children with the
D2 dopamine receptor A1 allele. Plomin et al (1995) have found evidence for
genetic markers being related to IQ. Skuder et al (1995) have found evidence
for a polymorphism in mitochondrial DNA that is associated with IQ. Reed et
al. (1995) have shown lower cognitive performance in normal older adult male
twins carrying the apolipoprotein E*4 allele. The apolipoprotein E*4 allele
(Kamboh, 1995) is known to increase susceptibility to Alzheimer's disease.
Keltikangas-Jarvinen, Raikkonen & Ki (1993) have shown apolipoprotein E
phenotypes affect temperament in children, adolescents, and young adults.
Bertilsson et al (1989) have shown that there are personality differences that
correspond to differences in Debrisoquine hydroxylation (a genetic
difference). Lesch et al (1996) have very recently presented evidence that
differences in a gene affecting the regulation of serotonin affects anxiety.
As findings of this type accumulate, it will be easier for the public to
accept the idea that genes affect behavior. As another example, the author has
put forward a theory in which intelligence depends on the extent of
myelination (Miller 1994a, 1996c). The theory is supported by extensive
empirical analysis and explains a wide variety of facts. It is also
empirically testable by directly measuring the amount of myelin after death
for the more intelligent, and comparing it with the amounts found in the less
intelligent brains. Likewise, there is now a large literature showing that
brain size (and head size as a proxy for brain size) is correlated with
intelligence (Miller, 1992; Rushton & Ankney, 1996; Wickett, Vernon, & Lee,
1994; Willerman, Schultz, Rutledge, & Bigler, 1991). As such evidence becomes
better accepted, more people will find it easy to believe that such variables
as brain size or myelination are subject to strong genetic effects. Hopefully,
this in turn will make it easier to accept that intelligence is itself
genetically influenced. For those that doubt that brain size has substantial
heritability there is already evidence that head size has substantial
heritability (Rushton & Osborne, 1995).
Another possibility is that technology may make some types of eugenics more
feasible, and they become popular. Modern fertility enhancing technology is
expensive and is primarily used by families of high income who badly want a
child. Thus it probably has some eugenic effects.
Artificial insemination has a potential for being used for eugenic
purposes. In many couples where the male has inadequate quantity or quality of
sperm, the couple chooses to use artificial insemination in order to have
children. There is probably some positive eugenic effect in the current
sources of sperm since many are reported to be near universities or medical
schools where the population would be of above average intelligence. However,
while great care is taken to screen donors for genetic diseases and for
sexually transmitted diseases, it is not now customary to use an intelligence
test to select donors of high intelligence, although such tests would be easy
to administer. Yet given the willingness of parents to pay for expensive
college educations for their children, it would surely seem worthwhile for the
potential parents to pay the slightly higher costs of higher quality sperm.
The costs would be slightly higher because not only would there be the cost of
testing, but it would probably be necessary to pay more to donors in order to
have a larger pool to select from. However, the cost would still be minor in
relation to the total cost of conceiving and rearing a child. If well-heeled
parents seek the best designer jeans for their offspring, why shouldn't they
seek the best genes? However, one sperm bank has received considerable
publicity by seeking high quality, intelligent donor, originally Nobel prize
winners. (See Grahm, 1983) There is no reason other sperm banks could not
adopt similar methods. Since one sperm donation can supply several
inseminations and donors can be expected to donate repeatedly, the cost of
seeking high quality donors would be low. In spite of the apparently very high
benefit-cost ratio from selecting sperm on the basis of the donors
intelligence, an Italian doctors group has decided that there should be no
selection of sperm based on the social, economic or professional standing of
the donor (Montalbano, 1995). Yet, these are all cheaply ascertained
surrogates for intelligence, and other genetic traits that contribute to
obtaining high social and professional standing.
Should Lesbians or single women become mothers by artificial insemination?
If the sperm used is of high quality, it is very likely that the offspring
will be of high intelligence, and unlikely that they will become public
burdens. Should post-menopausal women have babies using advanced technology
and their husbands sperm, as a 62 year old women recently did in Italy
(Montalbano, 1995). Given the high cost of such technologies, it is very
likely that their husbands had genes for high intelligence. Yet this measure
was to be banned by the new Italian doctors code, as was artificial
insemination after a partner's death . More speculatively, it is now feasible
to fertilize a woman's egg outside of the womb and then implant it. Right now
the procedure is used only for couples who would otherwise be infertile. One
can imagine a time when the wealthier couples have potential embryos checked
for genetic problems, or perhaps have several embryos fertilized and then
select the one for implantation that appears genetically the best.
Mammalian cloning has been shown to be possible, and if applied to humans
will probably involve the cloning of high IQ individuals, even if the basis
for choosing an individual to clone is something else (being the dictator, or
having extraordinary talents in certain areas).
It is also conceivable that selective abortion might be used to avoid
bearing children that carry what are considered undesirable combinations of
genes. This is done to a limited extent now for Downs syndrome and certain
other genetic conditions. If such expensive procedures are adapted they may be
adapted by the wealthier couples rather than the poorer ones.
A factor that could lead to eugenics programs is that the power elite is
likely to have the genes that we would like to encourage. This elite will be
very receptive to rationalizations that will permit those who wish for large
families to have them. A rule that exempted those of high IQ from family size
restrictions would virtually always exempt the elite (politicians, executives,
professors, union leaders, army officers etc.) from family size restrictions.
Likewise, programs that discourage those convicted of crimes (or suffering
from alcoholism or drug abuse) from having children are unlikely to impact
heavily on the ruling classes. If circumstances emerge where nationwide family
size restriction is desirable, eugenics may come to provide the rationale for
the rule makers to exempt themselves from the rules.
Conclusions
There is sufficient knowledge now about the importance of genetic factors
to indicate that, over time, income could be raised by eugenics. Such a
program is not politically feasible now, but someday it may be, especially
when overpopulation makes it necessary to restrict births. Eugenics may then
become popular among the ruling classes because it provides a rationale for
exempting them from the restrictions that would otherwise apply.
In practice, eugenics programs may take the form of trying to reallocate
child bearing from families with undesirable traits to families with desirable
traits. This should increase for the next generation the proportion of the
population with desirable traits. Although such programs are traditionally
referred to as eugenics programs (i.e. ones to improve the population
genetically), such programs can be expected to work for traits transmitted
within families from parents to children regardless of whether such
transmission is by genetic means or by other means. All that is necessary to
predict the success of such programs is to know the correlation to be expected
between parental traits and those of the offspring, information that is
already available for many traits.
Even when the degree of political support for direct eugenic measures is
weak (say only 20% of the population would vote for them) consideration of the
eugenic effects of alternative ways of accomplishing certain goals might
change the ranking of alternative methods for accomplishing these goals, and
produce some eugenic benefits.
References
Banfield, E. C. (1974). The Unheavenly City Revisited. Boston: Little
Brown.
Barry, L. D. (1969). Population policy: Payments for fertility limitation
in the United States. Social Biology, 16, 239-248.
Benbow, C. P. & Benbow, R. M. (1984). Biological correlates of high
mathematical reasoning ability, In G. J. De Vries (Ed.), Progress in Brain
Research, Vol. 61. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers.
Benbow, C. P. & Benbow, R. M. (1986). Physiological correlates of extreme
intellectual precocity. Mensa Research Journal, 21 , 54-87.
Bertilsson, L.; Alm, C., de Las Carreras, C., Widen, J., Edman, G,
Schalling, D. (1989). Debrisoquine hydroxylation polymorphism and personality.
Lancet I, 555.
Berman, S. M. & Noble, E. P. (1995). Reduced visuospatial performance in
children with the D2 dopamine receptor A1 allele, Behavior Genetics, 25,
45-58.
Bouchard, T. J., Lykken, D. T., McGue, M, Segal, N. L. & Tellegen, A.
(1990). Sources of human pyschological differences: The Minnesota study of
twins reared apart. Science, 250, 223-228.
Boulding, G. K. (1969). Marketable licenses for babies, in Hardin, G. (Ed.)
Population Evaluation and Birth Control. San Francisco, W. H. Freeman as cited
in Chadwick, R. F. (Ed) Ethics, Reproduction and Genetic Control, p. 181.
Bradford, J. (1990). The antiandrogen and hormonal treatment of sex
offenders. In W. Marshal, D. Laws, & H. Barbaree (Eds.), Handbook of Sexual
Assault: Issues, theories, and treatment of offenders. Pp 297-310. New York:
Plenum.
Chan, C . K. (1987). Eugenics on the rise: A report from Singapore. in
Chadwick, R. F. (Ed) Ethics, Reproduction and Genetic Control, pp. 164-171.
Cohn, S. J. Cohn, C. M. G. & Jensen, A. R. (1988). Myopia and intelligence,
a pleiotropic relationship. Human Genetics, 80, 53-58.
Curtin, B. J. (1985). The Myopias, Philadelphia: Harper & Row.
Eaves, L. J., Eysenck, H. J. & Martin, N. G. (1989). Genes, Culture, and
Personality. London: Academic Press.
Ellis, L. (1989). Theories of Rape. New York: Hemisphere Publishing.
Ernst, C. & Angst, J. (1983). Birth Order: its Influence on Personality.
New York: Springer-Verlag.
Eysenck, H. J. (1995). Genius : The Natural History of Creativity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goodwin, F. K. & Jamieson, K. R. (1990). Manic-depressive Illness. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Graham, R. K. (1983). Interview with Robert K. Graham on The Repository for
Germinal Choice. The Eugenics Bulletin, Winter, 1983, 1-11. Future Generations
site www.eugenics.net
Herrnstein, R. J. & Murray, C. (1994). The Bell Curve: Intelligence and
Class Structure in American Life, New York: The Free Press.
Hoffman, L. W. (1975). The employment of women, education and fertility. In
Mednick. M., Tangri, S., & Hoffman, L. (Eds). Women and Achievement: Social
and Motivational Analyses. Washington, Hemisphere Publishing.
Jensen, A. R. (1994). Psychometric g related to differences in head size,
Personality and Individual Differences, 17, 597-606.
Jensen, A. R. & Johnson, F. W. (1994). Race and sex differences in head
size and IQ, Intelligence, 18, 309-333.
Kamboh, M. I. (1995). Apolipoprotein E polymorphism and susceptibiity to
Alzheimer's disease, Human Biology, 67, 195-215.
Karlsson, J.L. (1991). Genetics of Human Mentality. New York: Praeger.
Keltikangas-Jarvinen, L., K. Raikkonen, & T. L. Ki (1993). Dependence between
apolipoprotein E phenotypes and temperament in children, adolescents, and
young adults. Psychosomatic Medicine, 55, 155-163.
Kolata, G. (1996). Gene mutations may once have warded off diseases. New
York Times, December 3, 1996.
Kost, K. & Forrest, J. D. (1995). Intention status of U.S. births in 1988:
differences by mothers' socio-economic and demographic characteristics. Family
Planning Perspectives, 27,11-17.
Kuhl, S. (1994). The Nazi Connection: Eugenics, American Racism, and German
National Socialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lesch, K., Bengel, D., Heils, A.,Sabol, S., Greenberg, B. D., Petri, S.,
Benjamin, J. (1996)Association of anxiety-related traits with a polymorphism
in the serotonin transporter gene regulatory region. Science 274, 1527-1531.
Loehlin, J. C., Horn, J. M., & Willerman, L. (1989). Modeling IQ changes:
Evidence from the Texas adoption project. Child Development, 60, 993-1004.
Levin, M. (1994). Comment on the Minnesota transracial adoption study.
Intelligence, 19, 13-20.
Lynn, R. (1994). Some reinterpretation of the Minnesota transracial
adoption study. Intelligence, 19, 21-28.
Lynn, R. (1996). Dysgenics: Genetic Deterioration in Modern Populations,
Westport: Praeger.
Miller, E. M, (1992). On the correlation of myopia and intelligence,
Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs, 118, No. 4, , 363-383.
Miller, E. M. (1994a). Intelligence and brain myelination: A hypothesis,
Personality and Individual Differences,17, 803-833.
Miller, E. M. (1994b). Paternal provisioning versus mate seeking in human
populations, Personality and Individual Differences, 17:2, 227-255.
Miller, E. M. (1994c). The Relevance of group membership for personnel
selection: A demonstration using Bayes theorem, Journal of Social, Political,
and Economic Studies, 19:3, 323-359.
Miller, E. M. (1994d). Tracing the Genetic History of Modern Man. Mankind
Quarterly, 35. 71-108.
Miller, E. M. (1995a). Environmental variability selects for large families
only in special circumstances: Another objection to differential K theory,
Personality and Individual Differences, 19:6, 903-918.
Miller, E. M. (1995b). Race, socioeconomic variables, and intelligence: A
review and extension of the bell curve, Mankind Quarterly, 35:3, 267-291.
Miller, E. M. (1996a). The Evolution of Australian and Amerindian
Intelligence, Mankind Quarterly, 37, 149-186.
Miller, E. M. (1996b). BackFire: A Review and Extension, Journal of Social,
Political, and Economic Studies, 21, 477-491.
Miller, E. M. (1996c). Intelligence and myelination, Mensa Research
Journal, 38, 6-54.
Miller, E. M. (1996d). Myopia and intelligence, Mensa Research Journal, 38,
55-75.
Miller, E. M. (1997a). Income, intelligence, social class, and fertility,
Journal of Social, Political, and Economic Studies, Vol. 22 (Spring 1997) No
1, 95-117.
Miller, E. M. (1997b). "Out of Africa": Neanderthals and Caucasoids?
Mankind Quarterly. 37:3, 231- .
Miller, E. M. (1997c). Race, intelligence, and income. In Leading Essays in
Afro-American Studies, edited by Nikongo BaNikongo. Carolina Academic Press,
1997.
Mischel, W. & Metzer, R. (1962). Preference for delayed reward as a
function of age, intelligence, and length of delay interval, Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 64, 425-431.
Montalbano, W. D. (1995). Code of ethics given to fertility doctors.
Times-Picayune, April 17, 2.
Pederson, N. L., Plomin, R., McClearn, G. E., & Friberg, L. (1988).
Neuroticism, extraversion, and related traits in adult twins reared apart and
together. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 55, 950-957.
Plomin, R., G. McClearn, D. Smith, P. Skuder, S. Vignetti, M. Chorney, K.
Chorney, S. Kasarda, L. Thompson, D. Detterman, S. Petrill, J. Daniels, M.
Owen, & P. McGuffin (1995). Allelic associations between 100 DNA markers and
high versus low IQ, Intelligence, 21, 31-48.
Reed, T. et al. (1995). Lower cognitive performance in normal older adult
male twins carrying the apolipoprotein E e4 allele, Archives of Neurology, 51,
1189-1192.
Reilly, P. R. (1991). The Surgical Solution: A History of Involuntary
Sterilization in the United States. Baltimore: John Hopkins.
Rosner, M. & Belkin, M. (1987). Intelligence, education, and myopia in
males. Archives of Opthalmology, 105 1508-1511.
Rowe, D. C. (1994). The Limits of Family Influence. New York: Guilford
Press.
Rowe, D. C. & Osgood (1984). Sociological theories of deliquency and
heredity: A reconsideration. American Sociological Review, 49, 526-540.
Rushton, J. P. (1980). Altruism, Socialization, and Society, Englewood
Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
Rushton, J. P. (1995). Race, Evolution and Behavior: A Life History
Perspective. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Rushton, J. P. & Ankney, C.D. (1996) Brain size and cognitive ability:
Correlations with age, sex, social class, and race. Psychonomic Bulletin and
Review, 3, 21-36.
Rushton, J. P. & Osborne, R. T. (1995). Genetic and environmental
contributions to cranial capacity in black and white adolescents. Intelligence
20, 1-13.
Saetz, S. B. (1985). Eugenics and the Third Reich. The Eugenics Bulletin,
Winter 1985, p. 1-31, found at the Future Generations website.
www.eugenics.net
Scarr, S., & Weinberg, R. A. (1978). The influence of "family background"
on intellectual attainment. American Sociological Review, 43, 674-692.
Scheper-Hughes (1992). Death Without Weeping: The Violence of Everyday Life
in Brazil. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Seligman, D. (1992). A Question of Intelligence. New York: Birch Lane
Press.
Skuder, P., Plomin, R., McClearn, G., Smith, D.,Vignetti, S., Chorney, M.,
Chorney, K., Kasarda, S., Thompson, L., Detterman, D., Petrill, S., Daniels,
J., Owen, M., & McGuffin, P. (1995). A polymorphism in mitochondrial DNA
associated with IQ? Intelligence, 21, 1-12.
Snyderman, M. and Rothman, S. (1988). The IQ Controversy, the Media and
Public Policy. New Brunswick, Transaction Books.
Specter, M. (1997). After decades and many missteps, cloning success. New
York Times, March 3, Sec. A, p.1.
Spitz, H. H. (1986). The Raising of Intelligence: A Selected History of
Attempts to Raise Retarded Intelligence. Hillsdale, N. J.: Erlbaum.
Storfer, M. D. (1990). Intelligence and Giftedness, San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Sulloway, F. J. (1995). Birth order and evolutionary psychology: A
meta-analytic overview. Psychological Inquiry, 6, 75-80.
Sulloway, F. J. (1996). Born to Rebel: How Sibling Rivalry Fosters
Revolutionary Genius. Pantheon, NY.
Teasdale, T. W., Fuchs, J. & Goldschmidt, E. (1988). Degree of myopia in
relation to intelligence and educational level. The Lancet, 1351-1353.
Tu, G. & Israel, Y. (1995). Alcohol consumption by Orientals in North
America is predicted largely by a single gene. Behavior Genetics, 25, 59-65.
Van Court, M. (1983). Unwanted births and dysgenic reproduction in the
United States. The Eugenics Bulletin, Spring, 1983, 8-16. Available at Future
Generations website www.eugenics.net
Wickett, J. C., Vernon, P. A. & Lee, D. H. (1994). In vivo brain size, head
perimeter, and intelligence in a sample of healthy adult females. Personality
and Individual Differences, 16, 831-838.
Willerman, L., Schultz, R., Rutledge, J. N. & Bigler, E. D. (1991). In vivo
brain size and intelligence. Intelligence, 15, 223-228.
Westman, J. C. (1994). Licensing Parents. New York: Insight Books.
Wilson, J. Q. & Herrnstein, R. J. (1985). Crime and Human Nature. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone