Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
The Bell Curve and its Critics
Charles Murray Commentary, May 1995 v99 n5 p23(8)
Summary: 'The Bell Curve' has been subjected to a great deal of harsh
criticism, but much of that criticism will likely lead to social research that
will validate the research published in the book. Critics who assert that no
valid single measure of intelligence exists are dismissed as unscholarly.
In November 1989, Richard Herrnstein and I agreed to collaborate on a book
that, five years later, became The Bell Curve. It is a book about events at
the two ends of the distribution of intelligence that are profoundly affecting
American life. At one extreme, transformations in higher education,
occupations, and federal power are creating a cognitive elite of growing
wealth and influence. At the other extreme, transformations in occupations and
social norms are creating a cognitive underclass. "Pressures from these
contrasting movements at the opposite ends of society put terrific stress on
the entire structure," we write in the preface, and we spend another 550 pages
of main text and 300 pages of supplementary material explaining what we mean,
and what we see as the implications for America's future.
The Bell Curve was released by the Free Press early in October 1994, a few
weeks after Richard Herrnstein's death. The initial reaction was encouraging.
Acting on Herrnstein's suggestion, the American Enterprise Institute (AEI)
held a small conference of academics and journalists from various points on
the political spectrum soon after the book's publication. The conference went
well, with brisk exchanges about a book on which people had differing opinions
but which they discussed over the course of two days as a serious and careful
work of scholarship. Two weeks after the conference, Malcolm Browne's
thoughtful review appeared in the New York Times Book Review, as did Peter
Brimelow's long and favorable article in Forbes - still the best published
synopsis of The Bell Curve.
Then came the avalanche. It seems likely that The Bell Curve will be one of
the most written-about and talked-about works of social science since the
Kinsey Report 50 years ago. Most of the comment has been virulently hostile.
The book is said to be the flimsiest kind of pseudo-science. Designed to
promote a radical political agenda. A racist screed. Methodologically
pathetic. Tainted b the work of neo-Nazis.
"Never," my AEI colleague Michael Ledeen observes, "has such a moderate
book attracted such an immoderate response." This is the central irony
connected with the reaction to The Bell Curve. For if any one generalization
can be made about a work as long and diverse as The Bell Curve, it is that the
book is relentlessly moderate - in its language, its claims, its science. It
is filled with "on the one hand. . . . on the other hand" discussions of the
evidence, presentations of competing explanations, cautions that certain
issues are still under debate, and encouragement of other scholars to explore
unanswered questions that go beyond the scope of our own work. The statistical
analysis is standard and straightforward.
Why then the hysteria? The obvious answer is race, the looming backdrop to
all discussion of social policy in the United States. Ever since the first
wave of attacks on the book, I have had an image of The Bell Curve as a sort
of literary Rorschach test. I do not know how to explain the extraordinary
discrepancy between what The Bell Curve actually says about race and what most
commentators have said that the book says, except as the result of some sort
of psychological projection onto our text.
Other factors are at work as well. Michael Novak (who has written favorably
about The Bell Curve) and Thomas Sowell (who has his criticisms of the book)
have pointed out in similar terms that the Left has invested everything in a
few core beliefs about society as the cause of problems, government as the
solution, and the manipulability of the environment for reaching the goal of
equality. For the Left, as Novak puts it, The Bell Curve's
message cannot be true, because much more is at stake than a particular
set of arguments from psychological science. A this-worldly eschatological
hope is at stake. The sin attributed to Herrnstein and Murray is theological:
they destroy hope.
I am sure Novak and Sowell are on the right track. The underlying reasons
for the reaction to The Bell Curve will turn out to be significant in their
own right, revealing much about the intellectual temper of our era. But
perspective on those reasons must wait for some years. Let me make a more
limited prediction: when the Sturm und Drang has subsided, nothing important
in The Bell Curve will have been overturned. I say this not because Herrnstein
and I were especially far-sighted, but because our conclusions are so
cautiously phrased and our findings anchored so securely in the middle of the
scientific road.
In the meantime I want to present my own assessment of where the debate
stands. The problem is how to do it within a reasonable space and how to avoid
being overtaken by events. A first wave of reviews and commentaries in the
major media appeared between October 1994 and January of this year. A second
wave, consisting of reviews in the academic journals, is on the way. I have
already seen manuscript copies of some of these reviews, often highly
technical, that will be published over the course of the next year.
The volume of all this material reaches many hundreds of pages. To comment
in detail on even a single one of the major reviews would require an article
the length of this one. I will use this space instead to present a general
proposition about The Bell Curve, and to illustrate it with examples.
My proposition is that the critics of The Bell Curve are going to produce
the very effects that their attacks have been intended to avert. I am not here
referring to the book's popularity with the reading public (it spent fifteen
weeks on the New York Times bestseller list), although it seems true that the
descriptions of The Bell Curve as an angry, racist polemic have led people in
bookstores to pick it tip to see what the fuss is about. The pages to which
they turn are nothing like what they expect, their curiosity is piqued, and
some of them buy it.
But the unintended consequences I have ill mind go far beyond the sales
that the attacks have stimulated. The attacks are also likely to affect
intellectual trends. I foresee a three-stage process.
In the first stage, a critic approaches The Bell Curve absolutely certain
that it is wrong. He feels no need to be judicious or to explore our evidence
in good faith. He seizes upon the arguments that come to hand to make his
point and publishes them, with the invective and dismissiveness that seem to
be obligatory for a Bell Curve critic.
In the second stage, the attack draws other scholars to look at the issue.
Many of them share the critic's initial assumption that The Bell Curve is
wrong. But they nonetheless start to look at evidence they would not have
looked at otherwise. They discover that the data are interesting. Some of them
back off nervously, but others are curious. They look farther. And it turns
out that there is much more out there than Herrnstein and I try to claim.
In stage three, these scholars start to produce new material on the topics
that had come under attack in the first place. I doubt that many will choose
to defend The Bell Curve, but they will build on its foundation and ultimately
do far more damage to the critics' "eschatological hope" than The Bell Curve
itself did.
I will give four examples of these unintended outcomes, drawing from the
attacks on the "pseudo-science" of a general-intelligence factor; on the link
between genes and race differences in IQ; on the power of the statistical
evidence; and on our pessimistic assessment of society's current attempts to
raise IQ through outside interventions.
Much of the attack on The Bell Curve's science has been mounted not against
anything in the book itself but against the psychometric tradition on which it
is based. Specifically, Herrnstein and I accept that there is such a thing as
a general factor of cognitive ability on which human beings differ: the famous
g.
Ever since the late 1960's, when IQ became a pariah in the world of ideas,
this has been a politically-incorrect position to take. In the early 1980's, a
book by Stephen Jay Gould, The Mismeasure of Man, cemented the discrediting of
g among liberals outside the scientific community. His portrait of
psychometrics as a pseudo-science pursued by charlatans was swallowed
uncritically and enthusiastically by the elite media, as documented by Mark
Snyderman and Stanley Rothman in The IQ Controversy: The Media and Public
Policy (1988).
A central thesis of The Mismeasure of Man was that g is nothing more than a
statistical artifact. Gould based his denial of a general mental factor on a
series of claims about factor analysis, the statistical method for identifying
g.
In a review of The Bell Curve in the New Yorker, Gould resurrects the same
arguments. Echoing The Mismeasure of Man, he writes: "g cannot have inherent
reality . . . for it emerges in one form of mathematical representation for
correlations among tests and disappears (or greatly attenuates) in other
forms, which are entirely equivalent in amount of information explained." He
continues: "The fact that Herrnstein and Murray barely mention the
factor-analyic argument forms a central indictment of The Bell Curve and is an
illustration of its vacuousness." Where, Gould asks, is the evidence that g
"captures a real property in the head"?
The reason that we "barely mention the factor-analytic argument" against
the existence of g is that it has little scholarly standing. Gould's
statistical indictment of g was refuted in various scientific quarters soon
after the appearance of The Mismeasure of Man, and research into g proceeded
without a noticeable blip.(1)
To see what this particular fight is about, a little background is
essential. One of the earliest findings about mental tests was that the
results of different tests of apparently different mental skills were
positively correlated. Charles Spearman, the British founding father of modern
psychometrics, was the first to hypothesize that they were correlated because
each was tapping into a common construct - the general mental ability he then
labeled g. Factor analysis was the method he used to extract this general
factor that accounted for the intercorrelations among subtests.
Another pioneering psychometrician, L.L. Thurstone, who in the 1930's
became Spearman's great antagonist by demonstrating how factor analysis need
not yield a dominant general factor, is the hero of Gould's story. Gould is
correct in stating that there are alternative methods with the same overall
power to account for the correlations among the tests. But he is wrong when he
implies that by using an alternative method, an analyst can get rid of g. As
Richard Herrnstein liked to say, "You can make g hide, but you can't make it
go away."(2)
Hence the frustration among psychometricians who have tried to make it go
away. After applying the particular factor-analytic method that prevented g
from emerging, they had nowhere to take the results. If they labeled their
independent factors as distinct mental skills and developed a research agenda
based on them, they got crushed by critics who could demonstrate that their
results were more elegantly explained by g. Indeed, g not only explained more
variance than any other factor, it typically explained three times as much
variance as all other factors combined.
But one need not rely only on statistical validation of g. By now there is
also a growing body of evidence that links g (and IQ scores more generally)
with neurophysiological functioning.(3) An even larger body of evidence,
covered in The Bell Curve, demonstrates g's value for predicting academic
achievement and job performance.
Gould's position, then, has been thoroughly discredited among scholars,
however dominant it remains in the media. Had he kept quiet about The Bell
Curve or attacked it on other grounds, his view might have continued to hold
sway there. But when he repeated the same arguments in his New Yorker review -
which I am told has been triumphantly circulated by nonpsychologists as the
canonical refutation of The Bell Curve - he accomplished something that
Herrinstein and I could not have done: he made scholars who know what the
evidence shows angry enough to go public.
By and large, scholars in the field of intelligence are reclusive - the
experiences of people like Arthur Jensen, Hans Eysenck, and Richard Herrnstein
himself taught them that the consequences of being visible can be extremely
punishing - and many of them were additionally disinclined to jump to the
defense of a book coauthored by someone with my reputation as a right-winger.
But Gould and, less visibly, his Harvard colleague Howard Gardner ill a review
of The Bell Curie in American Prospect, were saying things that were palpably
wrong about a topic of deep importance to professionals in the field.
Some of these professionals responded with outraged letters to the New
Yorker (none was printed). Then came a statement signed by 52 scholars and
published in the Wall Street Journal in which all the main scientific findings
of The Bell Curve were endorsed (without any explicit mention of the book or
its critics). I also hear second-hand of incidents in which reporters have
called scholars about "this pseudo-science g business" and received an answer
they did not expect. The effects of the backlash are still taking shape, but
the media may finally be getting the message. The big unreported story about
the study of intelligence in the last decade is the remarkable resilience and
importance of g.
I come now to the second example of how the attacks on The Bell Curve are
likely to have unintended consequences: the determination of the critics to
focus on race and genes, even though The Bell Curve does not.
The Bell Curve draws three important conclusions about intelligence and
race: (1) All races are represented across the range of intelligence, from
lowest to highest. (2) American blacks and whites continue to have different
mean scores on mental tests, with the difference varying from test to test but
usually about one standard deviation in magnitude - about fifteen IQ points.
"One standard deviation" means roughly that the average black American scores
at the sixteenth percentile of the white distribution. (3) Mental-test scores
are generally as predictive of academic and job performance for blacks as for
other ethnic groups. Insofar as the tests are biased at all, they tend to
overpredict, not underpredict, black performance.
These facts are useful in the quest to understand why (for example)
occupational and wage differences separate blacks and whites, or why
aggressive affirmative action has produced academic apartheid in our
universities. More generally, Herrnstein and I write that a broad range of
American social issues cannot be interpreted without understanding the ways in
which intelligence plays a role that is often, and wrongly conflated with the
role of race. When it comes to government policy, there was in our minds just
one authentic implication: return as quickly as possible to the cornerstone of
the American ideal that people are to be treated as individuals, not as
members of groups.
The furor over The Bell Curve and race has barely touched on these core
points. Instead, the critics have been obsessed - no hyperbole here - with
genes, trying to stamp out any consideration of the possibility that race
differences have a genetic component.
For the record, what we said about genes, IQ, and race in the book is that
a legitimate scientific debate is under way about the relationship of genes to
race differences in intelligence; that it is scientifically prudent at this
point to assume that both environment and genes are involved, in unknown
proportions(4); and, most importantly, that people are getting far too excited
about the whole issue. Genetically-caused differences are not as fearful, nor
environmentally-caused differences as benign, as many think. What matters is
not the source but the existence of group differences, and their
intractability (for whatever reasons).
Six months into my post-Bell Curve life, I have concluded that Herrnstein
and I were prematurely right on this point. Certainly we were right
empirically when we observed that the public at large is fascinated by the
possibility of genetic differences, and that the intellectual elites have been
"almost hysterically in denial about that possibility," as we put it in the
book. I think we were also right in trying to dampen that fascination. But
listening to some of my most loyal friends who insist that I must be
disingenuous when I continue to sax, that the genetic question is not a big
deal, I have to conclude that we failed to make our case persuasively (on pp.
311-15 of The Bell Curve).
Yet the critics, in insisting that the issue of genes really is a big deal,
are once again going to produce the very effect they want to avert. In this
instance, they have based their attacks on the premise that a full, fair look
at the data will make the issue go away. None appears to have recognized that
Herrnstein and I did not make nearly as aggressive a case for genetic
differences as the evidence permits.
The most abundant source of data that we downplayed is in the work of J.
Philippe Rushton, a Canadian psychologist who since 1985 has been publishing
increasingly detailed material to support his theory, that the three races he
labels Negroid, Caucasoid, and Mongoloid vary not just un intelligence but in
a wide variety of characteristics. We put our brief discussionn of Rushton in
an appendix. The critics of The Bell Curve are putting him on the front page,
often outrageously caricaturing his work.(5) The trouble with this strategy is
that Rushton is a serious scholar who has assembled serious data. The attacks
on The Bell Curve ensure that those data will get attention.
A related example is the charge that The Bell Curve is based on "tainted
sources." Charles Lane introduced this theme with an article in the New
Republic and then a much longer one in the New York Review of Books. In the
latter piece, he proclaimed that "No fewer than seventeen researchers cited in
the bibliography of The Bell Curve have contributed to Mankind Quarterly, a
notorious journal of `racial history' founded, and funded, by men who believe
in the genetic superiority of the white race." Lane also discovered that we
cited thirteen scholars who had received grants from the Pioneer Fund,
established and run (he alleged) by men who were Nazi sympathizers,
eugenicists, and advocates of white racial superiority. Leon Kamin, a
vociferous critic of IQ in all its manifestations, took up the same argument
at length in his review of The Bell Curve in Scientific American.
Never mind that The Bell Curve draws its evidence from more than 1,000
sources. Never mind that among the scholars in Lane's short list are some of
the most respected psychologists of our time, and that the "tainted sources"
consist overwhelmingly of articles that were published in respected and
refereed journals. Never mind that the relationship between the founder of the
Pioneer Fund and today's Pioneer Fund is roughly analogous to the relationship
between Henry Ford and today's Ford Foundation. The real effect of Lane and
Kamin's work will be to focus academic attention on the main substantive issue
they discuss relative to our "tainted sources," African IQ.
The topic of African IQ is a tiny piece of The Bell Curve: a
three-paragraph section in chapter 13 intended to address a hypothesis
Herrnstein and I heard frequently, that the test scores of American blacks
have been depressed by the experience of slavery. We briefly summarize the
literature indicating that African blacks in fact have lower test scores than
American blacks.
Lane and Kamin assault this conclusion ferociously. We make a soft target -
since we say so little about African IQ, it is easy for Lane and Kamin to
point to the many technical difficulties of knowing exactly what is going on.
But in The Bell Curve we also omit many more details making a strong case that
African blacks have extraordinarily low scores on standardized mental tests,
including ones especially designed for illiterate non-Western subjects. Lane
and Kamin want this literature to be weak and racist. It is not, and it bears
importantly, if inconclusively, on possible racial genetic differences.
When the story of African IQ is eventually untangled, the safest bet is
that the roles of nutrition, education, culture, and genes in the development
of cognitive functioning will turn out to be complex and intertwined. In other
words, I still think Herrnstein and I were right, if prematurely: it is
possible to live with the truth about genes and race, whatever it may be,
without changing one's mind about how a liberal society should function. But
whether we were right or wrong, the violent reaction is making sure that the
full range of data will be brought to public attention.
The third line of attack on The Bell Curve that I predict will have an
unintended outcome is the attempt to dismiss the statistical power of the
book's results.
Perhaps the most important section of The Bell Curve is Part II, "Cognitive
Classes and Social Behavior." It describes the relationship of IQ to poverty,
school-dropout rates, unemployment, divorce, illegitimacy, welfare, parenting,
crime, and citizenship. To avoid the complications associated with race, it
does all this for a sample of whites, using the National Longitudinal Study of
Youth.
The eight chapters in Part II deal with questions like: "What role does IQ
play in determining whether a woman has a baby out of wedlock?" Or: "What are
the comparative roles of socioeconomic disadvantage and IQ in determining
whether a youngster grows Lip to be poor as an adult?" These are fascinating
questions. But you will have a hard time figuring out from the published
commentary, on The Bell Curve that such questions were even asked, let alone
what the answers were.
Instead, the main line of attack has been that there is really no need to
pay any attention to those chapters, because Herrnstein and Murray confuse
correlation with causation; because IQ really does not explain much of the
variance anyway; and because the authors' measure of socioeconomic background
is in any case deficient. On all three counts, the critics are setting up a
reexamination of the existing technical literature on social problems that
will be intellectually embarrassing to them in the end.
First, regarding correlation and causation, here, boiled down, is what we
say in the introduction to Part II: The nonexperimental social sciences cannot
cdemonstrate unequivocal causality. In trying to explain such things as
poverty, illegitimacy and crime, we will use statistics to show what
independent role is left for IQ after taking a person's age, socioeconomic
background, and education into account. When there are other obvious
explanations - family structure, say - we will take them into account as well.
Apart from the statistics, we will describe in common-sense terms what the
nature of the causal link might be - why for example, a poor young woman of
low intelligence might be more likely to have a baby out of wedlock than a
poor young woman of high intelligence. At the end of this exercise, repeated
in similar form for each of the eight chapters in Part II, there will still be
unanswered questions, and we will point to many of those unanswered questions
ourselves. But the reader will know more than he knew before, and the way will
be opened for further explorations by our colleagues.
The statistical method we use throughout is the basic technique for
discussing causation in nonexperimental situations: regression analysis,
usually with only three independent variables. We interpret the results
according to accepted practice. To enable readers to check for themselves, we
include the printout of all the results in Appendix 4.
The assault on this modest analysis has been led by Leon Kamin in
Scientific American. There he argues that the role of IQ cannot be
disentangled from socioeconomic background; he suggests that in our database
the children of laborers have such uniformly low IQ scores that no one can
possibly, tell whether the low IQ or the disadvantaged background is to blame
for the higher rates of crime, unemployment, and illegitimacy that afflict
such youngsters. "The significant question," Kamin writes, "is, why don't the
children of laborers acquire the skills that are tapped by IQ tests?"
My answer to his significant question is: "Often, they do acquire such
skills," which is what makes the data so interesting. In America, bright
children of laborers tend to do quite well in life, despite their humble
origins. Conversely, dull children from privileged homes tend to do poorly,
despite all the help their parents lavish on them.
Herrnstein and I contend that such patterns point to causation. This is
indeed an inference - a sensible inference.
We approached the correlation/causation tangle in other sensible ways as
well. Consider the vexing case of education. People with high IQ's tend to
spend many years in school; people with low IQ's tend to leave. Does the IQ
cause the years of education, or the years of education the IQ?
For various technical reasons, simply entering education as an addtional
independent variable is unwise. So instead we defined two subsamples, each
with the same amount of education - one of adults who had completed exactly
twelve years of school and obtained a high-school diploma, no more and no
less; the other of adults who had completed exactly sixteen years of school
and obtained a bachelor's degree, no more and no less. For each topic, we
accompanied the analysis of the entire sample with separate analyses of the
high-school and college samples. Thus the reader could take a look at the
independent effect of IQ for people with identical education.
Our procedure has irritated a number of academic critics (notably James
Heckman and Arthur Goldberger) who grumble that the state of the art permits
much more. Yes, it does, and in the book we say how much we look forward to
watching our colleagues apply those more sophisticated techniques to the
unanswered questions. But more sophisticated modeling techniques would also
have opened a wide variety of technical problems that we wanted to avoid. The
procedure chose gave an excellent means of bounding the independent effects of
education, and that was our purpose.
But let us say a critic grants the existence of independent relationships
between IQ and social outcomes after holding other plausible causes constant.
How important are these "independent relationships"? Hardly at all, says
Stephen Jay Gould: The Bell Curve can safely be dismissed because IQ explains
so little about the social outcomes in question - just a few percent of the
variance, in the statistician's jargon.
Here is the truth: the relationships between IQ and social behaviors that
we present in The Bell Curve are not only "significant" in the standard
statistical sense of that phrase, they are powerful in a substantive sense,
often much more powerful than the relationships linking social behaviors with
the usual suspects (education, social status, affluence, ethnicity). In fact,
Herrnstein and I actually understate the strength of the statistical record in
The Bell Curve. The story is complex, but worth recounting because it tells so
much about the academic response to The Bell Curve.
In ordinary multiple-regression analysis, "independent variables," the
hypothesized causes, are related to a "dependent variable," the hypothesized
effect. Two statistics are of special interest. The first is the set of
regression coefficients, one for each independent variable, which tell you the
magnitude of the effect each independent variable has on the dependent
variable after taking the role of all the other independent variables into
account. Each coefficient has a standard error, which may be used to determine
whether the coefficient is statistically significant (i.e., unlikely to have
been produced by chance). The second statistic of special interest is the
square of the multiple correlation, written as [R.sup.2] (pronounced "r
square"), that tells you how much of the variance in the dependent variable is
explained by all the independent variables taken together.
One of the early topics about multiple regression that graduate students
study is the different uses of regression coefficients and [R.sup.2]. If you
have a coefficient with a large value and small standard error, it is
typically the statistic of main interpretive importance, while [R.sup.2] is of
secondary and sometimes trivial importance. Such is the case with the kind of
analysis in The Bell Curve, for reasons we explain in Appendix 4.
In all this, we treat our data as our colleagues around the country treat
regression results every day. There is nothing controversial here - as
evidenced by the fact that none of the quantitative social scientists who
reviewed this part of our manuscript before publication raised a question
about our methods.
But that is not the end of the story. Herrnstein and I make reference to
the [R.sup.2.s] in Appendix 4 as if they represent "explained variance" - and
thereby we commit a technical error, falsely understating the overall
explanatory power of our statistics. In logistic regression analysis - the
particular type we use throughout Part II - the statistic labeled [R.sup.2] is
an ersatz and unsatisfactory attempt to express the model's goodness-of-fit.
Most statisticians to whom I have talked since say we should have ignored it
altogether. Stephen Jay Gould, and others who are making the same criticism he
does, have fallen into the same error.
It would be nice if a few respected professors would publicly point out
that, whatever else one might think about The Bell Curve, the criticisms of
the book's small [R.sup.2.s] are wrong. But this is unlikely to happen.
Probably the allegation will quietly fade away as the academics who know the
true story discreetly impart the news to those who do not.
The unfounded criticisms of the statistics in The Bell Curve that I have
discussed so far will merely cause embarrassment among a few who both
understand the issues and have the decency to be embarrassed. The real
potential for backfire in the statistical critique of The Bell Curve comes
from the attack on our use of socioeconomic status (SES).
Measures of SES are a staple in the social sciences. Leaf through the
dozens of technical articles in sociology and economics dealing with issues of
success and failure in American life, and you will frequently find a measure
of SES as part of the analysis. A major purpose of The Bell Curve was to add
IQ to SES as an explanatory variable. To avoid controversy, we deliberately
constructed an SES index that uses the same elements everybody else uses:
income, occupation, and education. We did not have an a-priori reason for
weighting any of these more heavily than the others, so we converted them to
what are called "standard scores" and added them Lip to get our index - all of
which would ordinarily have caused no comment.
But when it comes to The Bell Curve, a standard SES index suddenly becomes
problematic. James Heckman notes ominously that we do not have income data for
a large part of the sample. Arthur Goldberger looks suspiciously on the idea
of standardizing the variables. Leon Kamin hypothesizes that probably the
self-reports of income, education, and occupation are exaggerated to a degree
that falsely produces the relationships we report.
My response to such criticisms is, fine, let us test out these potential
problems. Compare the results for the subsamples with and without income data.
Do not standardize the variables; create some other scales and use some other
method of combining them. Examine the validity of the self-report data.
Examine what happens when the constituent variables are entered separately
instead of as an index.
As scholars are supposed to do, Herrnstein and I checked out these and many
other possibilities - the results reported in The Bell Curve were triangulated
in numbing detail over the years we worked on the book - and we knew what the
critics who bothered to retrace our steps would discover: that there is no way
to construct a measure of socioeconomic background using the accepted
constituent variables that makes much difference in the independent role of
IQ. In the jargon, our measure of SES is robust, and as valid as everyone
else's has been.
But there's the rub: how valid has everyone else's been? Until The Bell
Curve came along, measures of SES similar to ours were used without a second
thought. Now, suddenly they are to be questioned. I doubt whether the
profession will be able to confine the questioning to just The Bell Curve.
What Herrnstein and I have done, in effect, is to throw down a challenge: if
you don't like the way IQ dominates this thing we call "socioeconomic status"
in producing important social outcomes, come up with another means of
measuring the environment that produces results you like better.
Such measures can probably be developed - but they will not be ones that
the critics of The Bell Curve will like. Suppose, for example, that one can
create a good measure of "the degree of presence and competency of a father in
the raising of a female child." That might have a large independent effect on
the girl's chances of giving birth to a baby out of wedlock, whatever her IQ.
Suppose that one can create a good measure of "the degree to which a young
male is raised in an environment where high moral standards are enforced
consistently and firmly." Again, I can imagine this having a major effect on
the likelihood of his becoming a criminal, independently of IQ.
But the same measures that compete with the importance of IQ are going to
make starkly clear something that The Bell Curve has already suggested: the
kinds of economic and social disadvantages that liberals have traditionally
treated as decisive are comparatively unimportant. It may sound like an issue
that concerns only the social scientists. Far from it. If I were to nominate
the biggest sleeper effect to emerge from The Bell Curve debate, it would be
the collapse of SES as a way of interpreting social problems. The rationale
for liberal social policy cannot easily do without it.
Raising the question of policy brings us to the last of my four examples of
the potential backfire effect of attacks on The Bell Curve - the malleability
of IQ. These attacks focused on Chapter 17, "Raising Cognitive Ability," which
chronicles the record of attempts to raise IQ through better nutrition,
prenatal care, infant intervention, and preschool and in-school programs. The
cries of protest here have been almost as loud as those directed at our
chapter on race, and for the reason that Michael Novak identified: by arguing
that no easy methods for raising IQ exist, we "destroy hope," or at least the
kind of hope that drives many of the educational and preschool interventions
for today's disadvantaged youth.
We do express hope, actually. Because the environment plays a significant
role (40 percent is our ball-park estimate) in determining intelligence - a
point The Bell Curve states clearly and often - we say that sooner or later
researchers ought to be able to figure out where the levers are. We urge that
steps be taken to hasten the day when such knowledge becomes available.
But in examining the current state of knowledge, we also urge realism.
Speaking of the most popular idea, intensive intervention for preschoolers, we
conclude that "we and everyone else are far from knowing whether, let alone
how, any of these projects have increased intelligence." We also predict that
"many ostensibly successful projects will be cited as plain and indisputable
evidence that we are willfully refusing to see the light."
This prediction has been borne out. Thus, the psychologist Richard Nisbett,
writing in The Bell Curve Wars,(6) a compendium of attacks on our book,
accuses us of being "strangely selective" in our reports about the effects of
intervention, and wonders if we were "unaware of the very large literature
that exists on the topic of early intervention."
The "very large literature" of which we were unaware? The only study
Nisbett mentions that we do not is one published in Pediatrics in 1992 which
he describes as showing a nine-point IQ advantage at age three for
participants in the intervention. Nisbett neglects to acknowledge the
unreliability of IQ measures at age three. More decisively, Nisbett is
apparently unaware that a follow-up of the same project was published in 1994,
when the children were, at age five, old enough for IQ scores to begin to
become interpretable. The results? The experimental group had an advantage of
just 2.5 points on one measure of IQ and two-tenths of a point on another -
both differences being substantively trivial and statistically
insignificant.(7) In other words, the only study in "the very large
literature" that we missed does not contradict our conclusion that such
interventions have provided promising leads but no more.
I will make two broader statements. First, in the critiques to date, no one
has pointed to a credible study containing evidence of significant, long-term
effects on cognitive functioning that we do not consider in The Bell Curve.
Second, our account of the record to date is, if anything, generous. The two
major intensive interventions for raising the IQ of children at high risk of
mental retardation - Project Milwaukee and the Abecedarian Project - have come
under intense methodological criticism in the technical literature. We allude
to the controversy in the book, but in neither case is the evidence so clear
that we could come down hard on the "no-effect" conclusion, and so we do not.
If we err, it is in the direction of giving more credit to the interventions
than is warranted.
But just as we predicted, many others are nominating "programs that work"
that we mysteriously failed to consider. And I am sure that some of them do
work, for goals other than raising IQ. We would be the last to suggest that
education cannot be made better, or that the socialization of children cannot
be improved. But in The Bell Curve we talk about a particular goal: improving
the cognitive functioning of human beings over the long term. On that score,
the record remains as Herrnsten and I describe it: yes, it can be done, but at
present only in modest amounts for most children, usually temporarily, and
inconsistently.
In this instance, I have reason to hope that the unintended effect of the
attacks on The Bell Curve will be to crystallize a debate that has long needed
crystallizing. The cry that "Herrnstein and Murray are too pessimistic" is
going to force a great many claims to be laid on the table for examination.
Thus, Howard Gardner's review takes us to task for not citing Lisbeth Schorr's
book, Within Our Reach. I would be delighted to join in a rigorous examination
of the programs Schorr describes, and see whether we find among them hard
evidence of long-term improvement in cognitive functioning. Let us bring up
all the other nominees for inspection as well. In short, let us use the furor
over The Bell Curve finally to come to grips with how difficult it is, given
the current state of knowledge, for outside interventions to make much
difference in the environmental factors that nurture cognitive development.
If outside interventions are not promising, what about the more general
phenomenon we label the "Flynn effect" (after the political scientist James
Flynn, who has done the most to bring it to public attention), whereby IQ
scores have been rising secularly throughout the world since at least the
1930's? As Thomas Sowell has argued in the American Spectator, the Flynn
effect gives reason to conclude that intelligence is malleable after all.
Herrnstein and I allude to that possibility without expressing much optimism
about it. Moreover, even if the rise in IQ scores could be taken at face
value, we would still not know how to intervene so as to manipulate it. In our
view (as in Flynn's), it seems likely that most of the increase in IQ scores
over time represents something besides gains in cognitive functioning. But
what that something is remains unclear, and this issue is still wide open.
A few weeks after The Bell Curve appeared, a reporter remarked to me that
the real message of the book is "Get serious." I resisted at first, but I now
think he had a point.
We never quite say it in so many words, but the book's subtext is that
America's discussion of social policy since the 1960's has been carried on in
a never-never land where human beings are easily changed and society can
eventually become a Lake Wobegon where everyone is above average. The Bell
Curve does indeed imply that it is time to get serious about how best to
accommodate the huge and often intractable individual differences that shape
human society. This is a counsel not of despair but of realism - including
realistic hope. An individual's g may not be as elastic as one would prefer,
but the inventiveness of the species seems to have few bounds. In The Bell
Curve, we are matter-of-fact about the limits facing low-IQ individuals in a
postindustrial economy, but we also celebrate the capacity. of people
everywhere in the normal range on the bell curve to live morally autonomous,
satisfying lives, if only the system will let them. Accepting the message of
The Bell Curve does not mean giving up on improving social policy, it means
thinking anew about how progress is to be achieved - and even more
fundamentally, thinking anew about how "progress" is to be defined.
The verdict on the influence of The Bell Curve on policy is many years
away. For now, the book may, have another useful role to play that we did not
anticipate. The attacks on it hale often read like an unintentional
confirmation of our view of the "cognitive elite" as a new caste, complete
with high priests, dogmas, heresies, and apostates. They have revealed the
extent to which the social science that deals in public policy has in the
latter part of the 20th century become self-censored and riddled with taboos -
in a word, corrupt. Only the most profound, anguished, and divisive
reexamination can change that situation, and it has to be done within the
profession. If The Bell Curve achieves nothing else, I will be satisfied if it
helps get such a reexamination going.
(1) For a survey of the contrasting receptions of The Mismeasure of Man
accorded by the press and by the scientific community, see Bernard Davis's
"Neo-Lysenkoism, IQ, and the Press" (Public Interest, Fall 1983).
(2) For those who want to pursue the technical issues, I recommend John B.
Carroll's recent book, Human Cognitive Abilities: A Survey of Factor-Analytic
Studies (Cambridge University Press, 1993). Carroll, former director of the
L.L. Thurstone Psychometric Laboratory, points out that Thurstone himself came
to accept the notion of a general factor in his later years.
(3) For examples, see A.R. Jensen, "The g Beyond Factor Analysis," in R.R.
Ronning, J.A. Glover, J.C. Conoley, and J.C. Witt (eds.), The Influence of
Cognitive Psychology on Testing, or B. Bower, "Images of Intellect: Brain
Scans May Colorize Intelligence," Science News (October 8, 1994).
(4) Intelligence is known to be substantially heritable in human beings as
a species, but this does not mean that group differences are also heritable.
Despite our explicit treatment of the issue, it is perhaps the single most
widespread source of misstatement about The Bell Curve.
(5) For Rushton's argument and evidence, see J. Philippe Rushton, Race,
Evolution, and Behavior: A Life History Perspective (Transaction Books, 398
pp., $34.95).
(6) Edited by Steven Fraser, Basic Books, 216 pp., $10.00 (paperback).
(7) Jeanne Brooks-Gunn et al., "Early Intervention in Low-Birth-Weight
Premature Infants," JAMA, vol. 272 (1994).
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone