Open Letters
THE ORION PARTY
The Prometheus League
- Humanity Needs A World Government PDF
- Cosmos Theology Essay PDF
- Cosmos Theology Booklet PDF
- Europe Destiny Essays PDF
- Historical Parallels PDF
- Christianity Examined PDF
News Blogs
Euvolution
- Home Page
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Library of Eugenics
- Genetic Revolution News
- Science
- Philosophy
- Politics
- Nationalism
- Cosmic Heaven
- Eugenics
- Future Art Gallery
- NeoEugenics
- Contact Us
- About the Website
- Site Map
Transhumanism News
Partners
Kings of Men: a Special Issue of the journal INTELLIGENCE about Arthur Jensen
Kings of Men: Introduction to a Special Issue of the Journal of
INTELLIGENCE (1998)
by DOUGLAS K. DETTERMAN
Case Western Reserve University
This special issue is dedicated -- to Arthur Jensen. It has become apparent
that he is unlikely to receive the recognition his work merits. The issue
begins with a statement by Jensen which discusses some of his work people are
less familiar with. His bibliography is also reprinted. A number of persons
selected for their diversity in outlook then comment on the work of Arthur
Jensen and the impact it has had.
This special issue is devoted to Arthur Jensen. Several years ago it became
apparent to me that Arthur Jensen would probably never receive the kind of
recognition others with even lesser accomplishments have been given. He will
not receive the honors his work merits from organizations like the American
Psychological Association, the National Academy of Science, or the National
Association for the Advancement of Science, to name a few. The reasons for
this lack of recognition are obvious. He has taken controversial and
politically unpopular stands on issues that are important to the study of
intelligence.
To attempt to rectify this situation, I contacted him and asked that he
allow Intelligence to do a special issue in his honor. My plan was to have him
write an introduction that would describe his career. This would be followed
by commentary on his work by a wide assortment of researchers in the field.
Not surprisingly, the one addition he requested was that a list of his
publications be included. He has had a highly productive career and, I must
say, I was not ful1y aware of the extent of his interests until I saw the list
of publications.
The plan originally formulated has been carried out in this issue of
Intelligence. In his personal statement, you will see that Jensen emphasizes
work that may be less familiar to many readers but is no less important. The
commentaries on Jensen's work are well worth reading. They tell you as much
about the commentators as about Jensen. You will also see that even those who
strongly disagree with Jensen have high respect for his intellectual integrity
and what he has accomplished. Though this volume stands as a tribute to Arthur
Jensen by his contemporaries, like all scientists, his ultimate recognition
will be the degree of acceptance of the ideas he has developed.
What has Jensen accomplished in his career? By any measure, Arthur Jensen
has made substantial contributions to the study of human intelligence. While
opinion may differ about what his most important contributions have been, I
have three that I think would rank high on anyone's list.
Genetics. It is hard to remember how dominant environmental thinking was
just 30 years ago. Many thought that even mental retardation could be cured by
purely environmental interventions. The genetics of intelligence were seldom
discussed. Jensen's Harvard Educational Review article and subsequent
publications on the genetics of intelligence had an enormous effect on the
zeitgeist. It was no longer possible to ignore genetic influences when
discussing intelligence. He paved the way for the many behavior geneticists
who were to follow in his footsteps.
We have still not realized the full ramifications of this change. For
example, not everyone yet fully appreciates that genetics will have to be
taken into account when considering environmental variables. Much of the
research that was done on the effect of so called environmental variables is
worthless because those studies failed to partial out genetic influences and,
so, are hopelessly confounded. Among the most discerning, there is a new
appreciation for the methodologies that will have to be used to truly
understand the environment. Year's from now we may realize that our
appreciation of genetic influences was the first step over the threshold to a
better understanding of the environment.
Cognition and the Brain. Jensen's early work on reaction time and
intelligence focused interest on cognition and its relationship to brain
processes and how cognition and brain processes relate to intelligence. A
better appreciation of the cognition-brain-intelligence relationship is
critical to ultimately understanding intelligence. Though Jensen was not the
only one to appreciate this, his work was certainly pivotal. What seemed to
impress people most was that such a simple task as choice reaction time
correlated with intelligence.
While we are now in only the earliest phases of understanding the
cognition-brain-intelligence relationship, there is no question that is where
the field is heading. Techniques for studying this relationship like averaged
evoked potentials, PET, and fMRI are increasingly being used and reported
upon. The future is promising for these tools. But without an appreciation of
the brain-cognition-intelligence relationship it is unlikely they would have
been used at all.
g. Without question, Jensen's most significant contribution has been to
show the importance of general intelligence, or g. The idea introduced by
Spearman, while still a graduate student in 1904, reached its highest pinnacle
yet in Jensen's (1998) recent book, The g factor: The science of mental
ability. Besides being beautifully written, I predict the book will be the
foundation for research for decades to come. It is a summary, that nearly
anyone can read, of the research that makes g such an important concept. No
one can fully understand individual differences without an understanding of
general intelligence and its implications.
Jensen has been the major champion of the concept of g over the last two
decades. He has shown that of all individual differences so far demonstrated,
g is the most powerful both as a scientific construct and in the prediction of
every day performance. He has crystallized methods for studying g and applied
those methods. His work on g alone is sufficient for a distinguished
scientific career.
Why has Arthur Jensen accomplished what he has accomplished? It seems
reasonable to ask why he has accomplished so much if for no other reason than
to understand scientific achievement. I think there are a number of personal
characteristics that were important in his success. I have had the chance to
observe him closely over the last 25 years and these conclusions are based on
those observations.
Smart. Jensen comes up with more good ideas than anyone I have known. In
the course of reviewing for Intelligence, I have seen countless times when he
has suggested ideas for studies to people that have been successfully carried
out. He receives no credit for this and, in most cases, is never acknowledged
for his contribution. I once asked him why he didn't carry out some of these
good ideas himself. He told me he had more things than he could possibly do
and the important thing was to see the work done to advance the field.
His published work is testament to his clear and insightful thinking. The
work is always understandable and usually makes a fundamental point. There may
be people who publish more, but I am sure there are very few whose
publications reflect as many good ideas as Jensen's do.
Tenacity Developed from a Love of His Work. Jensen sticks to an idea when
he knows he is right. There are few people who have a firmer sense of what is
right and what is wrong and who are willing to follow their own instincts
about what is right. His tenacity is propelled by a real enjoyment of the work
he does. If you talk to him about intelligence, it is hard not to become
excited yourself because of the enthusiasm he shows. It is clear he really
loves the pursuit of answers in this field for their own sake.
Agnosticism and Open Mindedness. In his own statement in this issue, he
admits to a healthy agnosticism about everything. This is particularly true
about intelligence. He has no investment about how a question comes out, he
simply wants it answered correctly. For years, his critics have called him
every name in the book and have accused him of all kinds of biases and
prejudices. In fact, I have never known anybody with fewer prejudices. The
biggest prejudices scientists usually have are those in favor of their own
ideas. Such prejudices are very hard to avoid and the notion of the
"objective" scientist is, for most of us, a goal we fail to achieve. However,
Jensen has no loyalty whatsoever to any theory or hypothesis even if they come
from his own ideas. He would gladly know the truth even if it proved him
wrong. In fact, he would be excited to know the truth.
His agnosticism is one of the characteristics that it took me longest to
identify. I think that is because it is such an unusual one and not typical of
most others I have known. When I first met him personally, I wondered what his
biases and prejudices really were and tried to identify them for many years.
My effort was wasted. I finally came to the conclusion that he just doesn't
have any. I think this may be a point that is impossible for his critics to
understand. On the other hand, it is the very reason he has stood up so well
against his critics. He has invested himself in pursuit of the truth, not any
particular set of ideas.
Thick Skin. I doubt that there have been few people in the history of
science who have suffered more criticism than Jensen. There are other
examples, of course, including Galileo, Darwin and others. But I doubt if any
of them had to have police guards or were regularly threatened with acts of
physical violence. I have heard all sorts of rumors about Jensen. One of the
most interesting was that he conspired with the Nixon Whitehouse to kill
Headstart. I asked him about this and he had a recollection of someone asking
him about his research but there was no conspiracy. What is ludicrous about
this rumor is that Headstart spending increased dramatically during the Nixon
administration (Caruso, Taylor, & Detterman, 1988). There have been many other
rumors and gossip, but the ones I have been able to check out have all been
false.
Besides vociferous attacks from organized opposition, Jensen has also had
to suffer the indignity of seeing his research and writing systematically
misrepresented in the popular press. Many of the articles that I have read in
the popular press have made me wonder how much of Jensen's work the author had
actually read. I am sure that this misrepresentation would be the most
difficult part for me to withstand. However, in the years I have known him, I
have never heard him complain about this treatment or express any sentiment of
unfairness. I always wondered why. It was not long ago that I figured it out.
Because he has no commitment to any particular outcome, Jensen finds it
amusing, and perhaps humorous, that people become so exorcised about ideas,
ideas that could be right or wrong. Instead of applying their intellect to
finding out if these ideas hold water, they express their emotions against the
message bearer. The saddest part of the whole thing is that the criticisms
that have been directed against Jensen have led to little, if anything, of
lasting scientific value. Viewed in this way, the effort expended in futile
activity is rather ironically humorous.
One of the incidents that typifies many of Jensen's personal
characteristics occurred when he came to Case Western Reserve University to
give a colloquium. The talk was open to the university community and drew a
large crowd. Among those in the crowd were several members of the local
Communist Party. They had come to hear him talk about race and intelligence
but, instead, he had just begun his reaction time research and was talking
about that. During his presentation they listened attentively and politely, as
is the custom of all Midwesterners, even members of the Communist Party. At
the end of the presentation, there was time for questions and they asked a few
pointed ones showing that they had studied up for Jensen's appearance. (In
fact, they had probably read more of Jensen than most in the audience.)
After the talk ended, there was a reception in the lobby. As he was
drinking his wine and eating his cheese, Jensen slowly made his way around the
room working toward the Communist Party members who were bunched in a corner.
He was probably drawn to them because it was clear that they were among the
best informed about his work even though they had philosophical differences.
Maybe it was the philosophical differences' that attracted Jensen to them. I
will never be sure. They began asking him questions about intelligence which
he enthusiastically answered. The conversation went on for some time. The rest
of the audience drifted away and the caterers began cleaning up. Jensen
carried on enthusiastically and, at least in my opinion, his opponents were
loosing badly. Looking for a way out, the Communist Party members slowly began
backing towards the door. But Jensen was just getting started and for every
step backward they took toward the door, he took one forward both figuratively
and literally. Feeling a bit sorry for them by this time, I told Dr. Jensen
that we had to leave for dinner. Taking the opportunity, the representatives
of the Communist Party bolted for the door and began walking east on Euclid
Avenue. You could see that Jensen was disappointed to loose his sparring
partners. He quickly asked which way we were going to dinner. I said we first
had to return to my office which was east on Euclid. Quickly, he proceeded me
out the door and caught up to his victims. The discussion proceeded down
Euclid Avenue until our ways had to part. I think this encounter was the
highlight of Jensen's visit.
Solitude. Finally, I think one thing that Jensen has enjoyed as a result of
his notoriety is a kind of solitude in which to think, work, and write. Even
those who become moderately successful in this business are asked to do many
things they don't really want to do and that don't contribute to their
scientific accomplishment. Because many have regarded him as a social outcast,
he has been spared many of these nearly meaningless activities that he would
have had to carry out if he had been in the good graces of those in power. Add
to this a wife who Jensen acknowledges has left him totally free to pursue his
research and you have what seems to me a nearly ideal circumstance for a
scientific career. My one concern in doing this issue is that we could ruin
all of that by giving him the recognition he deserves. Let's hope that doesn't
happen.
The following quote is one of my favorite from Galton. It describes general
intelligence and those who possess it in high quantity. Galton never knew
Jensen but I am sure that he had men like him in mind when he wrote this:
"People lay too much stress on apparent specialties, thinking over rashly
that because a man is devoted to some pursuit he could not possibly have
succeeded in anything else. They might just as well say that because a youth
had fallen desperately in love with a brunette, he could not possibly have
fallen in love with a blonde. He may or may not have more natural liking for
the former type of beauty than the latter, but it is as probable as not that
the affair was mainly or wholly due to a general amourousness of disposition.
It is just the same with special pursuits. A gifted man is often capricious
and fickle before he selects his occupation, but when it has been chosen he
devotes himself to it with a truly passionate ardour. After a man of genius
has selected his hobby, and so adapted himself to it as to seem unfitted for
any other occupation in life and to be possessed of but one special aptitude,
I often notice, with admiration, how well he bears himself when circumstances
suddenly thrust him into a strange position. He will display an insight into
new conditions, and a power of dealing with them, with which even his most
intimate friends were unprepared to accredit him. Many a presumptuous fool has
mistaken indifference and neglect for incapacity; and in trying to throw a man
of genius on ground where he was unprepared for attack, has himself received a
most severe and unexpected fall. I am sure that no one who has had the
privilege of mixing in the society of the abler men of any great capital, or
who is acquainted with the biographies of the heroes of history, can doubt the
existence of grand human animals, of natures pre-eminently noble, of
individuals born to be kings of men. (Galton, 1869, pp. 24-25)"
I think if you read this issue cover to cover, you will find that no matter
what your opinions are on the issues, no matter who is right or wrong, Arthur
Jensen is a man to be respected not only for what he has accomplished but for
who he is. Thank you, Professor Jensen.
Acknowledgements: Parts of this work were supported by Grants No. HD07176
from the National Institute of Child Health and Human Development, Office of
Mental Retardation.
-----------------------
Intensive, Detailed, Exhaustive by THOMAS J. BOUCHARD, JR., University of
Minnesota
Arthur Jensen's bibliography is characterized as breathtaking and his
scientific work as intensive, detailed, exhaustive, fair-minded, temperate,
and courageous. Specific articles and books are targeted as must reading. I
argue that Jensen's characterization of the influence of the Berkeley
psychology department in the 1940's reflects his own intellectual biases
rather than those of the department. Jensen's work is praised as an extension
of the British Biological-Theoretical Tradition which attempts to integrate
psychological, biological, social genetic, sociological, and cultural
processes in a coherent theoretical framework. A new definition of Jensenism.
based on the Jansenist heresy, is provided.
Upon reading both Arthur Jensen's bibliography and his new book, The g
Factor: The Science of Mental Ability, in the same week only one word comes to
mind-"breathtaking". Reading his bibliography is as much a delight as reading
his books and papers, truly an intellectual feast. As a fellow Galtonian I
will point out a few facts the casual reader might miss if they did not count
items and have not read much of Jensen's work; a) he is the first author on
357 of the 384 items, b) he is the sole author of 319 of the 384 items, c) he
has four citation classics, d) he has published nearly 10 items a year
(including books) since 1962, e) there is no indication that he is slowing
down, and f) the quality is not only superb, it is getting better! One
disconcerting feature of the bibliography is the paucity of items that have
been reprinted. I was stunned, for example, to see the classic 1977 article,
"Cumulative deficit in IQ of blacks in the rural South", reprinted only once.
It is still the definitive paper on the topic. I suspect that the reason so
few papers have been reprinted is the same one that has resulted in his not
having been given the numerous honors other scientists of his stature have
already received. He has dared to study and speak straight forwardly about
important issues that most other social scientists only whisper about -- race
and class differences in IQ, lack of bias in intelligence testing, the
biological basis of general intelligence, genetic influences on intelligence,
and fallacious research methods in developmental psychology. This point can be
nicely illustrated by comparing the way Jensen was treated when he visited the
University of Minnesota in 1976 and the way Todd Risely was treated on a
recent visit. Jensen had been invited to speak on his new work dealing with
test bias by the Institute of Child Development (ICD). I had been asked by
Scarr, the invitee, to sit in the front row of the auditorium with her because
she had heard that he might be attacked. Attacked he was. He was overwhelmed
on stage by some extremely hostile members of the audience. She, I, and the
police in attendance had to escort him out to safety. He was able to make a
presentation to a small audience at ICD later in the day. What the University
community was not allowed to hear was a synopsis of work that has now become
the definitive statement on test bias, work which has completely reversed
professional opinion on this issue. Almost everything which has followed is
derivative. In 1997, Risley was invited to the University of Minnesota by the
Institute of Child Development where he expounded on his findings reported in
the book, "Meaningful differences in the every day experiences of young
American children" (Hart & Risley, 1995). Hart and Risley reported on a
long-term within-family correlational study in which they show a high
correlation between parental language diversity and children's IQ. This work
was cited by President Clinton during the 1997 White House Conference on
Children (UPI, 1997). In his work Jensen has repeatedly emphasized the
behavior genetic dictum that correlations between parental behavior and child
behavior computed on biological relatives reared together are completely
uninterpretable. This fundamental methodological flaw, repeatedly committed by
many psychologists, is a simple variation on the argument that "correlation
does not mean causation". For reasons, that I cannot fathom, warnings about
this elementary flaw have still not been incorporated into many introductory
statistics and methodology textbooks (an exception is Ellis (1994)). One has
to ask about the viability of a science that allows the consistent repetition
of a serious methodological flaw pointed out and solved by Galton (by the use
of the adoption design) over 150 years ago. It is not as if no one noticed
Galton's admonitions. The problem was discussed in great detail by Burks
(1928a, 1928b, 1938). In recent years it has been written about in great
detail by Meehl (1970, 1971, 1978), Scarr (198 1, 1992, 1997, 1978) and in
other guises by Plomin (1994).
WHAT EVERY PSYCHOLOGIST SHOULD READ
Upon examining his bibliography I am embarrassed at the number of Jensen's
publications that I have not read. That will not, however, keep me from making
some recommendation to readers who are much less familiar with his work. From
the early work read, "The Stroop Color-Word Test: A review" (Jensen & Rohwer,
1966). The 1969 Harvard Educational Review (HER) article, "How much can we
boost IQ and scholastic achievement?", (Jensen, 1969) is still a gem as are
the replies to critics. Some critics have argued this article is a citation
classic because it is often cited solely for purposed of refutation. I have no
doubt that many who cite it for the purpose of refutation have not read it. I
recommend it, however, because it is a true classic. Better yet read his book
Genetics and Education (Jensen, 1972) in its entirety as it contains the HER
article and numerous other superb papers. Jensen, of course, makes a few
mistakes now and then as Kamin (1975) points out in his review of this book.
The history of one the mistakes is fascinating. Jensen reprinted a graph that
included a data point, for dizygotic twins reared apart -- a sample of IQ kin
data that did not exist at the time. According to Kamin this kind of error
reflects the bias of those who take a genetic position. Locurto (1991),
however, informs us that the graph came from an article by Heber, Dever, and
Conroy (1968). The senior author of that paper was in fact a well known
environmentalist (see pages 63-66 in Locorto's book for a discussion of
Heber).
If you are somewhat interested in behavior genetics and don't know much
beyond high school genetics, and would like a primer in quantitative genetics
read, "Genetic and behavioral effects of nonrandom mating" (Jensen, 1978). If
you want to know something about psychometrics and the issue of bias in mental
testing the definitive work is still "Bias in mental testing" (Jensen, 1980a).
If you are short on time the Behavior and Brain Science summary of "Bias in
mental testing" (Jensen, 1980b) will give you a very good overview of the bias
issue. If, like me, you have wondered about Stephen J. Gould's veracity and
competence in the mental ability domain you must read Jensen's review of "The
missmeasure of man". The title of the review is "The debunking of scientific
fossils and straw persons" (Jensen, 1982) and it is among Jensen's very best
book reviews. I would recommend it be followed up with Phil Rushton's review
of the revised edition of the same book (Rushton, 1997). If you still need
more criticism of Gould read Dennett's (1995) assessment of Gould. Alas as I
write these words I find that S. J. Gould has been elected president of the
American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS). The only solace I
can garner from this event is that the AAAS once elected Margaret Mead as its
president (Freeman, 1983; Freeman, 1991; Freeman, 1992). Mistakes will be
made, but some seem more egregious than others.
While doing my simple counts of Jensen's work it occurred to me that Jensen
would have analyzed "the data" differently. He would have argued that it is
imperative to remove redundancy and artifacts, he would have grouped the
papers by type, by source of publication, by decade. etc., and he would have
thrown much more light on the topic. To use the title of one of his book
reviews it would have been "Intensive, detailed, exhaustive". Indeed these
three terms capture much of the flavor of Jensen's writings. I should also add
fair-minded, temperate, and courageous. For someone who has been attacked so
vituperatively, both in public and in the published literature, I continue to
be astounded at the lack of anger and hostility in his replies and the
astuteness with which he dissects the arguments of his critics. To use a
psychoanalytic metaphor, I am inclined to believe that he sublimates anger and
hostility into mental energy -- see his astute discussion of the construct of
mental energy in Jensen (1997).
I suspect if you asked other Galtonians what they would recommend as "must
reading" the list would be somewhat different from mine. There is so much
excellent material to chose from that if only a few lists were combined the
final list would virtually exhaust his bibliography.
Jensen's writings are virtual tutorials on how to write science and how to
deal with controversy -- stick to the available evidence, put all the evidence
in it's full context, carefully explain the methods, their rationale and the
assumptions, acknowledge the lack of evidence when it does not exist and avoid
ad hominem arguments. In other words stick to the evidence and be intensive,
detailed and exhaustive.
A DIGRESSION ON BERKELEY AND WHO INFLUENCES WHOM
I found Jensen's description of how, in the psychology department at
Berkeley in the 1940's, genetic influences on individual differences were
neglected somewhat misleading. His description should have been tempered by
the recognition that Tolman in a very early paper titled, "The inheritance of
maze-learning ability rats" (1924) took a clear position on the importance of
genetic factors as they influence behavior. Gerald McClearn (1962) provides a
concise history of this period at Berkeley. Tolman strongly encouraged Tryon
to study genetic influence on behavior and they collaborated to develop a
self-recording maze to collect data from the selectively bred animals (Tolman,
Tryon, & Jeffress, 1929). Tryon published at least 12 papers on individual
differences and genetic influences on learning ability in rats between 1929
and 1941. The first, in 1929, was titled "The genetics of learning ability in
rats". This research program resulted in the famous Tryon maze-bright and
maze-dull rat strains. Heron (1935) replicated the Tryon work at Minnesota
shortly thereafter. Most psychologists are not aware of the fact that Heron
published, with Skinner, (Heron & Skinner, 1940), a paper comparing the rate
of bar pressing in the maze-bright and maze-dull rats (the "brights" had a
higher rate!). My point here is that the idea of genetic influences on
behavior was alive and well at Berkeley when Jensen was there. For some reason
it did not "infect" him. I am sad to report that much the same thing happened
to me. I entered Berkeley as a sophomore in 1963 and also received an
education strongly biased in the direction of experimental (environmental)
psychology. As a graduate student in the same department, however, I recall
Tryon's spellbinding introductory psychology lectures -- I was a teaching
assistant in the course -- that incorporated behavior genetic findings. Tryon
anticipated Jensen's work and the arguments of "The Bell Curve" (segregation
of cognitive classes in American society) by many years. My collagues at
Minnesota tell me that Patterson did also, a claim supported by calls from his
students in the 40's asking me what the fuss about "The Bell Curve" was all
about, "Wasn't it old news?". The importance of the ideas Tryon was talking
about simply did not fully register in my mind. I did not relate them to my
own interests in personality and social psychology. Gerald McClearn was also
on the Berkeley faculty, teaching Behavior Genetics at this time (he went on
to Colorado to found the Institute for Behavioral Genetics), but unfortunately
we did not have any contact. Fortunately, Harrison Gough -- my advisor --
required me to read the first textbook in behavior genetics (Fuller &
Thompson, 1960) for my special exams and this gave some sense of the field. I
also recall Frank Barron presenting, in a very positive manner, the classic
meta-analysis of the IQ literature by Erlenmeyer-Kimling and Jarvik (1963)
updated in 1981 by Bouchard and McGue (1981) -- to an Institute of Personality
Assessment and Research seminar. No one seemed to have been aware of the
importance of this paper. Nor did they take it seriously, as IQ was out of
style in those days. The intrepid Barron, however, had already carried out an
early twin study of creativity (Barron & Parisi, 1976). The importance of work
in behavior genetics remained only on the periphery of my consciousness until
the appearance of Jensen's 1969 HER paper. I had taught a course on Human
Intelligence at the University of California Santa Barbara using the textbook
by Hunt (1961). Even though I had only a rudimentary knowledge of behavior
genetics I had found the book very unsatisfactory in its treatment of genetic
influences. Jensen's monograph exploded on the scene like a bombshell and I
immediately wrote and asked him for a copy. The 1969 monograph and Jensen's
subsequent writing have changed the field of behavior genetics and individual
differences in fundamental ways. I report this long anecdote about the
Berkeley psychology department because I believe we really do not know why or
how people are influenced by the environmental context in which they find
themselves. Why, for example, did Jensen become enamored with Hull's theory
instead of Tolman's which explicitly recognized the role of heredity and
individual differences? Jensen, of course agrees with me on this point. As he
succinctly puts it, "It always amazed to see psychologists offering glib
explanations of some immensely complicated behavioral individual incident when
psychological science has not even provided explanations for comparatively
simple phenomenon ."
MEMBERSHIP IN THE LONDON SCHOOL
Now that I have castigated others for the sin of assuming they know how we
have been influenced by our environment I will proceed to commit the same sin.
One consistent feature of Jensen's research career is his love of theoretical
models with elemental parts and clear quantitative implications. These feature
characterize Hullian learning theory, the serial position effect, the verbal
learning (experimental) tradition he found himself in at the Human Learning
Center in Berkeley, the Level I-Level II theory of group differences, and
quantitative behavior genetic theory. This pattern of intellectual interests
early on led him to become a member of the The London School. I prefer to call
the London School the British Biological-Theoretical Tradition because, a) the
latter term puts the origins of the group in a large context (Darwin and
Galton came well before the University of London which is the London referred
to in the term London School), b) it describes the approach of the group and,
c) it provides a nice contrast with what I call the French
Clinical-Therapeutic Tradition. The British Biological-Theoretical Tradition
has been attacked on a variety of grounds (reductionistic, anti-egalitarian,
racist, cold and heartless, etc.) but the most vehement arguments have been
against its biological orientation. Consider the following quote, "The
interpretation of IQ data has always taken place, as it must, in a social and
political context, and the validity of the data cannot be fully assessed
without reference to that context. That is in general true of social science,
and no amount of biology-worship by behavior geneticists can transfer IQ
testing from the social to the biological sciences (Kamin, 1974, p. 2)."
Lewontin, Rose, and Kamin (1984) have extended this argument to all behavioral
traits including psychopathology. These critics have cut to the heart of the
matter. The goal of British Biological-Theoretical Tradition has indeed been,
since the time of Galton, to integrate psychology, biology, and genetics
(Bouchard, 1996). "The g Factor: The science of mental ability" is a direct
descendant of Galton 's book "Hereditary Genius" and Spearman's book "The
abilities of man" (1927). It is a brilliant work. It pushes the goal of
British Biological-Theoretical Tradition a giant step forward. I challenge the
reader to examine Jensen's magnum opus and decide for him or herself if it has
crossed the threshold from the social to the biological sciences. It is worth
noting that E.O. Wilson's recent book, "Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge"
(Wilson, 1998), defends a very similar but even broader research program.
While reading "The g Factor" I was struck by Jensen's detailed knowledge of
the lives of many of the important historical figures in the IQ story. His
bibliography explains why he is so knowledgeable. In 1984 he wrote
bibliographic entries for the Encyclopedia of Psychology on Galton, Pearson,
Spearman, and Thurstone and in 1994 he wrote bibliographic entries for Galton,
Spearman, and Eysenck for the Encyclopedia of Intelligence. More recommended
reading.
"JENSENISM"
Jensen reported in his commentary in this issue the definition of
"Jensenism", taken from current dictionaries, in order to try to free himself
from its grip. I don't think this is possible, consequently, I thought it
might be worth preparing a proper and more comprehensive definition that
praises Jensen. My definition is anticipatory and includes the effect of his
magnum opus, "The g Factor". My definition mimics the definition of an older
heresy -- Jansensim (See encyclopedia Britanica 15th Ed., Micropaedia, p. 515)
Jensenism: A scientific movement of unorthodox tendencies (heresy) that
appeared chiefly in the United States in the late 1960's. The movement was
scientific (religious) in origin, arising out of the theoretical (theological)
problem of reconciling the empirical observation of massive and important
individual differences if intelligence as well as a large and persistent
black-white difference in intelligence (lack of divine grace) with the belief
that all men are created equal (human freedom). Jensenism exalts the influence
of the genes (grace) made available by mother nature (Christ the Redeemer).
According to the doctrine, genes are capable of explaining most of the
differences; and it puts forth the scientific (Augustinian) arguments
regarding the necessity of genes for any explanation of the differences, the
infallible efficacy of genes, and demonstrates the absolutely arbitrary
character of environmental explanations. Consistent with this pessimistic view
of man's nature and freedom are its rigoristic views on scientific method and
quantification.
The publication of the manifesto of Jensenism, "The g Factor", after
attempts to censor it, aroused violent controversy. The work was accused,
chiefly by Psychologists (Jesuits), of divesting freewill of all reality and
of rejecting the universality of the redemption by environmental means.
Nevertheless, the Jensenist interpretation of the empirical evidence spread.
It was defended by many disciples and it attracted many influential converts.
The establishment, in the pages of the New York Times (Papacy), struck out
against Jensenism with the publication of a devastating review of "The g
Factor" (the Bull of Cum Occasione) which among other things condemned the
five propositions of Jensenism on the relationship between black-white
differences in IQ and genes.
Jensensim is a complex movement, based more on a commitment to scientific
method (a certain mentality and spirituality) than on specific doctrines. It
is an attempt, in line with that of the Reformers, to reform psychology (the
Church) in the spirit of early science (Christianity). It opposed what, in its
view, was a compromising approach to true scientific method (Christian
theology) and practice but was rejected by psychology (the Church) as an
exaggerated and unorthodox position.
------------------
Costs and Benefits of Defying the Crowd in Science by ROBERT J. STERNBERG,
Yale University
Scientists, mirroring the societies in which they live, have devised
numerous ways of rewarding conformity and punishing defiance. Some of the
mechanisms are reviewed. Scientists who defy the crowd can gain extrinsic
reinforcement, but often from sources that promote irresponsibility on the
part of these scientists. For the most part, Arthur Jensen has spent his
career in defiance of the scientific crowd. Some of this work has made an
outstanding contribution to the science of intelligence: other work, I
believe, has been regressive. What kind of system might appropriately reward
that work which has made a contribution?
On November 27, 1997, the day of the Macy's Thanksgiving Day parade, my
wife and I were in New York City. We had no interest in the Thanksgiving Day
parade and were walking down Seventh Avenue when we started encountering
noticeable pedestrian traffic walking in the opposed (northward) direction.
The farther we walked, the heavier the opposing pedestrian traffic became, and
the more visibly annoyed people became that we were walking in the opposite
direction. Eventually, we reached a density of human traffic such as we had
never seen before. The choice of whether to walk in the direction opposed to
everyone else was taken away from us: Police waved us over onto a side street
to head toward the east. We could either join the crowd or leave it
altogether. We were forbidden to oppose it.
Throughout much of history and much of the world even today, people have
had the same choice with respect to their ideas. They have had the option
either to join the crowd or, if they are lucky, to leave it, but not to oppose
it. Through secret police, inquisitions, kangaroo courts, and even summary
execution, people who have chosen either not to be part of the parade or at
least to be fellow-travelers with it have been subjected to punishment. Of
course, people in the United States like to believe that it is different
there. After all, many of those living in the U.S. believe it to be a "free
country."
On the one hand, the freedoms enjoyed by residents of the U.S. are
substantial. For example, people can criticize the government or even sue its
chief executive, both without being imprisoned or otherwise totally silenced.
At the same time, the society has been able to function without a formal
government-sponsored "thought police" in part because the members of the
society have themselves taken on aspects of the role of a thought police,
obviating the need for a formal squadron. The society has devised many ways to
punish nonconformers, as any child in a schoolyard has observed. Of course, at
other times in the country's history -- most notoriously but not only during
the McCarthy era -- nonconformers in the U.S. have not been so lucky. Those
who have defied the crowd have been vilified or even perished. Scientists are
not much different from other people. Scientists, too, have developed a number
of ways to ensure that their numbers follow the crowd.
ENFORCING CONFORMITY TO THE CROWD AMONG SCIENTISTS
Thought policing is not limited to politics. It occurs in science as well.
Many individuals enter science because they believe it is a calling that
encourages free thinking and independent thought. Many of these same
individuals soon discover that their idealism bears little contact with
reality. As Kuhn (1970) and others have observed, scientists are no more
independent-minded or free-thinking than anyone else. If anything, they
cherish conformity more than the rest.
Scientists enforce conformity in a number of ways, both formal and
informal.
1.Training. For the most part, students learn through their preprofessional
training what the current paradigms are and what kinds of work are rewarded
and what kinds are not. They are encouraged to do kinds of work that will be
rewarded. To a large extent, training is considered "good" to the extent that
it teaches students where the rewards are.
2.Publications. Many people who have submitted articles to journals have
discovered that the refereeing process is an excellent way to ensure
conformity under the banner of quality control. Of course, it is difficult to
get articles accepted if they are totally pedestrian; but there is almost
always some journal that will take an article, no matter how pedestrian it may
be. More difficult is to get articles accepted if they go against the accepted
wisdom, as John Garcia discovered in his studies of conditioning and as many
others have discovered in their own work. Thus, many people find that the work
that is hardest to get accepted is not only their worst work, but also their
best.
3.Grants. Grants provide an excellent way to reward conformity. People who
work outside established paradigms often find it very difficult or impossible
to get funded, so that they are effectively prevented from doing much of what
they might have intended to get done. There are many forces that contribute to
making granting agencies a conservative force (see Sternberg, 1996a, 1997).
First, low selection ratios allow even one negative reviewer essentially to
blackball a proposal. Second, programmatic agencies fund work within their
established program of research but not outside it. Third, people who are
asked to serve on review panels will, for the most part, be those working
within established and accepted paradigms. Fourth, those who agree to spend
the vast amounts of time it requires to be on such panels may tend even more
toward conformity than those who would rather devote the time to their own
research. Finally, proposals are expected to make contact with existing
paradigms, and if they do not, they can be rejected for this reason alone.
4.Recognitions. Through prizes, awards, organizational offices, and the
like, scientists can enforce their set of values, recognizing those who play
the accepted game well and failing to recognize those who go outside the
accepted limits. In some cases, these views may even have nothing to do with
the work for which recognition is being given. For example, a lifetime
achievement award to be presented to Raymond Cattell at the annual meeting of
the American Psychological Association in 1997 was suspended pending
investigation of his religious beliefs!
5.Book Reviews. Books of scholars who go beyond the limits are typically
subject to negative reviews, sometimes by people who seem not to have read the
books.
6.Graduate Students. "Respectable" researchers do not send their
undergraduate students to work with "disreputable" researchers.
7.Informal Networks. Perhaps most importantly, those who work outside
accepted networks never make it into the professional in-groups. They are less
likely to be asked to serve on committees, write promotion letters, give
invited talks at major scientific conferences, give departmental colloquia,
and the like.
In sum, the various fields of science construct a system for enforcing
conformity. Scientists who do not conform are "out." But other mechanisms come
into play that not only reward scientists for divergent views, but actually
encourage the scientists to diverge even more, even to the point of
irresponsibility.
ENCOURAGING NONCONFORMITY TO THE CROWD AMONG SCIENTISTS
If scientists received no rewards at all for nonconformity, they might
cease to be nonconformists. But there are at least three major sources of
rewards for nonconfonnists.
1.Internal Rewards. Scientists who state what they believe and then fight
for their beliefs have the satisfaction of knowing that they are saying and
doing what they believe in. They can also hope that, in the long term, the
scientific establishment will come around to their way of thinking and reward
what they are doing. In fact, such changes are not unusual. In their writings,
both Sandra Scarr and Robert Plomin have commented on how behavior-genetic
work that was devalued in the 1970s came to be valued by the latter half of
the 1990s.
2.Fringe Groups. Fringe groups of scientists may set up their own
organizations to reward what they are doing, or may find that their work is
ideologically consistent with the priorities of political or social fringe
groups and thus accepted and even welcomed by such groups. Such scientists may
therefore find themselves having to decide whether to associate with these
groups in order to feel extrinsically rewarded. But these groups may in turn
encourage the scientists to take positions even more extreme than those they
believe in, and perhaps to take positions that are irresponsible.
3.The Media. By far the most powerful ally of the nonconforming scientist
in this country can end up being the media. The media thrive on controversy
and on the offbeat. Thus if virtually all scientists believe that AIDS is
caused by the human immunodeficiency virus (HIV) and a few scientists do not
believe this to be the case, the disbelievers may find themselves actually
getting more media attention because of the divergence of their views. If most
people believe that racial differences in psychometrically measured
intelligence are largely environmental and a few scientists believe (or are
willing publicly to state) that such differences are probably largely genetic,
the views of the minority are likely to attract attention. Moreover, even if
most of these scientists' views are conventional, it is the unconventional
part of their views that is likely to attract the media attention.
The situation can become pernicious because media attention tends to be
short-lived. Unfortunately, almost the only way for nonmainstream scientists
to maintain media attention and the extrinsic reinforcement it brings is
either to take new unconventional positions, or to become more extreme in the
positions they already have taken. Many of us scientists who have worked with
the media have found reporters trying to get us to make statements more
extreme than we really believe, simply because such statements make for more
interesting press coverage. The reinforcement system thus can turn a
nonconforming but responsible scientist into a less responsible or even an
irresponsible one. Worse, it may be only through the media that one can gain
any coverage of one's divergent views. Iced out of mainstream science,
scientists with nonconforming views may thus turn to the media to get press
coverage of their views, not fully realizing the dangerous game into which
they are entering. Of course, the press coverage further "turns off'" the
so-called respectable scientists, so that what formerly might have been a bad
situation with regard to the scientist's participation in mainstream science
becomes an even worse one.
THE ROLE OF DEFIANCE OF THE CROWD IN SCIENCE
Defiance of the crowd in a Thanksgiving parade is rather innocuous. In
science, defiance of the crowd has higher stakes. Elsewhere, Todd Lubart and I
have proposed that defiance of the crowd is the hallmark of creativity
(Sternberg & Lubart, 1991, 1995). Individuals in science or any other field
who make the most difference are those who defy the crowd. These individuals
generate ideas that, like stocks with low price-earnings (PE) ratios, seem
unattractive and even repugnant to others. The individuals work to raise the
value of their metaphorical stocks, attempting to convince other people of the
value of their ideas. Ultimately, they metaphorically "sell high," moving on
to their next unpopular idea.
In our work, we give numerous examples of how initial receptions to
creative ideas are often unfavorable and even patently hostile (Sternberg &
Lubart, 1995). Scientists have developed a number of ways to ensure that
scientists follow the crowd.
What's the problem, then? Why not just institute some kind of guarantee
that scientists who defy the crowd will be rewarded rather than punished? The
problem stems from the fact that creativity is typically defined not only in
terms of novelty, but also in terms of quality and appropriateness. In terms
of the stock-market analogy, one needs to remember that many and probably most
low P-E stocks never do rise much in value. Consider the example of HIV and
AIDS.
The scientist who denies that the human immunodeficiency virus causes AIDS
takes a large risk. He will be disparaged by other scientists for defying the
crowd. But if he can show to their satisfaction or that of others who hold
power in the society that he is correct, then he may actually end up being a
hero. In the case of the HIV opposition, no such demonstration has emerged.
Nor has any credible science emerged from the efforts of proponents of cold
fusion. In both cases, novelty without perceived quality has led proponents of
offbeat views to be labeled not as creative, but rather, as crackpots.
Creative people, of course, are risk-takers, but they tend to be sensible
risk-takers (Sternberg & Lubart, 1995). They are willing to take risks that,
in the long run, are more likely to pay off. The risks taken by proponents of
the theory that HIV does not cause AIDS and of the theory of cold fusion have,
to date at least, failed.
THE CASE OF ARTHUR JENSEN
Where does Arthur Jensen fit into the schema that has been set up in this
article? First, most of Jensen's career has been outside mainstream science.
Since his article almost 30 years ago in the Harvard Educational Review
(Jensen, 1969), Jensen has been viewed by many as outside mainstream science.
This fact is ironic, because the overwhelming majority of his articles and
books have been within mainstream science. Jensen's work on reaction time and
intelligence (e.g., Jensen, 1982) is solidly within the information-processing
tradition. Jensen's work on test bias (Jensen, 1980) is solidly within the
psychometric tradition, as is his work on the g factor (Jensen, 1998). Thus,
what constitutes a relatively small proportion of his work has, for the
majority of the scientific community, defined him. As noted in an invitation
letter to this symposium that "he has received very little official
recognition for his work and probably will not in the future" (Detterman,
1997), Jensen's defiance of the scientific crowd has cost him. Awards and
recognitions that he otherwise might have received for influential, highly
cited work may never come.
Second, Jensen has been courted both by political fringe groups and by the
press. Not despite but rather because of the unpopularity of his views, Jensen
has been a media figure to an extent that is rare in mainstream psychology.
Few psychologists are as well known, and some who perhaps are, such as the
late Richard Herrnstein, are known for much the same reason -- not for their
mainstream work (in Herrnstein's case, on animal learning), but for their work
on race, heritability, and intelligence.
Scientifically, I disagree with most of the corpus of Jensen's work for
reasons that are not relevant to this article but are discussed elsewhere
(e.g., Sternberg, 1985, l996b). But in terms of the criteria by which I
believe scientific work should be judged -- such as creativity, basis in
theory, empirical rigor, and impact -- I believe that most of Jensen's work
fares well. The corpus of Jensen's psychometric work on the general factor and
of his information-processing work on reaction time -- but not of his behavior
genetic work, including work on racial differences.-- place him as one of the
outstanding leaders in the field of human intelligence. Indeed, few people now
alive have had more impact on the field, for better or worse. And few people
studying human intelligence have more scientific investigations to their
credit. Indeed, much of the highly cited work in the field of intelligence has
little or, arguably, no scientific basis at all.
I exclude from this accolade Jensen's work on behavior genetics and racial
differences in intelligence because, for a number of reasons discussed
elsewhere (e.g., Sternberg, I 996b), I believe this work to be not only wrong,
but wrong-headed. My goal here, though, is not to discuss substantive
differences, but rather, how a field should evaluate scientific work that
defies the crowd.
Arthur Jensen is, in my opinion, an epitome of the need to change the
reward system in science. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that many other
scientists believed as I do that Jensen's work on information processing and
on psychometrics has been ground-breaking but his work on behavior genetics
has not been, or even has been regressive. How does the reward system
function?
Much of the way the academic reward system functions -- not just in science
-- is by the reputation of the academic (Caplow & McGee, 1958). When
reputation is viewed unidimensionally or almost unidimensionally, the field
may find itself forced into judgments it should not make. If one body of work
within a corpus is disfavored, scientists may end up generalizing this
disfavor unfairly to other work by the same investigator.
At times, some kind of combination formula with regard to the bases of
evaluation is inevitable. For example, when a department has just one
available slot for a job and someone must be hired, a hard choice must be made
despite the fact that an idiographic model of evaluating candidates might seem
much more appropriate than a nomothetic model. But many decisions need not be
unidimensional.
Many and probably most major scientific awards are to individuals for the
cumulative corpus of their work. As a result, a scientist who has done even
one stream of unpopular work may find him or herself iced out of the awards
system because this work damages -- rightfully or wrongfully -- the valuation
given to the overall corpus or work. Perhaps a better way to grant recognition
would be to a program of work, with the individual rather than the work being
seen as incidental. Thus, instead of giving an award to Scientist X for
Research Program A, the award would be given to Research Program A -- not
necessarily the whole corpus of a scientist's work -- with the scientist
receiving the award incidentally. The focus would be on the work, not on the
scientist. In the case of Jensen, one could recognize the value of his work on
reaction time or the general factor without recognizing the value of other
work. In the case of Cattell, one would reward the work, say, on the theory of
fluid and crystallized intelligence or on the 16-personality factor theory
irrespective of what Cattell's personal beliefs might be.
In some cases, judgments of work are being influenced not by portions of
the person's work, but by judgments of the person's character with respect to
things that arguably have nothing to do with the work. Cattell's religion is a
case in point. A more extreme example is Paul DeMan. The work of Paul DeMan,
in particular, and deconstructionism in general, are undergoing a thorough
reexamination in light of fairly recent discoveries that DeMan wrote
virulently anti-Semitic tracts in his youth. Such tracts certainly may and
probably must greatly damage our evaluation of DeMan as a person. But Richard
Wagner the composer and Ezra Pound the poet were also virulent anti-Semites.
Their work stands as it was, regardless of how personally despicable either or
both of them likely may have been. It would probably be a loss to the world if
Wagner's and Pound's works were ignored because of their despicable personal
views or because of their deeply flawed personal characteristics.
If we are to believe Gardner (1993), many creative individuals have had
much less than savory personal characteristics. There is good reason to judge
people and their work separately, and then to judge people's distinct programs
of work separately. Indeed, almost every creative individual has produced work
of which he or she is, at best, not proud, and at worst, ashamed (or should
be).
CONCLUSION
Science has a number of ways of enforcing adherence to the dictates of the
crowd. Scientists who choose to defy the crowd can still gain reinforcement,
but when it comes from others, it is often in the form of temptations that can
lead the scientist down a path to irresponsibility. Scientists would do better
if they focused their evaluations not on individuals, but on programs of work
within the total corpus of the scientists' work. In this way, people whose
work is viewed as undesirable in some ways are not punished so that neither
they nor other work they may do is taken seriously.
In the case of Arthur Jensen, I believe that a large body of his work is
deserving of great commendation (although I disagree with most of it). I hope
it is for his work on information processing and the general factor that he is
remembered, not for his work on behavior genetics, test bias, or racial
differences in intelligence and related traits.
If there is anything for which citizens of a country should give thanks on
Thanksgiving Day, it is not that they can join a parade, but that they can
choose to walk, at the very least, away from it, and at best, in opposition to
it.
Acknowledgements: Preparation of this article was supported under the
Javits act program (Grant R206R5000 I) as administered by the Office of
Educational Research and Improvement, U.S. Department of Education. The
findings and opinions expressed in this article do not necessarily reflect the
positions or policies of the Office of Educational Research and Improvement or
the U.S. Department of Education.
-------------------
The "Jensen Effect" and the "Spearman-Jensen Hypothesis" of Black-White IQ
Differences by J. PHILIPPE RUSHTON, University of Western Ontario
Arthur Jensen's research on the biological basis of mental ability has
culminated in his encyclopedic new work The g Factor (1998) which massively
confirms "Spearman's (1927) hypothesis" that Black-White IQ differences vary
systematically as a function of each test's g loading. More generally, The g
Factor consolidates the psychometric, neurophysiological, behavior genetic,
and comparative evidence for the existence and importance of g and links it to
evolutionary processes. But perhaps Jensen's greatest legacy to science will
be his pioneering method of correlated vectors which subsumes, under a much
broader principle, his famous (1969a) hypothesis about the heritability of the
Black-White IQ gap and, as Osborne (1980) dubbed it. the "Spearman-Jensen
hypothesis" that Black-White IQ differences are greatest on the g-factor.
Jensen's method of correlated vectors demonstrates that g (specifically a
test's g loading) is the best predictor of that test's correlation with a
given variable, in future, when a significant correlation occurs between
g-factor loadings and variable X, the result might usefully be called a
"Jensen Effect" (for that X variable). because otherwise there is no name for
it, only a long explanation of how the effect was achieved. Naming it the
"Jensen Effect" would honor one of the greatest psychologists of our time.
A Personal Note
Perhaps I am the only psychologist of my generation who missed the
tumultuous appearance of Arthur Jensen's (1969a) famous Harvard Educational
Review article arguing that IQ is heritable and that genetic factors are
involved in the Black-White IQ gap. The attendant brouhaha failed to reach my
attention in England where I was an undergraduate student at the University of
London. Two years later, however, when Hans Eysenck popularized Jensen's
argument in his 1971 book Race, Intelligence, and Education, I was a graduate
student at the London School of Economics and Political Science, and Eysenck's
book created such a furor that a small group of us social psychologists
decided to study the issue. Jensen's clearly argued response to seven
"replies," as well as his original exposition (all usefully compiled in an
offprint series by the Harvard University Press) led some of us to believe
that he might well be right.
Jensenism, described as one of the great heresies of 20th century science,
continued to inspire heated debate at the London School of Economics for the
next two years, culminating in a physical assault on Professor Eysenck when he
came to give us a lecture in 1973 on "The Biological Basis of Intelligence." I
was more than just a horrified witness to this 'political action' by a dozen
Maoists (proudly sporting red Mao-Tse Tung badges in their lapels). I was even
featured in a newspaper photograph in a scrum around Eysenck, energetically
pulling at rampaging 'demonstrators,' but wearing the fashionably long hair of
the time, it might not be obvious from the photograph whose side I was on! The
Maoists made no attempt to hide after Eysenck was hustled away, for the police
were not to be called and there was an unfortunate sentiment that Eysenck only
got what he deserved. "No Enemies on the Left" was a mantra at the L.S.E. in
the early 1970s.
The first time I heard Jensen speak in person was at the 1978 annual
meeting of the American Psychological Association in Toronto where he (1979)
presented "g: Outmoded Theory or Unconquered Frontier?" The science was
inspirational, all about reaction-time and speed-of-processing correlates of
IQ. The large ballroom was filled to overflow and the audience, rapt with
attention, burst into enthusiastic applause when he had finished. If only in
contrast to anxious expectations, the 'infamous Dr. Jensen' struck me as warm,
humane, and giving of one of the most exciting talks I had ever heard.
I eventually met Jensen in early 1981 while spending a term as a Visiting
Scholar at Berkeley's Institute of Human Development. Having just written a
book explaining altruism from a social learning perspective (Rushton, 1980),.
I was broadening my focus to encompass behavioral genetic and sociobiological
viewpoints. Although many of those at the Institute of Human Development had
earned international reputations for documenting the early emergence of
personality traits and their power to predict social adjustment, few were
interested in searching for behavior genetic causes. The reason was not hard
to find. At Berkeley, any discussi
[... missing part ...]
ervous hop, skip, and a jump away from Jensen's controversial racial
hypothesis.
Jensen occupied an office in the School of Education, one floor up from my
office in the psychology department. We easily established rapport. The
question of race differences was beginning to fascinate me and on this topic,
of course, Jensen was most informative. Over several lunches at Pasand, one of
his favorite local Indian restaurants, he sketched out his views and helpfully
answered queries. Back at his office he provided reprints. It was clear that
Jensen's defining trait was intellectual curiosity and for him the study of
race differences presented an acid test. How could the topic, which loomed so
large in education and society, be avoided for ideological reasons if
psychology was to be scientific and if the individual scientist was to
maintain personal integrity? I came away profoundly influenced and determined
to read the relevant literature.
International Distribution of IQ, Brain Size, and Related, Traits
Many researchers were inspired by "Jensenism." Lynn (1978, 1982) and Vernon
(1982) not only pushed the envelope, but extended the 'outside of the
envelope' and made the race-IQ debate international in scope with their
findings that East Asians average higher on tests of mental ability than do
Whites, whereas Caribbeans (and especially Africans) average lower. As Lynn's
(1997) and Jensen's (1998) most recent reviews show, East Asians, measured in
North America and in Pacific Rim countries, typically average IQs in the range
of 101 to 111. Caucasoid populations in North America, Europe, and Australasia
typically average lQs from 85 to 115 with an overall mean of 100. African
populations living south of the Sahara, in North America, in the Caribbean,
and in Britain typically have mean IQs from 70 to 90. (Blacks in sub-Saharan
Africa score about 2 standard deviations [approximately 30 IQ points] below
the mean of Whites on nonverbal tests.)
As a budding sociobiologist, I too was inspired by Jensenism. It seemed to
me that by its impact on diverse areas of behavioral science, Jensenism might
help complete the Darwinian revolution. I began to review the international
literature, studying not only IQ, but other behavioral traits like speed of
physical maturation and longevity, personality and temperament, family
structure and crime, and sexual behavior and fertility, and later brain size
(Rushton, 1984a, 1984b, 1988). I have found that on these traits East Asians
are slower maturing, less fertile, less sexually active, with larger brains
and higher IQ scores than Africans, who tend towards the opposite in each of
these areas. Europeans, I found, fell between the other two groups. As Jensen
(1984) elaborated (in a commentary on my first review), a network of such
related evidence provides more opportunity for finding and testing alternative
theories than does any single dimension drawn from the set.
As a now avowed Jensenist, I carried out experiments finding, for example,
that the amount of inbreeding depression on 11 sub-tests of the Wechsler
Intelligence Scale for Children in Japan predicted the magnitude of the
Black-White differences on the same sub-tests in the U.S. (Rushton, 1989).
Inbreeding depression, a purely genetic effect, was a sufficiently robust
predictor to overcome generalization from the Japanese in Japan to Blacks and
Whites in the U.S. There really is no other explanation, other than a genetic
one, for the correlation between inbreeding depression and Black-White
differences.
I also calculated cranial capacities from external measurements of the head
using large archival data sets including a stratified random sample of 6,325
U.S. Army personnel (Rushton, 1992), a sample of tens of thousands of men and
women collected by the International Labour Office in Geneva (Rushton, 1994),
and a sample of thousands of American children from birth to age seven
(Rushton, 1997). After adjusting for the effects of stature, weight, and sex,
the cranial capacities consistently averaged higher for East Asians than for
Europeans, who averaged higher than Africans, as reviewed by Rushton and
Ankney (1996) and Jensen (1998).
Jensen's The g Factor
All the issues Jensen raised in 1969 are still with us today. Indeed, much
of the opposition to IQ testing and heritability would probably disappear if
it were not for the stubborn and unwelcome fact that, despite extensive
well-funded programs of intervention, the Black-White difference refuses to go
quietly into the night.
Jensen's long intellectual march has culminated triumphantly in his latest
book, The g Factor (1998), an exposition of the reality of Spearman's (1927)
seminal concept of g, the general factor of intelligence. Jensen's tome does
not draw back from Jensenist conclusions--that the average difference in IQ
found between Blacks and Whites has a substantial hereditary component, that
this difference is related mainly to the g-factor, and that it has important
societal consequences.
Chapter 11 of The g Factor fully documents how, on average, the American
Black population scores below the White population by about 1.2 standard
deviations, equivalent to 18 IQ points. This mean difference between Blacks
and Whites in IQ scores has scarcely changed over the past 80 years (despite
some claims that the gap is narrowing) and can be observed as early as three
years of age. Controlling for overall socioeconomic level only reduces the
mean difference by 4 IQ points. Contrary to purely cultural explanations,
culture-fair tests tend to give Blacks slightly lower scores, on the average,
than more conventional tests, as do non-verbal tests compared with verbal
tests, and abstract reasoning tests compared with tests of acquired knowledge.
The reason, in fact, that Jensen pursued Spearman's hypothesis is that it
so exquisitely solved a problem that had long perplexed him about test bias
with respect to Black-White differences. He had noted that the Black-White
differences are markedly smaller on tests of rote learning and short term
memory than on tests of reasoning and those requiring any transformation of
the information. He initially formalized these observations in his so-called
Level I-Level II theory (Jensen, 1968). Level I tasks were those that required
little or no mental manipulation of the input to arrive at the correct output.
A clear example of Level I ability is Forward Digit Span in which people
recall a series of digits in the same order as that in which they are
presented. Level II tasks, however, require some mental manipulation of the
input in order to arrive at the appropriate response. A clear example of Level
II ability is Backward Digit Span in which people recall a series of digits in
the reverse order to that in which they are presented. Jensen found that
Black-White differences are twice as large for Backward as for Forward Digit
Span. As this finding did not readily lend itself to an explanation in terms
of cultural bias or in terms of any other theory Jensen knew of except his
Level I-Level II notion, he kept thinking about it.
After Jensen re-read Spearman, he realized that his Level I-Level II
formulation was only a special case of the more general hypothesis proposed by
Spearman. Jensen began testing Spearman's hypothesis on a wide variety of
psychometric tests administered to large representative samples of the
American White and Black populations (Jensen, 1985, 1987). The g Factor
summarizes the results from 17 independent data sets on a total of nearly
45,000 Blacks and 245,000 Whites derived from 171 psychometric tests. g
loadings consistently predict the magnitude of the Black-White difference (r =
+.63). Spearman's hypothesis is borne out even among three-year-olds
administered eight sub-tests of the Stanford-Binet. The rank correlation
between g loadings and the Black-White differences is +.71 (p <.05).
Spearman's hypothesis applies even to the g factor extracted from
performance on elementary cognitive tasks. In some of these studies,
9-to-12-year-olds are asked to decide which of several lights is illuminated
and move their hand to press a button that turns that light off. All children
can perform such tasks in less than one second, but children with higher IQ
scores perform faster than do those with lower scores, and White children, on
average, perform faster than Black children (Vernon & Jensen, 1984). The
correlations between the g loadings of these types of reaction time tasks and
the Black-White differences range from +.70 to +.8l.
Jensen also applied Spearman's hypothesis to East Asian-White comparisons,
using the same reaction time measures. The direction of the correlation is
opposite to that in the Black-White studies, indicating that, on average, East
Asians score higher in g than do whites. No one so far seems to have looked at
East Asian-White differences on conventional psychometric tests as a function
of their g loadings. From the study just mentioned, however, Jensen's
prediction should be clear: One should find the mirror image of Spearman's
hypothesis for Black-White differences. It might be interesting to note, in
light of the above, that in an early reply to a charge of "white supremacy,"
Jensen (l969b, p. 240) made a remarkably presaging conjecture, He wrote: ". .
.if I were asked to hypothesize about race differences in what we call g or
abstract reasoning ability, I should be inclined to rate Caucasians on the
whole somewhat below Orientals, at least in the United States."
The Spearman-Jensen Hypothesis
Osborne (1980) suggested that if scientific credit was to be assigned
appropriately, the "Spearman hypothesis" that Black-White differences are
greater on more g-loaded sub-tests should become the "Spearman-Jensen
hypothesis" because it was Jensen who brought Spearman's hypothesis to
widespread attention, and it was Jensen who did all the empirical work
confirming it. Jensen (1997) himself has noted that, "Because Spearman himself
never presented it as a formal hypothesis, a few people have objected to my
crediting it to Spearman. So whenever I say 'Spearman's hypothesis,' I hope
you will visualize these words in quotation marks."
The Jensen Effect
The Spearman-Jensen hypothesis turns out to be readily subsumable under a
more general principle that, when resulting in a positive finding, we might
call a "Jensen Effect." Recall that the Spearman-Jensen hypothesis was tested
by first extracting the g factor from a variety of cognitive tests, and then
relating these scores (a 'vector' of scores, i.e., with direction as well as
quantity), to the mean Black-White differences on those same tests (a second
'vector' of scores). Jensen extended this method of correlated vectors to a
variety of variables. Using this procedure, Jensen (1998) showed that the
vector of a test's g loadings is the best predictor of that test's correlation
with a variety of variables, including not only scholastic and work-place
performance, but also brain size, brain pH, brain glucose metabolic rate,
average evoked potential, reaction time, and other physiological factors. The
Jensen Effect can be seen whenever there is a significant correlation between
the vector of the sub-tests' g loadings and the vector of the same sub-tests'
loadings on variable X (where X is some other, usually non-psychometric
variable).
This methodological innovation of Jensen's may be an even greater discovery
than the totality of empirical results generated by it, important though these
undoubtedly are. His method of correlated vectors is fully explicated in The g
Factor (Appendix B) and is also discussed in the opening remarks of this
symposium. To honor Jensen's accomplishments into the future, I propose that
when a significant correlation occurs between the two vectors the result be
called a Jensen Effect (for that X variable), because otherwise there is no
name for it, only a long explanation of how the effect was achieved.
Chapter 12 of The g Factor presents Jensen's technical arguments for why he
believes that race differences are about 50% genetic in origin. He emphasizes
the fact that it is precisely those components of intelligence tests that are
most heritable and that most relate to brain size which most profoundly
differentiate Black from White groups. The heritability data are especially
interesting because genetic theory and culture theories of race differences
make predictions opposite to each other. Culture theory predicts that
differences between races will be greater on those culturally malleable items
on which races can grow apart as a result of dissimilar experiences.
The g Factor also cites the evidence of transracial adoption studies. Three
studies have been carried out on Korean and Vietnamese children adopted into
White American and White Belgian homes. Though many had been hospitalized for
malnutrition, prior to adoption, they went on to develop IQs ten or more
points higher than their adoptive national norms. By contrast, Black and
mixed-race (Black-White) children adopted into White middle-class families
typically perform at a lower level than similarly adopted white children. In
the well known Minnesota Transracial Adoption Study, by age 17, adopted
children with two White biological parents had an average IQ of 106, adopted
children with one Black and one white biological parent averaged an IQ of 99,
and adopted children with two Black biological parents had an average IQ of 89
(which is not different from that of Black children raised by Black parents in
these northwestern states).
The g Factor also devotes a fair amount of space to racial differences in
brain size. Chapter 6 reviews the literature which shows that the brain-size
IQ relation emerges most clearly using Magnetic Resonance Imaging (r = .44
across eight separate studies). Chapter 12 documents the three-way racial
gradient in brain size established by aggregating data from studies using four
kinds of measurements: (a) wet brain weight at autopsy, (b) volume of empty
skulls using filler, (c) volume estimated from external head sizes, and (d)
volume estimated from external head measurements and corrected for body size.
East Asians and their descendants average about 17 cm3 (1 in3) larger brain
volumes than do Europeans and their descendants, whose brains average about 80
cm3 (5 in3) larger than do those of Africans and their descendants. Jensen
(1998, pp. 442-443) calculated an "ecological" correlation (used in
epidemiological studies) of +0.998 between median IQ and mean cranial capacity
across the three populations of "Mongoloids," "Caucasoids," and "Negroids."
Finally, The g Factor considers the race differences from an evolutionary
perspective. Jensen accepts the "Out-of-Africa" theory, that Homo sapiens
arose in Africa about 100,000 years ago, expanded beyond Africa after that,
and then migrated east after a European/East Asian split about 40,000 years
ago. Since evolutionary selection pressures were different in the hot savanna
where Africans evolved than in the cold Arctic where Mongoloids evolved, these
ecological differences had not only morphological, but also behavioral
effects. The farther north the populations migrated 'Out of Africa,' the more
they encountered the cognitively demanding problems of gathering and storing
food, gaining shelter, making clothes, and raising children during prolonged
winters. As these populations evolved into present-day Europeans and East
Asians, they underwent selective pressure for larger brains.
The g Factor's strong conclusion about race differences in fact came as
something of a suprise to me. In all my discussions with Jensen about race
differences since 1981, I had been struck by his careful circumspection. More
than once he went so far as to say that he doubted that methods were available
for determining whether Black-White differences were heritable (including the
methods of behavior genetics). As best I recall, he said something like: "We
can never 'prove' for certain that the race differences in IQ are heritable in
the sense that we can 'prove' something in mathematics. All empirical science
can do is increase the probability that genetic factors are involved."
Pushing Out the Envelope Even Further
Science is a never ending journey and Jensenism has traveled far since
1969. With regard to the significance of brain size, for example, early on,
Jensen described brain size as unrelated to IQ (1969a, p. 73; 1973, p. 333,
349), and did not cite the literature on racial differences in brain size.
Somewhat later, in Bias in Mental Testing (1980), he cited Van Valen's (1974)
re-assessment of the literature showing a +.30 correlation between brain size
and IQ along with a Table from Hooton (1939) showing a linear relation between
head size and socioeconomic status. By 1984, Jensen cited Ho, Roessmann,
Straumfjord, and Monroe's (1980) autopsy studies showing a Black-White brain
weight difference of about 100 grams and outlined a variety of ways to examine
relations between race, brain-size, and IQ. By the time of The g Factor,
Jensen's own studies had shown that head size was related to IQ even
within-families, that the head size/IQ relationship occurred on the most
g-loaded tests, that Blacks and Whites differed in head size, and that the
Black and White differences in head size disappeared when Blacks and Whites
were matched for IQ.
The conclusion that there are racial differences in average brain size is
becoming accepted. For example, Ulric Neisser, Chair of the recent American
Psychological Association's Task Force Report on The Bell Curve (Neisser et
al., 1996) acknowledged that, with respect to "racial differences in the mean
measured sizes of skulls and brains (with East Asians having the largest,
followed by Whites and then Blacks). . . .there is indeed a small overall
trend" (Neisser, 1997, p. 80).
From the beginning, Jensenism did not stop with IQ. For example, Jensen (1
969a, p. 86) cited studies showing the early development of motor behavior in
Black infants with some Black samples at six months of age scoring nearly one
standard deviation above White norms. Paralleling the behavioral precocity,
Jensen (1969a, p. 87) reported evidence of faster bone development in Black
infants (established using X-rays) and earlier maturation of brain wave
patterns (measured using EEGs). Soon after, Jensen (1973: 289-290) suggested
that race differences in the production of two-egg twins, being most common
among Blacks and least common among East Asians, with Caucasians intermediate,
"may be a reflection of evolutionary age." In a long footnote, he wrote:
"[T]he three racial groups lie on a developmental continuum on which the
Caucasian group is more or less intermediate. A related fact is that there is
an inverse relationship throughout the phylogenetic hierarchy between the
tendency for multiple births and the prolongation of immaturity."
As a committed Jensenist, I pursued these hypotheses with vigor and
proposed a gene based "life-history theory" familiar to evolutionary
biologists as the r-K scale of reproductive strategy to account for the racial
trade-off between brain size and egg-production, and other variables (Rushton,
1995). At one end of this scale r-strategies emphasize high reproductive rates
while at the other K-strategies emphasize high levels of parental investment.
This scale is generally used to compare the life histories of widely disparate
species, but I used it to describe the immensely smaller variations within the
human species. Following Jensen's trail I went on to hypothesize that
Mongoloid people are, on average, more K-selected than Caucasoids, who in turn
are more K-selected than Negroids. My book Race, Evolution, and Behavior
documents the reality of racial differences in over 60 physical and behavioral
traits.
Conclusion
In recent years, the equalitarian dogma has run headlong into some very bad
karma. In the wake of the success of The Bell Curve (Herrnstein & Murray,
1994), and other recent books that provide race-realist answers to the
question of differential group achievement, there has been an intense effort
to get the 'race genie' that Jensen's l969 Harvard Educational Review paper
loosed safely back in the bottle, to squeeze the previously tabooed toothpaste
back in the tube. By firmly establishing the psychometric, neurophysiological,
behavior genetic, and comparative evidence for the existence and importance of
Spearman's g, Jensen's The g Factor makes it near certain that such
obscurantist efforts will end up shredded by Occam's razor.
----------------------
On Arthur Jensen's Integrity by SANDRA SCARR, University of Virginia,
emerita
Few psychologists have engendered the controversy or endured the abuse that
Arthur Jensen has in the past three decades. His adamant adherence to a
hard-edged science and an uncompromising personal integrity have led to
notoriety. Although these virtues might be rewarded, if applied to less
controversial topics. Art Jensen has been vilified because he applied his
standards to the most important and painful social issues of our day. In this
article, I admire his ethics but trace the negative reactions he evoked. His
legacy to psychological science goes beyond important studies on choice
reaction times and intelligence, environmental effects on intelligence, and
race differences in mental development: Art Jensen set a standard for an
honest psychological science.
For more than 40 years, Arthur Jensen has unflinchingly strived to make
psychology an honest science. My emphasis is on both words, honest, and
science. For this alone, I would admire him enormously, but there is much more
to admire about Art's lifework, which continues unabated by his official
retirement. Besides his intellectual mentor, Robert Thorndike, and a few other
pillars, such as Lee Cronbach, Robert Woodworth, and Lewis Terman, Arthur
Jensen's contributions tower above educational psychology and psychometrics.
The Scientist
As his own essay (this issue) demonstrates, Art relentlessly pursues a
hard-edged, hypothetic-deductive science that treads on a more emotional,
humanistic psychology. Art has no sympathy for mushy thinking. For him,
impressions and feelings are not data and have no place in psychology, beyond
perhaps the hypothesis-formation stage. Art is ruthlessly scientific: If
hypotheses derived from a theory cannot be tested by logical experimentation
and data analysis, the theory does not deserve to be called psychological
science.
Art rejects convenient compromises and politically expedient obfuscation.
These virtues have not been universally appreciated. I have never known him to
evade a controversy or mollify an opponent, when the intellectual stakes are
high. Outspoken and bloodlessly calm in the face of threats, Art confronts the
most emotional critics with logical argument and polite disdain. He remains
agnostic where data do not drive him to a conclusion, and his agnosticism on
matters of test bias, IQ testing, and racial differences in "g" has cost him
dearly. Even with his back to the wall, he continues to proclaim the facts, as
he sees them.
He exposes intellectual dishonesty in whomever he finds it, and there is
plenty of intellectual dishonesty to find among our Politically Correct
colleagues. Art is an important player in battles against the kind of naive
environmentalism that has squashed constructive, scientific contributions from
psychologists to the most important educational issues of our time, from Head
Start to special education to university entrance requirements. Although we
are both infamous for exposing naked Emperors, I may be just a tiny bit more
tolerant of the bleeding-hearts among us -- a weakness that has saved me from
much of the abuse he has suffered.
Research Contributions
Art's own studies of learning processes and "g" unwaveringly follow models
derived from physical sciences. Psychological science consists of rigorous
experiments, psychometrically credible tests, and sophisticated data analyses.
He is an unapologetic reductionist, who believes that complex processes will
always be explainable in simpler, component terms.
For Art, mind is no more than brain chemistry. In this belief, he clearly
rejects systems theories and cognitive theories of mind, in favor of
mechanistic, physical models. For those who believe that the whole may be more
than the sum of its component parts, especially in biological systems, and
that experience is constructed by minds, Art's strict adherence to physical
science model may seem anachronistic.
Determined and persistent, Art followed several lines of research on
learning and intelligence. To my mind, his three most important research
contributions are:
1.The elegant series of studies on reaction times in complex, choice tasks;
2.His studies of older and younger siblings in California and Georgia to
test competing genetic and environmental hypotheses about racial differences
in IQ; and
3.The clever construct validity studies, matching the performance of
younger White children to that of older Black children on tasks where
Black-White difference are most prominent.
In the series of studies on reaction times, he showed that brain functions
-- speed, reliability, and capacity -- can be measured in seemingly simple
reaction time tasks that are importantly related to psychometric "g" and by
extension to many forms of academic and other life achievements. Despite
carping by critics from the narrow world of experimental psychology, Art
showed real-life implications for laboratory tasks that heretofore ha4 gone
unnoticed, except among laboratory psychologists. (I was there in Britain
where the mocking of some learning researchers was extremely distasteful to
all but the nastiest high-table fools.) In characteristic fashion, Art ignored
the ad hominem slurs and persisted to show how important their seemingly
trivial tasks really were. Art succeeded in giving psychometric "g" some
important physical correlates (he might say physical bases, but I won't go
that far). That line of research has many more miles to go.
Closer to my interests, in the second example, Art saw an opportunity for a
naturally occurring experiment -- the comparison of older and younger
siblings, as a test of competing theories about the origins of racial
differences in IQ. He reasoned logically (as always) that if environmental
deprivations were responsible for lower test scores of Blacks, then the longer
children were exposed to such environments, the more they would lag behind
test norms; that is, the lower their IQ scores would become. Older siblings
have longer exposure to such deprivations; hence, they ought to score lower on
IQ and standardized achievement test than their younger sibs. If, on the other
hand, genetic differences were primarily responsible for Black-White
differences, then no older-younger sibling differences should be observed.
Among Berkeley, CA school children, no older-younger sibling differences on
tests were observed. In poverty-stricken, rural Georgia, however, the
environmentally predicted declines in test scores were found.
More developmental psychologists are embarrassingly glib on racial
differences; Any observed Black-White difference must be due to "racism,"
social disadvantage, and other neighborhood and school features, because they
correlate with IQ. By using sibling comparisons, Art showed that such excuses
(I refuse to call them explanations) were not true in Berkeley, where exposure
to the mainstream culture is extensive for even the poorest minority children,
whereas in rural Georgia, restriction of learning opportunities explained the
sibling IQ differences. These studies showed that in really deprived rearing
circumstances, even Art Jensen can find environmental effects! Kidding aside,
these studies of sibling differences in IQ are all the more important because
Art did them. One can only hope his critics will remember to attribute them to
him.
The studies of sibling IQ differences in California and Georgia helped me
to think about what kinds of environments have negative effects on
intellectual development and which do not. Our own adoption studies found that
children adopted in infancy into working class families achieved IQ levels as
high as adoptees reared in privileged professional families, whereas
biological offspring of such families differed by 10 IQ points, on average.
Clearly, genes were the major cause of social class differences in IQ, not
whether parents take their children to ball games or museums, or whether they
listen to Country & Western tunes or to Mozart (take that,
Art-the-music-snob). These results, and Art's sibling studies, led me to stand
up for "good-enough parents," who provide loving support and learning
opportunities, but not necessarily those the intelligentsia value most. My
proposal, that most parents are "good enough" at child rearing to support
their children becoming the best they can be, provoked PC colleagues to attack
me as anti-child welfare, because surely every child needs to have parents
just like them to become the best (their self-serving snobbery is appalling
and unrecognized).
Since our working class Midwesterners were doing as good a job with their
adopted children as their highly educated compatriots, my conclusion about
"good enough" parents is logically inescapable. So is the conclusion from
Art's research; to wit, the African-American families in California did expose
their children to learning opportunities sufficient to maintain their
intellectual growth over the school years. The fact that their IQ test scores
lagged behind those of Whites is not likely to be explained by differences in
learning opportunities.
An interesting parallel to this work is our longitudinal study of
interracial adoptees. At the average of 7 years, the African-American adopted
children scored 106.1 on IQ tests. By the average age of 18 however, their IQ
scores had declined to 96.8. Children with one White and one Black parent
scored, on average, 109.0 at age 7 and 98.5 at age 18; children with two Black
parents (and later adoptive placements) scored 96.8 at age 7 and 89.4 at age
18. The test performance of the Black/Black adoptees was not different from
that of ordinary Black children reared by their own families in the same area
of the country. My colleagues and I reported the data accurately and as fully
as possible, and then tried to make the results palatable to environmentally
committed colleagues. In retrospect, this was a mistake. The results of the
transracial adoption study can be used to support either a genetic difference
hypothesis or an environmental difference one (because the children have
visible African ancestry). We should have been agnostic on the conclusions;
Art would have been.
A less recognized line of research, and one with great implications for
developmental psychology, is Art's use of younger White children to model the
test performance of older Black children. By showing that response and error
patterns of Black children matched, on average, those of White children two
years younger, Art did more than challenge the test-bias literature. He showed
that differences in test performance among age-matched White and Black
children can be most simply explained as differences in rates of mental
development. The implicit analogy to physical growth is powerful: Slower
growth rates over the same length of time lead to lesser final attainments,
whether one is speaking of height or of intelligence. The implications of
these studies are truly frightening, but Art does not flinch. I have yet to
see these findings incorporated into introductory psychology textbooks or
developmental texts, however, so the wrath of Politically Challenged has not
rained down on him yet.
Scholarly Reviews
Among his many works, those that will be most widely cited and remembered
are his rigorous reviews of data on test bias, evidence for the "g" in general
intelligence, and reviews of research on group differences in IQ and
achievement. In scholarly yet accessible prose, Art tells coherent stories
that make the best sense of complex theories and data. Along the way, he
refutes the many ad hoc claims about test bias, disposes of theories of
multiple intelligences, and lays waste to naive environmental theories of race
and social class differences in educational achievements. In a dozen
impressive books and hundreds of articles, spanning 30 years, Art has brought
uncompromising logic and scientific rigor to the most controversial topics of
our age.
In my last term at the University of Virginia, I taught an undergraduate
course on intelligence. The text was Bias in Mental Testing. At first, some
students were surprised and even alarmed that many of their assignments were
drawn from a book by that infamous Dr. Jensen. But they came to appreciate the
serious nature of the book and its helpful chapters on testing, validity,
reliability, and potential biases in mental tests. By the end of the semester,
they felt they had accomplished several feats -- to have read nearly all of
the 700+ pages and to have passed tests on the content. Another accomplishment
was their open minds about the content and the author, whom they came to
admire. It's a splendid book.
Notoriety
Art seems to have been genuinely surprised by the notoriety he attained
from his writings on race and IQ. Others cannot understand his surprise. When
one lobs hand grenades at the intelligence and potential achievements of
others, one should anticipate a violent reaction. For Art to say that only 5%
of the Harvard Education Review article concerned racial difference in IQ is
like saying the only problem Lincoln had in the time he attended Ford's
theater was the split second he was shot. Somehow, the percentage is not the
critical issue in either case.
Anticipated or not, the consequences of his notoriety were severe and
prolonged. Few can claim to be, or to have been, as sorely tested as Art has
been in defense of psychology as a science. I have witnessed his steadfastness
in the face of a screaming, unruly mob who disrupted his lecture on learning
and intelligence and threatened his personal safety. I learned what it was
like to be spat upon and to put my body on the line to get Art out of a
University of Minnesota auditorium. It was shocking and frightening, as surely
the radicals intended, but it was most of all infuriating, because no
disciplinary actions were taken against those who assaulted us. Those were the
wonderful 1970s.
As he mentions in his essay (this issue), his automobile tires were
slashed, police had to open his mail, and his office at the University of
California-Berkeley was stripped bare to protect him from a potential bomb.
Art's office at Berkeley was more like a San Quentin cell than a typically
cluttered faculty office. His family was threatened, and his personal freedoms
seriously compromised -- all because he reported his conclusions about
genetics and IQ, based on a serious scientific review of the research
literature.
By his own account, he is no extravert. Nor, I may add, did warmth and
humor soften the acrimonious exchanges he had with hostile audiences. One
might also observe that insight into his violent, enraged opponents was
lacking. The logical, unemotional Dr. Jensen would never behave in such an
uncivilized manner, nor comprehend those who do.
Art Jensen has also endured abuse from thugs with pens instead of
megaphones. Personally, I have no empathy for politically driven liars, who
distort scientific facts in a misguided and condescending effort to protect an
impossible myth about human equality (= identity). Art believes he understands
the motives of the Marcus Feldmans, Steven Jay Goulds, and Leon Kamins of the
intellectual world. They seem to speak his language, albeit with forked
tongues. I find them despicable, because they have the knowledge and intellect
to know that they deliberately corrupt science. To deny falsely the scientific
evidence that nearly all measurable human traits are moderately to highly
heritable is to deny parents and policy makers essential knowledge to run
their own lives and the society as a whole. Self-appointed saviors of the
equality myth are far more dangerous to an honest psychological science than a
hundred outraged groupies who don't know that the lecture was supposed to be
about, anyway.
All in all, with clear conscience, Art stands up for data, searches for the
most logical and supportable explanations, and rejects all of the ad hominem
garbage thrown his way.
I did observe a humorous episode with the notorious Arthur Jensen. While at
York University, we took a little stroll to a neighborhood shop, where another
customer asked me if we were from the conference on intelligence. She had
heard that the terrible Arthur Jensen was there. "I can't understand how they
could have let him in the country!," she proclaimed. With Art standing mutely
at my side, I told her that Dr. Jensen was indeed present. "Is he as awful as
they say?," she asked. "Oh yes," I said, "dreadful!"At least that's the way I
recall it.
Art Jensen's contribution to psychological science are enormous, and they
continue to mount. His work includes the impeccable tome on test bias, the
most thoughtful research on learning and intelligence, and some critical
studies on race and environment. The massive body of work will persist for
generations of psychologists. Yet, I believe that his most important
contribution is intellectual honesty and integrity to a psychological science
that is threatened with Politically Correct corruption. Art has not known how
to be politically expedient, or to couch his ideas in soothing terms, so that
he has often suffered academic rejection. But most people heard you, Art, and
they remember, even if they did not like the message. Both inside and outside
of academia, your intellectually honest legacy will prevail.
---------------
Jensen on "Jensenism" by Arthur R. Jensen
University of California, Berkeley
"Though Jensenism is a term listed in several dictionaries, Arthur Jensen
has produced a more extensive body of work than suggested by the dictionary
entry. To the public, he is mainly known for his work on the genetics of
intelligence. This article discusses the work that is publicly less well
known. Work discussed includes studies in learning, memory. the cumulative
deficit hypothesis, Spearman's hypothesis, and speed of information
processing, to name a few. The publicly better known work is also discussed. A
bibliography of Jensen's publications is included in an appendix. (Abstract
written by D. Detterman)"
To discover that one's name has entered the dictionary as an "ism" is both
flattering and embarrassing, and is cause for reflection. I know because it
happened to me. Recent editions of a number of dictionaries contain the word
"Jensenism." The Random House and Webster's Unabridged Dictionaries, for
example, contain the following entry:
Jensenism, n. the theory that an individual's IQ is largely due to
heredity, including racial heritage. [1965-1970]; after Arthur R. Jensen (born
1923), U.S. educational psychologist who proposed such a theory; see -ism] --
Jensenist, Jensenite, n., adj.
For those who understand the meaning of heritability in quantitative
genetics, the wording is rather inept and the "theory" attributed to me has
been around at least since the time of Francis Galton (1822-1911), whose
Hereditary Genius (1869) predated the very article that led the popular press
to label me a "hereditarian" by exactly one century. The dictionary definition
can't be overly derided, however, as it is quite true that, in 1969, I did
present a fairly comprehensive review of the evidence that IQ is substantially
heritable and had stated that it is a reasonable hypothesis that genetic as
well as environmental factors are involved in the well documented Black-White
average difference in IQ. Also, I like to think that I was partly responsible
for getting Galtonian thinking back on track in differential psychology after
it had been derailed in the behavioral sciences for at least a generation
following World War II (the period dominated by what Sandra Scarr once
referred to as "naive environmentalism").
However, the more serious disadvantage of having one's name turned into an
"ism" is that, from that moment on, one is liable to be identified only as the
"ism" in the dictionary. The rest of one's research activity can be unfairly
eclipsed, and findings and formulations that are unique and perhaps even
fundamentally more important are forgotten. One of my aims here is to
forestall this threatened eclipse of other aspects of my research and shine
some light on how that which got me labeled as an "ism" fits into the larger
orbit of my lifetime's work.
Essentially, I have always been a differential psychologist. Human
idiosyncracies and individual differences in behavior interested me before I
had ever heard of psychology. The first book I read on the subject, more or
less by accident while in high school, was J.B. Watson's Psychology From the
Standpoint of a Behaviorist (1929). It was probably the main reason I chose to
major in psychology in college, after reluctantly but realistically deciding
not to pursue a career in music. Though I became acquainted with some
well-known psychologists, such as Edward Tolman and Egon Brunswik, as an
undergraduate psychology major at Berkeley, the one psychologist whose work
most captured my attention (but whom I never saw in person) was the then
Sterling Professor of Psychology at Yale, Clark L. Hull, a latter-day
Watsonian and Pavlovian behaviorist. One could say that I became a Hullian,
and I recall writing a long term paper for one of my courses extolling Hull's
theory of learning -- excessively so, according to the comments of the TA (one
of Edward Tolman's graduate students) who graded my paper. Primed, I suppose,
by Watson, I was especially attracted to Hull's purely mechanistic system for
explaining behavior, as spelled out in his Principles of Behavior (1942). B.F.
Skinner's Behavior of Organisms (1938) was also appealing but lacked the
systematic theoretical system that made Hull's approach seem more promising to
me.
I was totally unaware at the time that these now classic works in
psychology, and indeed my whole undergraduate education in psychology,
neglected individual differences and the influence of genetic factors on
behavior. These topics were scarcely admitted as part of the field of
psychology, at least as it was presented at Berkeley in the 1 940s.
Experimental psychology dominated the department at that time, and the
implicit assumption of experimental psychology was that individual differences
in the behavioral realm originated entirely outside the organism, through its
exposure to different environmental contingencies, and they could be
explained, if one were at all interested in doing so, in the purely
stimulus-response-reinforcement terms of conditioning and learning. In its
focus on discovering general laws or principles of behavior, experimental
psychology traditionally treated individual differences as a nuisance
variable, or as merely error variance in the statistical analyses of its data.
This limited perspective of my undergraduate courses in psychology was
extremely implicit and so completely taken for granted that it did not enter
my consciousness until some years later. I occasionally meet psychologists
even today who think of individual differences as error variance or as purely
a product of environmental diversity. I was still largely operating on this
assumption in 1964 when I wrote a major paper that attempted to explain social
class differences in scholastic learning entirely in terms of the then current
S-R theories and principles of verbal learning (67). Ironically, the
publication of that paper was so long-delayed that it appeared after my
position on the major basis of individual and group differences had changed in
a hereditarian direction. Large differences in the publication lag of one's
articles and book chapters during certain periods may even create a false
impression of contradictory vacillations in one's theoretical stance. The
publication dates of one's articles are not always perfectly correlated with
the actual chronology of one's changing position on theoretical issues.
Thanks to the beautiful "recreational reading" room (the Morrison Library)
on the Berkeley campus, where I spent most of my evenings, I believe I got as
much or more of my undergraduate education from entirely self-selected
extracurricular reading as I got from my courses and textbooks. The most
lasting influence I recall are works by M.K. Gandhi, Bertrand Russell, G.B.
Shaw, Havelock Ellis, H.G. Wells, Aldous Huxley, Alfred Korzybski, and
biographies of famous musicians, scientists, and philosophers. They instilled
a certain critical sense as well as a humanistic idealism that, in the long
run, made a greater impression on me than did most of the relatively
uninspiring textbooks I was required to read in my courses. To make more time
for the reading I most liked, it was my policy never to read anything in my
college textbooks more than once.
It was my extracurricular reading, probably more than anything else, that
led me to look for the ways psychological science might have practical
applications that could benefit individuals and society. Some years later when
I decided to enter graduate school to work toward a Ph.D., I examined various
university catalogues to see what they offered in applied psychology. I
recognized more of the names of psychologists whose works in applied areas,
such as clinical and educational psychology, that I had already come across in
my reading on faculty of Teachers College, Columbia University than in any
other university catalogue. Egon Brunswik's course on the history of
psychology had also left me with a distinct impression of Columbia as having
one of the pioneer departments of psychology, shaped by such luminaries as
James McKeen Cattell, E.L. Thorndike, and Robert Woodworth. (When I arrived at
Columbia, Woodworth was still lecturing at age 87, and I audited his two
courses.) The fact that Columbia University is located in New York City, home
to Carnegie Hall, Toscanini and the NBC Symphony, the New York Philharmonic,
and the Metropolitan Opera, provided a powerful added attraction. The musical
capital of America, New York is visited each year by many of the world's
greatest orchestras, conductors, and virtuosos. And my interest in music has
never been second to my interest in psychology, though I have necessarily
devoted more time to the latter, of course, since it has been my livelihood.
When I wasn't on the Columbia campus, chances are I was hanging out in
Carnegie Hall, either at a concert or a rehearsal.
At Columbia's TC I studied educational, clinical, and personality
psychology. My Ph.D. dissertation (under Professor Percival Symonds) was on
the Thematic Apperception Test as a measure of aggression (2,3). 1 found my
three years as Symonds' research assistant much to my liking. However, my
interest in the subject of his research at that time, based on the
psychoanalytic or "dynamic" interpretation of various projective techniques
(8, 20), proved short-lived. Though Symonds was a man of noble character and
in many ways a fine mentor, my three years at TC were probably influenced more
by the lingering shadow of the psychologist who had been Symonds' mentor but
who had died three years before I arrived at TC -- Edward L. Thorndike,
probably America's greatest psychologist. Thomdike's influence and his
conception of psychology still pervaded the intellectual atmosphere at TC
during my tenure and was repeatedly reinforced by an imposing portrait of the
great man that hung on the wall above the card-catalogues in the TC library. I
felt compelled to read some of Thorndike's books and I liked them a lot,
especially for their clear thinking and their objective and empirically
anchored approach to the remarkably broad range of subject matter in
psychology with which he dealt.
It is amazing how much of what today is viewed as established fact in
psychology was either discovered or presaged by E.L. Thorndike. As he was one
of the leading pioneers of psychology as a natural science, he became the
first of my "heroes" in psychology; the other two (Galton and Spearman) I
discovered a few years later. These are the three psychologists whose key
works I return to and re-read for their wealth of hypotheses, original and
insightful ideas, and inspiration, always to be rewarded. If there have been
any authentic geniuses in the history of scientific psychology, in my
estimation they include at least these three. (I have written about Galton
[238, 352, 3831 and Spearman [239, 353, 383].)
During my clinical internship at the University of Maryland Psychiatric
Institute in Baltimore, I examined a great variety of psychiatric patients,
using all of the prevailing techniques of clinical psychology, and typically
wrote a clinical report on each patient. During my training experience in
psychotherapy, I quickly came to realize that I was less satisfied and less
effective working with people directly than in working with data. I did not
enjoy many of the routine aspects of clinical work, probably because I am
quite low in extraversion. Hence I welcomed collaboration with one of my
clinical supervisors in some research we did on the Rorschach as an index of
pathological thinking that completely eschewed the traditional systems of
scoring Rorschach protocols and was solely based on characteristics of the
subject's verbal expression (5; see also 39, 46).
It was also at this time that I began seriously reading the books and
articles of Hans J. Eysenck, who was then a maverick personality researcher
and the professor of psychology in the University of London's Institute of
Psychiatry. Most of my evenings that year were spent reading every book and
article by Eysenck that I could find in the university library, as well as
many of the references he made to the influential work of others, particularly
Galton, Spearman, and Thurstone. This provided a much needed antidote to the
predominantly Freudian or psychoanalytic concepts that informed my clinical
work. It was not so much the specific aspects of Eysenck' s own theories or
his research, but rather his general approach to psychology as a natural
science that provided my first real sense of finally having discovered my true
vocation. I felt I was no longer groping for the path that I should take to
make my life seem worthwhile. I believed that research and teaching in the
field of differential psychology, broadly conceived, was exactly the path for
me. So I wrote to Eysenck for his permission and applied to NIMH for a
postdoctoral fellowship to spend a year in Eysenck's department in London.
Luckily, both were granted and, with a year's extension of my fellowship, I
had the good fortune to spent two full years with Eysenck. (Six years later I
returned to his department as a Guggenheim Fellow for another full year during
my first sabbatical leave from Berkeley [detailed in 149, 378]).
I emphasize my postdoctoral work with Eysenck, because I believe it planted
the seeds of virtually everything I have done since then. It put me on the
path that I have followed, in one way or another, for all of my later
research. Although each of the many subsequent byways could not have been
anticipated, they all led more or less consistently in one general direction
-- what came to be known as the London School of differential psychology,
originated by Galton and with Spearman, Burt, and Eysenck successively as its
leading exponents (283, 376, 377). (I knew personally only Eysenck [378] and
Burt [126. 225, 326, 367].) The London School is not really a school or even a
doctrine or a theory. Rather, it is a general view of psychology as a natural
science and as essentially a branch of biology.
Its central concern is variability in human behavior. It is Darwinian in
that it views both interspecies variation and an important part of
intraspecies variation (both individual and group differences) in certain
classes of behavior as products of the evolutionary process. It is
behavior-genetic in that the evolutionary process depends upon genetic
variation and selection, and the neural basis of behavioral capacities is
subject to these evolutionary mechanisms the same as other physical
characteristics. It is quantitative in that it emphasizes the objective
measurement and taxonomy of behavior and the operational definition of latent
traits or hypothetical constructs. It is analytical in that it subjects
quantitative data to mathematical formulation and statistical inference. It is
experimental in that it typically obtains measurements, both behavioral and
physiological, under specifically defined and controlled conditions. It is
reductionist in that it aims theoretically to explain complex phenomena in
terms of simpler, more elemental processes. It is monistic (as opposed to
dualistic) in that it neither posits nor seeks any explanatory principle that
does not consist of strictly physical processes; it views complex
psychological phenomena as emerging solely from interactions among more
elemental neurophysiological processes and their past and present interactions
with environmental conditions.
Besides the extensive reading, studying (courses in multivariate statistics
with Patrick Slater and factor analysis with A.E. Maxwell), and writing (4, 6,
7, 9, 14) that occupied my time as a postdoc, I undertook laboratory research
on individual differences in the effects of massed and distributed practice in
selective stimulus-response learning and I devised a special apparatus for the
directly measuring individual differences in reactive inhibition independent
of any form of learning per se (51). The specific hypotheses I tested derived
from Eysenck's theory of the basic neural processes responsible for individual
differences in extraversion-introversion (or E, as it was called), which had
been established as a continuous unitary trait by the factor analysis of
personality inventories, behavioral ratings, and objective behavior
measurements derived from certain laboratory techniques. Eysenck' s theory of
E at that time brought me back to Clark Hull's theory of learning, which had
first fascinated me as an undergraduate. I became a born-again Hullian, this
time around becoming more thoroughly versed in every facet of Hull's theory
and most of the theoretical and empirical literature related to it, including
Pavlov's classic work on conditioning.
Eysenck's theory held that the basis of E is the rate of build-up of a
hypothetical neural process called reactive inhibition, or IR (as defined in
Hull's system). The theory contends that trait extraversion reflects a more
rapid build-up and a slower spontaneous dissipation of IR under the conditions
in which IR is hypothesized to be manifested in behavior, such as the
experimental extinction and spontaneous recovery of conditioned responses, the
effect of massed trials versus spaced trials in serial rote learning, and the
reminiscence effect in motor learning (as on the pursuit-rotor). It was this
aspect of Eysenck's research program that led me into theories of learning and
the experimental psychology of human learning, which soon completely
overshadowed my interest in personality research. I saw the study of
individual differences in learning in its own right as a more fundamental and
scientifically researchable subject than the study of personality. The last
postulate in Hull's behavior theory in its final form (in 1952) states that
individual differences in learning, or excitatory potential (sEr), are a net
product of individual differences in each of the hypothetical constructs in
his system, such as habit strength (sHr), drive (D), reactive inhibition (IR),
conditioned inhibition (sIr), sensory limen or threshold of stimulus
activation (sLr), and spontaneous oscillation of reaction potential (sOr). I
thought this approach provided the basis for a rigorous, quantitative and
experimental approach to the study of individual differences in human
learning. I later elaborated on this idea in a paper that, in retrospect,
strikes me as an overly ambitious and practically unfeasible program for
research on individual differences in human learning (59). Since the largest
part of the individual differences variance in the forms of learning that are
important for education and the acquisition of many other real-life skills is
factorially indistinguishable from Spearman's g, or general intelligence, I
now believe a program of research on the nature of g to be probably more
fruitful than focusing on learning per se (189, 301).
But before going on with my story, I should point out what may not be well
known to younger readers, that Hull's system, which dominated the learning
field from about 1940 to 1960 (he died in 1952), waned rapidly in the early
Sixties and became virtually extinct by 1970. Since then, Hull's citation
index has hovered close to zero. This is a remarkable fate for one who, for
over a period of at least twenty years, many considered the leading theorist
in scientific psychology. In marked contrast, E.L. Thorndike, 48 years after
his death, remains among the 100 most frequently cited psychologists in recent
decades, and the number of citations of Charles Spearman has increased in each
decade since his death (in 1945) and risen most rapidly since 1970.
Thorndike's and Spearman's intuitions, hypotheses, theories, and the
phenomena on which their interests were focused, mainly learning and cognitive
ability, were evidently more important, more original, and scientifically more
productive than Hull's precisely formulated theory of learning, however
impressive his achievement seemed in its day. The problem, I think, was not
Hull's in use of the hypothetico-deductive method, which I believe was
exemplary, but that the many interrelated parts of his whole grand theoretical
edifice, its postulates (as Hull called them), were erected on too slim a
foundation of empirical studies. Hence the subsequently growing number of
experiments inspired by the theory and devised to test it increasingly failed
to confirm its predictions. Though modifications and additional ad hoc
principles were proposed to meet the explanatory demands imposed by new
empirical evidence, Hull's system gradually collapsed beyond repair and was
eventually discarded, much like the geocentric theory in astronomy and the
phlogiston theory in chemistry. In the history of science, of course, this is
a perfectly respectable demise for a theory. The really fatal shortcoming of
Hullian theory, however, was its nonbiological behaviorism, a position that
was bound ultimately to leave it theoretically barren.
Rather early in my career, while still a Hullian, I tried to modify Hull's
theory to make it accommodate some of the contradictory experimental evidence
by proposing a fundamental mathematical reformulation of the treatment of
reactive and conditioned inhibition within the Hullian framework (18). But
this kind of ad hoc doctoring could not save Hull's system any more than
postulating retrograde motion of the planetary epicycles could preserve
Ptolemy's geocentric theory. Though I gradually lost interest in Hull's
theory, my interest in human learning, particularly in its individual
differences aspect, was undiminished.
Now that the stage is set, with a backdrop of the values and attitudes
against which all my later activity can be more understandable, I will provide
a brief account of the specific studies that I believe mark the key points in
my research activity, and how and why I moved from each point to the next.
Studies never arise from thin air, of course, but also one does not have to go
looking for things to research. Each new project, it seems, is absolutely
compelled by the preceding ones, or by one's purposeful and critical reading
of the literature or by one's self-criticism and others' criticisms of one's
previous work. The completion of each study always leave some loose ends.
Problems abound and one continually searches for what seems the most fruitful
path toward each problem's solution. Given the pages allotted me, this account
is necessarily quite telegraphic, referencing only my main publications on
each topic. A perusal of my bibliography (see Appendix) indicates that my
publications fall into six main categories: (i) clinical and personality, (ii)
human learning, (iii) behavior genetics, (iv) racial-cultural differences, (v)
test bias, and (vi) mental chronometry and g theory. (I will ignore the first
category, with some dozen or so articles, which in retrospect I consider of
much less importance or interest.)
Human Learning [deleted for brevity]
The Behavior-Genetics of Intelligence
When, in 1966, I was invited to spend a year at the Center for Advanced
Study in the Behavioral Sciences, I had enough research material on the
learning characteristics of culturally disadvantaged children, as they were
called at that time, that I thought I could best spend my year at the Center
writing a book about my findings. I took all of my research material with me
and began work at the Center, a wonderfully undisturbed and heavenly
atmosphere for study and writing, with a most helpful staff and the
intellectual companionship of the many other fellows at the Center.
A reasonably comprehensive book about the educationally disadvantaged
children, I thought, should contain one short chapter addressing the issue of
the inheritance of intelligence, if only to show that this line of explanation
for individual and group differences in scholastic performance could be
dismissed as outmoded and scientifically discredited. I had never given this
topic much thought and knew shamefully little about it at that time. It had
never been touched upon in my entire education to that point and the subject
was generally either unmentioned or scorned by virtually everyone I knew
working in the field of learning and the educationally disadvantaged. My first
exposure to it was in 1957 during my postdoc in London, when I attended a
lecture on "the inheritance of mental ability" by Sir Cyril Burt. Though I was
highly impressed by Burt's lecture as a brilliant tour de force, its subject
didn't really capture my interest at that time. Burt's lecture was later
published in the American Psychologist (1958, 13, 1-150), and it seemed a good
place to start what became my program of reading virtually the entire world
literature on the genetics of mental ability at that time. I hadn't expected
to go that far into the subject, but the more I read, the more I realized it
couldn't be dismissed and had to be taken seriously.
In order to be able to evaluate much of what I read, I had to tackle the
technical aspects of quantitative genetics. Luckily, a professor of ethology
and genetics was also a fellow at the Center that year and was a most helpful
tutor and guide to the literature on quantitative genetics. I felt most
resentful of the fact that I had reached that stage of my education and of my
career and had not been exposed to the existing scientific knowledge on the
genetics of mental ability. I was even more dismayed to realize that my case
was all too typical of those working in most branches of psychology,
particularly experimental, educational, and clinical. All human variation in
abilities was attributed to the learning opportunities afforded by different
environmental and cultural circumstances to which individuals were exposed.
Though at that time the literature on behavior genetics was but a fraction of
its present volume, what there was seemed sufficient to call in question the
prevailing 100 percent environmentalism of the l950s and '60s. My task was cut
out for me: to help dispel the ignorance that generally prevailed in
educational psychology concerning the role of genetic factors. In reading E.L.
Thorndike, the father of American educational psychology, I found that he was
on the right track in his intuition about the importance of genetic factors in
individual differences, but his line of thought on this subject rapidly went
out of fashion shortly after World War II, for no good scientific reason.
Therefore, during my year at the Center, I wrote several articles that
stemmed from my new-found interest in the genetics of mental ability and its
implications for education (61, 62, 63, 64, 68, 70). The most frequently cited
of these articles is based on my examination of the famous Hoizinger formula
for estimating heritability from the difference between the correlations
between MZ twins and between DZ twins. I showed that Hoizinger's formula,
which was virtually the only one ever used in studies of the heritability of
intelligence up to that time, did not estimate heritability as it is defined
in quantitative genetics, nor did it take account of the effect of assortative
mating on the estimation of heritability from twin data (6 1; see also 178). I
provided a new formula that not only accorded with the meaning of broad
heritability as defined in genetics but also took account of assortative
mating. (The formula could also be generalized for estimating heritability
with other kin-ships besides twins, such as full siblings and half siblings.)
I used this formula to recalculate heritability coefficients for IQ on every
published study of MZ and DZ twins.
Although the articles I wrote that year emphasized the evidence for the
substantial heritability of individual differences in IQ, I thought (and
wrote) that it was unnecessary to invoke genetic causes for the observed
racial differences in IQ, which I thought could be explained in terms of
cultural bias in the tests and poor environmental opportunities for acquiring
the particular knowledge and skills called for by conventional tests. One of
my articles written at the Center (63), which originated as an invited address
at a convention was titled "How Much Can We Boost IQ and Scholastic
Achievement?" It came to the attention of the editors of the Harvard
Educational Review, and in 1968 (when I was back at Berkeley) they asked me to
expand it into a more comprehensive article for the Spring, 1969 issue of the
Review. They even provided an outline of the topics they wanted me to deal
with in the article, including my view on the heritability of race differences
(which I had not previously mentioned). I gladly accepted the editor's
invitation, as an opportunity to consolidate what I had been studying and
thinking about during my year at the Center. The result was a 200-page
typescript which became a 125-page article in the Harvard Educational Review
(HER) titled "How Much Can We Boost IQ and Scholastic Achievement?" (76).
Though unexpected at the time, I suppose it was the article that forever
changed my life, for better or worse.
My Year of Turmoil
Based on a review of the empirical literature, my HER article made four
main claims:
(i) experimental attempts to raise the IQ of children at risk for low IQ
and poor scholastic performance by various psychological and educational
manipulations had yielded little, if any, lasting gains in IQ or scholastic
achievement; (ii) individual differences in IQ have a high heritability
(.70-.80, corrected for attenuation), but environment also plays an important
part; (iii) most of the exclusively cultural-environment explanations for
racial differences in IQ and scholastic achievement were inconsistent and
inadequate, so genetic as well as environmental factors should be considered;
and (iv) certain abilities, particularly rote-learning and memory (i.e., Level
I ability) have only a weak relationship to IQ, which suggests that these
Level I abilities might be used to compensate to some extent for low IQ (i.e.,
Level II ability) and thereby make school instruction more beneficial for many
children, regardless of their racial or social class background, who are below
average in Level II but are average or above in Level I. (Pupils with this
pattern of abilities constitute the majority of those who are most at risk for
failure under traditional classroom instruction.)
Viewed as a whole, it seemed quite reasonable. But it was the few pages on
race differences in IQ and achievement (about 5% of the article) that aroused
so much sound and fury, most of it focused on the one sentence that violated
what I later came to realize is the greatest taboo in the latter half of the
twentieth century. Here is what I wrote concerning the Black-White difference
in IQ: "The preponderance of the evidence is, in my opinion, less consistent
with a strictly environmental hypothesis than with a genetic hypothesis,
which, of course, does not exclude the influence of environment or its
interaction with genetic factors" (76, p. 82).
That one aspect of the article was blown up by the mass media, with feature
articles in TIME, Newsweek, LIFE, U.S. News & World Report, the New York Times
Magazine, and many other newspapers and magazines, as well as radio and TV
programs. The Berkeley campus was in an uproar for weeks (and sporadically for
months and even years thereafter) with bands of demonstrators disrupting my
classes, slashing all the tires on my car, and painting swastikas on my office
door. The student paper, The Daily Cal, carried many denunciations and only a
few defenses of my position, and there were demands from dissident groups that
I be fired. The campus police assigned plainclothes bodyguards to accompany me
whenever I left my office, and for several months the campus bomb squad
handled the screening and opening all of my mail, even some of the
unidentified mail received at my home. There were telephoned and mailed
threats on my life and on my family; phone calls were routed (and recorded)
through the local police station. A number of the calls that came in over one
period of several days so worried the police that they urged me and my family
to spend a week away from our home at some unknown location, as the police
could not provide 24-hour protection. (We stayed with friends in a neighboring
suburb; an inconvenience, but as they had a lovely swimming pool, it was a
pleasant diversion.) Worst of all, from my standpoint, was that my on-going
research in the Berkeley schools was immediately terminated and permanently
proscribed by the Berkeley school officials (128). When I asked one official
for an explanation, he remarked, "The Berkeley schools are a political unit,
not a research institute."
Many other harrowing incidents followed, some taking place when I was
lecturing on other college campuses, both in the United States and abroad,
even when my lectures didn't touch on the subjects of genetics or race. The
largest, most tumultuous demonstration I ever experienced was, surprisingly,
at the University of Melbourne, in 1977, where about fifty policemen had to
rescue me from a madding mob. The unprovocative topic of my [undelivered]
lecture: The relationship between intelligence and learning [189; see also
301]. The very next day the same thing happened in the same setting to Hans
Eysenck. His topic: the relationship between personality and learning. (I have
written at greater length in the Preface to my Genetics and Education about
the bizarre events following the publication of my HER article [112; see also
149].)
The really important consequence of the HER article for my subsequent
activity was that it raised a number of questions and issues concerning
subjects that called for fuller explication or further research. In many
articles (from #77 on) and three books (143, 144, 206), I consolidated my
position on these subjects as best as empirical research permitted at that
time and launched new research on the remaining unanswered questions and
speculative hypotheses. Some people advised me to get out of this
controversial area altogether. One eminent psychologist friend warned that if
I scorned the Zeitgeist, it would in turn scorn me. However, rather than duck
for cover, which I peculiarly felt would be disgracefully un-Gandhian, I
resolved not to be whipsawed by the prevailing orthodoxy in the social and
behavioral sciences, but to do whatever I could to reform the social sciences.
And I believe that at least the scientific community, if not the media and the
political establishment, has indeed changed its mind if not its voice over the
past 30 years, with an almost total collapse of naive environmentalism and an
increasing recognition, at least in the pages of academic journals, of the
importance of genetic factors and of environmental factors with biological
effects on the development of human mental ability. The well-known survey by
Synderman and Rothman (1988) of over 600 psychologists in the relevant fields
showed that their modal response on every question that involved the very
issues considered heretical in my HER article agreed with the position I then
stated. To what extent my own work may have helped usher in the new
perspective would be impossible to estimate, but I believe I have played a
role. Many other influences, of course, have brought about the demise of
doctrinaire environmentalism and advanced the biological orientation of
mainstream behavioral science.
Bias in Mental Testing
At about the time of my HER article, the question of culture bias in mental
tests was frequently brought up. I was familiar with the early resarch on
social class bias in standard tests, pioneered by Kenneth Fells (who had been
one of my professors), but I found rather little more than speculation in the
literature regarding test bias with respect to racial or ethnic groups. Yet
that question was crucial. I reviewed what little evidence existed on the
subject in the mid-1960s (69, 99), but found it inadequate and largely
unconvincing. Besides the educational, social, and economic unfairness of
using tests that are differentially and systematically inaccurate for
different racial, ethnic, and social-class groups in our population, I
considered also the scientific importance of test bias for the field of
psychology in its own right. Psychometrics -- the science and technology of
mental measurement -- is of course basic to many fields in psychology, as
indeed reliable and valid measurement is essential for the development of any
science or technology. To the degree that the standard psychometric
instruments then in use were biased, either by culture, social status, or
gender, basic research in differential and educational psychology as well as
the practical applications of testing in educational placement, in college
admission, in personnel selection, and in assigning recruits to various
training schools in the armed services were all compromised by having to
operate with deficient tools.
I thought it imperative to devise methods for detecting the presence of
various kinds of psychometric bias. This became the main focus of my research
effort for the next few years (109, 153, 176, 179, 181, 182, 289). It
culminated, in 1980, with the publication of my Bias in Mental Testing (199;
see also 202,203,217), an 800-page tome which was then (and may still be) the
most comprehensive work on the subject. Research on criteria of bias based on
a test's so-called external validity, that is, its practical predictive
validity (i.e., both the regression [and correlation] of criterion measures on
test scores) in different sub-populations had already been quite well
investigated by psychometricians during the period between 1970 and 1980.
Though I fully explicated this work in Bias, my own research contributions
emphasized internal indicators of bias, such as whether different groups,
(e.g., Black-White, male-female) differ significantly in various psychometric
features such as the test's reliability, the test items' rank order of
difficulty, the test scores' correlation (and regression) with chronological
age, the relative frequency of choosing various distractors (i.e., error
responses) in multiple-choice tests, the groups' similarity in the factor
structure, and the groups' similarity in kinship correlations and heritability
values for the test in question.
A methodoligica1 innovation I introduced was the use of what I termed
"pseudo-race age groups." For example, when I found significant differences
between Black and White school children in their specific choices of error
distractors (in the Raven Progressive Matrices test), I created two
"pseudo-race" groups composed entirely of White children, the groups differing
in age such that the younger group and the older group had the very same mean
difference in total test score as the mean difference between age-matched
Blacks and Whites. I discovered that the same-age Black-White differences in
the frequencies of selecting a particular distractor (i.e., a wrong answer)
among the several distractors for each item on the Raven test were virtually
identical to the differences between the two groups of White children that
differed in age by almost two years (approximately ages 8 years and 10 years).
Applying this method to a variety of tests, including Gesell's Figure Copying
test (a good predictor of scholastic performance in the primary grades), free
drawing, and several Piagetian tests, we found that in every feature of test
performance, age-matched groups of Black and White children differed in
exactly the same way as did "pseudo-race" groups of different-age White
children when the age of the younger group is about 80% that of the older
group.
Our findings with pseudo-race groups suggested that the observed racial
differences in performance were not attributable to test bias, but reflected a
developmental difference in rate of mental maturation, with Whites (and more
so, Asians), on average, having a steeper trajectory and a higher asymptote.
From my own studies and my review of the total empirical literature on test
bias, I concluded in Bias: "...the currently most widely used standardized
tests of mental ability -- IQ, scholastic aptitude, and achievement tests --
are, by and large, not biased against any of the the native-born
English-speaking minority groups on which the amount of research evidence is
sufficient for an objective determination of bias, if the tests were in fact
biased" (p. ix). Essentially the same conclusion was announced independently
two years later in a joint report by the National Research Council and the
National Academy of Sciences (Wigdor & Garner, 1982), which had chosen a panel
of nineteen leading experts in psychometrics to review the evidence.
The Cumulative Deficit Hypothesis
One hypothesis proposed in the 1960s to explain the Black-White difference
in the trajectory of raw scores on mental tests and on scholastic achievement
across grades 1 to 12, held that the increasing racial disparity in test
performance with increasing age is the result of a cumulative deficit in
learning, such that failure to learn particular knowledge or skills thoroughly
at one grade level hinders the ability to learn more advanced material in
later grades. Because Black children, on average, begin school having learned
less of the prerequisites for learning in the primary grades, they fall
further and further below national norms in scholastic achievement with each
additional year. Progressive learning deficit is thought to act cumulatively,
like mounting credit card debt. This hypothesis was popular in the 1960s and
provided much of the rationale for Head Start and other compensatory education
programs (54; see also 158, 162, 304, 314, 380).
My investigation of the phenomenon, however, found the evidence for it
ambiguous, at best. The divergence between Black and White test scores with
increasing age or grade level in school was fully apparent when looking at raw
scores, but there was little, if any, evidence for a divergence of Black and
White mean scores when the scores are expressed as standardized scores. That
is, when measured in age-standardized scores, the mean Black-White difference
of about one standard deviation remains constant from kindergarten to 12th
grade, because the standard deviation within each group also increases
proportionally with age.
I reasoned that if there were a true cumulative deficit effect for IQ, and
if it was the cause of Blacks' lower average IQ, and if IQ declined the longer
a child stayed in a culturally disadvantaged environment, then Black children
at any given age should have, on average, a lower IQ than that of their
younger siblings. The cumulative deficit theory predicts that the positive
difference between the ages of the older (O) and the younger (Y) sibling is
positively correlated with the Y-O difference in IQ. There should be a
substantial such correlation among Blacks (i.e., the older sib should have a
lower IQ than the younger sib), but this effect should be negligible or
nonexistent for middle-class and upper-class Whites. A significant correlation
for Blacks would support the favored environmental explanation of the
cumulative deficit, because there is nothing in genetic theory which would
predict a systematic difference, on average, between the genotypes of full
siblings for any given characteristic, as each sib receives a random set of
half of each of its parent's genes.
I tested this prediction with several hundred pairs of Black siblings and
White siblings, all of school age (156). Despite the large samples, the
hypothesis was not born out, although the theory-predicted correlation was
significant (p < .05, one-tail test) only for verbal IQ in the all-male sib
pairs, and then only for those, in the primary grades. No other subdivision of
the data revealed the slightest indication of the predicted correlation, for
either Blacks or Whites.
This null outcome made me wonder if the Black population in Berkeley,
California, despite its typically lower IQ compared to Whites and Asians in
the same schools, was somehow atypical of the general Black population,
perhaps being less environmentally disadvantaged. The cumulative deficit might
occur only in children whose environmental disadvantage falls below a critical
a threshold necessary for normal phenotypic development of the individual's
genotypic potential. I realized, therefore, that another study using exactly
the same methods would have to be done in an area where there could be no
question that the vast majority of the Black school children lived in a
conspicuously impoverished environment.
I found the necessary data for this study in a school district in one of
the poorest counties in the rural South. The IQ of the Black pupils was 71,
averaged over kindergarten to 12th grade the average IQ of the White pupils
was 101. All of the full siblings, White and Black, enrolled in all of the
schools of this rural county were included in the study. The findings were
startling. The White school population showed no evidence of an age-related
decline in IQ, in this respect being like the White sample in my Berkeley
study. The Blacks, however, showed a marked age-decrement in IQ, as indicated
by the younger minus older sibling IQ difference -- a decrement of about one
IQ point for each year of the Y-O sibling age difference. In other words, with
family background controlled (by the sibling design) these Black children
declined, on average, about one IQ point per year throughout their time in
school (180). One might have argued that this was not necessarily an
environmental effect but a racially genetic difference in the trajectory of
the mental growth curves for Blacks and Whites. The California data, however,
seemed to rule out this interpretation, as they evinced no such effect for
Blacks. If the effect observed in Southern rural Blacks were a genetic racial
characteristic rather than an environmental effect, it should have shown up,
at least to some degree, in the California Blacks as well. It therefore seems
most likely that some substantial part of the IQ deficit for Blacks in the
poorest environments is a result of environment, most probably environmental
factors that have biological consequences, such as unfavorable prenatal
conditions, poor nutrition, and childhood illnesses, which can limit mental
development.
Spearman's Hypothesis
While re-reading Spearman's major work, The Abilities of Man (1927), I came
across a brief passage (p. 379) that had not previously captured my attention.
On second reading, however, it made a major impact. On the basis of one slight
study (by American psychologists) of Black-White differences on a variety of
cognitive tests, Spearman conjectured that variation in the magnitude of the
B-W difference across various tests is directly related to the size of each
test's g loading. (Because the article presented only the tests' means but not
their intercorrelations, Spearman could not extract the g factor with which to
test his conjecture.) I henceforth referred to this conjecture' as "Spearman's
hypothesis." It struck me as of quintessential importance, because, if true,
it is a much more general hypothesis than my Level I-Level II formulation,
which appears to be just a special case of Spearman's hypothesis. Spearman's
hypothesis also seemed to explain why the size of the B-W difference (in
standardized units) varied so widely across different cognitive tests. This
question had always been a stumbling block to the prevailing environmental
theories, which were a plethora of piecemeal, ad hoc, inconsistent, and
unconvincing explanations. Spearman's hypothesis, if true, would mean that the
B-W difference was essentially a difference in g. Therefore, if we are to
understand the phenotypic B-W difference in measurements of cognitive ability,
it would be necessary to understand the nature of g itself. First, Spearman's
hypothesis had to be put to a rigorous empirical test. This called for
representative samples of Blacks and Whites measured on as wide a variety of
mental tests as could be found. I tested Spearman's hypothesis on a large
scale (224, 256, 266, 267, 268, 288,290, 296, 324, 325, 339, 375). By
publishing my analysis of much of the evidence as a target article in The
Behavioral and Brain Sciences (266), its was subjected to commentaries by over
thirty experts in psychometrics and cognitive psychology. In brief, the total
evidence strongly bears out Spearman's hypothesis. It is no longer a
hypothesis, but must now be regarded as an empirical fact, as much so as
Galton's Law of Filial Regression or Thorndike' s Law of Effect. (The most
recent comprehensive summary of the methodology and evidence on Spearman's
hypothesis is provided in Chapter 11 of my recent book, The g Factor [383].)
Speed of Information Processing and g [deleted for brevity]
Non-psychometric Correlates of g
Critics of the g construct have argued that g is merely an arbitrary
artifact of the way psychometric tests are constructed and inherent in the
mathematical procedure of factor analysis. If this were truly the case, I
reasoned, the g factor should not be related to variables other than
psychometric tests and should tend to disappear when using different factor
analytic methods, assuming, of course, that such methods (like varimax
rotation) are not specifically devised to scatter the g variance among a
number of uncorrelated group factors.
Method Invariance of g. First, I treid to determine whether the g factor of
a correlation matrix of diverse psychometric tests is more or less invariant
when the g factor is extracted by any of the several quite different methods
that have been used by various researchers throughout the history of factor
analysis, from Spearman to the present day. By applying each of the main
methods of factor analysis to real data and also to artificial data for which
the g loadings of the "tests" were known exactly, it was found that g is
remarkably similar across all of the different methods, as shown by congruence
coefficients averaging over +.99 (360).
Meta-analysis of Physical Correlates. In 1930, long before the invention of
meta-analysis, Donald 0. Paterson published his classic work, Physique and
Intellect, which reviewed all of the then existing studies on the correlation
between physical features and measures of intelligence. Most of the
correlational studies were based on rather small samples, and as the
correlations between physical measures and IQ are typically small, they were
usually nonsignificant statistically. Paterson simply compared the number of
significant and nonsignificant correlations and usually concluded that the
null hypothesis could not be rejected. His conclusions of essentially "no
physical correlates of IQ" have become a dogma in psychology textbooks, and
the vast majority of psychologists even today will tell you, for example, that
there is no correlation between head size or brain size and IQ. As I generally
doubted many of Paterson's conclusions, I decided to review all of the studies
of physical correlates done since 1930 and, when possible, to combine the
results of various studies by the methods of meta-analysis. The result was
that the null hypothesis (i.e., no correlation) could be rejected at high
levels of confidence for most of the physical characteristics that had been
examined in relation to IQ; these include body size, head size, brain size,
blood types, ocular characteristics, and other anatomical and physiological
variables (341). The significant correlations between psychometric scores and
such a wide variety of physical traits argues forcefully that the population
variance on standard mental tests, such as IQ, reflects latent traits that are
profoundly enmeshed with organismic variables in complex ways.
An innovative feature of my meta-analytic review was that, where possible,
it examined three different types of correlation of a given physical trait
with IQ: (i) the correlation within individuals (WI), (ii) within families
(WF), and (iii) between families (BF). This methodology, based on sibling data
(202), is an analytically important tool that helps determine the probable
cause of the observed correlation. For example, failure to find a WF
correlation, even when there is a significant WI correlation in the general
population, rules out pleiotropy (i.e., two or more distinct phenotypic
characteristics being the result of the same gene). Height and IQ show a WI
(and BF) correlation, but they do not show a WF correlation (200). Head size
and IQ show a WF correlation (358), as do myopia and IQ (299), suggesting that
these two physical traits are pleiotropically related to IQ. These findings
aid the search for the specific gene loci responsible for variance in IQ or g
and may also provide clues to the precise physical basis of IQ variance.
The Methods of Correlated Vectors. IQ is highly g-loaded, but it is
typically saturated with other factors as well. To determine whether a given
nonpsychometric variable is related to g per se, rather than to any other
factors or specific sources of variance in test scores, I invented the method
of correlated vectors. Essentially, it consists of factor analyzing a large
psychometric battery of highly diverse subtests to obtain the g loadings of
each subtest. This column vector of the subtests' g loadings is termed Vg.
Each subtest is then correlated with some non-psychometric variable, X. The
column vector of these correlations is Vx. Controlling for differences in the
subtest reliabilities (by disattenuating or partialing out the subtests'
reliability coefficients), a significant correlation between the parallel
column vectors Vg and Vx shows that g and X are related. It tells us that the
larger a subtest's true g loading, the larger is its correlation with variable
X.
I have examined a number of variables (X) by this method. The correlation
between Vg and the various measures (i.e., Vx) is shown in brackets: in
brackets): spouse correlation [.90]; heritability [.60-.80]; inbreeding
depression [.80]; cerebral glucose metabolic rate [-.79]; brain intracellular
pH [.63]; head size [.60-.70]; choice and discrimination RI [.70-.80]; average
evoked potential habituation amplitude [.80]; and AEP waveform complexity
[.95]. All of these correlations are significant; the particulars on the
studies of each variable are given in (226, 258,282, 356, 383 [Chapters 6-9]).
No other factor shows anywhere near the same degree of relationship to
non-psychometric variables as does g. My research shows conclusively that
psychometric g, far more than any other factor, reflects individual
differences in certain biological and developmental properties of the brain
that govern its speed, consistency, and capacity for information processing.
Though manifested overtly in many ways that can be described in behavioral
terms, g itself cannot be described or explained in behavioral or
psychological terms. The g factor per se does not reflect any particular
achievements, knowledge, or skills, but rather the information processing
capacity for acquiring and using the knowledge and skills necessary for
achievement.
I have pointed out a crucial conceptual distinction, namely, that the
construct (in this case g) and the vehicle used for measuring the construct
(in this case, a psychometric test and the scores it yields) are not one and
the same; they are conceptually and empirically distinct. Though the rank
order of individuals' scores on any highly g-loaded test can be accounted for
largely in terms of individual differences in the level of g, the absolute
level of the individuals' raw scores on any such test also reflects the
particular composition of the test items (332). This fact has important
consequences for the interpretation of test scores and the secular trend in
the population mean for any particular vehicle of g (319, 368, 383, Chapter
10).
In addition to showing that g is correlated with various biological
variables, I have also amassed empirical evidence (based largely on the method
of correlated vectors) to show that it is g itself that accounts for most of
the practical predictive validity of tests used in educational placement and
selection and in personnel selection in industry and the Armed Forces. When
the validity coefficient is based on a multiple correlation, typically the
increment in predictive power contributed by all other factors (and by test
specificity) independent of g is remarkably small (383, Chapter 9).
Future Directions
I see basic research on human mental ability, particularly g and the major
group factors, as advancing in each of two directions, which I think of as the
horizontal and the vertical. Both are necessary and each can be scientifically
rigorous.
Horizontal research on g explores the whole nexus of behavioral, social,
and economic correlates and consequences of individual and group differences
in the level of g. I believe g plays a greater role in these spheres than most
educators, sociologists, criminologists, economists and social policy analysts
presently realize. But serious consideration of this probability seems to be
strongly resisted in some circles. The generally nihilistic reaction of the
mass media to The Bell Curve by Herrnstein and Murray (1994), which, more than
any previous scholarly work, examined the relationship between g and a number
of social variables of national concern, is a case in point. It is a
reasonable supposition that in the global economy and the competitive
technological and information-intensive world of the twenty-first century, a
nation's chief natural resource will be its population's overall level of
educability, in which the distribution of g-loaded abilities will inevitably
be a major determining factor. Researching the extent and the ramifications of
the g factor in the nexus of societal variables is the province of a budding
new field named the "sociology of intelligence" by sociologists Robert Gordon
and Linda Gottfredson. (See the a special issue of INTELLIGENCE, 1997,24, No.
1, for example.)
Vertical research digs down in search of the causal basis of g. Being
analytical and reductionistic by nature, I personally find this is the more
interesting aspect and the one to which I expect to devote my efforts in the
future. By definition, an underdeveloped field is one in which many of the
findings, and even some of the classic experiments, have not been replicated
and many of the supposed facts not fully consolidated. I am happy therefore to
see research on "mental speed" in relation to psychometric g being actively
pursued in a number of laboratories around the world. The new information that
I see coming in, almost every month, is most valuable. However, there is still
confusion, contradiction, and many unanswered questions. More standardized
apparatus and procedures are called for (as the same standardized reagents are
used in every chemical laboratory) and much more importance must be accorded
to replicating the theoretically crucial findings across different
laboratories. The measurement of individual differences in g by means of
mental chronometry is as close to the interface between brain and behavior as
we are likely to come. The consolidation of the knowledge gained at this
interface is important for vertical advancement, that is, identifying the
basis of g in the structural and functional features of the brain itself.
A few hypothesis-generating steps have already been taken by showing
g-correlates of direct brain measurements obtained with evoked potentials,
magnetic resonance imagining (MRI), positron emission tomography (PET scan),
and intracellular brain pH levels. Many researchers in the neurosciences,
however, have ignored g as a subject for brain research, mostly, I fear,
because a crucial distinction has not been made sufficiently clear.
In recent articles (374, 384), 1 have emphasized the distinction between
(i) the neural circuitry or design features of the brain possessed by all
neurologically intact members of a species that are responsible for that
species' characteristic behavioral capacities, and (ii) the properties of the
brain of a given species that cause intraspecies variation (i.e., individual
differences) in that species' characteristic behavioral capacities. We know
from research in behavior genetics that intraspecies variation in many
behavioral capacities is not entirely the result of experiential differences
and learning. But I have found no good reason to believe that the design
features of the brain (which are undoubtedly crucial determinants of
interspecies variation in behavioral capacities) are necessarily involved in
intraspecies variation. The latter may well be due to an entirely different
set of causes than neural circuitry or other designs features of the brain,
but rather involve such within-species factors as: differences in blood supply
(via the richness of the capillary network), the degree of myelination of
axons (which affects nerve conduction velocity), the neuroglial cells (which
nourish neurons), the brain chemistry of neurotransmitter (which affect
synaptic transmission), and individual differences in the number of neurons
involved in the various brain modules. We now know quite conclusively from MRI
studies, for example, that IQ is correlated with brain size, but we still
don't know what precisely it is about brain size that causes this correlation.
All but an exceedingly few neuroscientists today are interested in
intraspecies variation in behavioral capacities. They may well find
discovering the brain's general operating principles daunting enough, without
having to explore the causes of individual variation in the functional
efficiency of the essential design features of the brain and their general
operating principles. As Francis Crick (1994) has pointed out, neuroscience
cannot yet explain even how the human brain sees things in the environment,
much less how it performs the complex functions we call intelligence. The very
existence of the g factor (like all other psychometric factors) is only
revealed by examining intraspecies individual differences in each of the broad
and diverse class of functions we regard as constituting intelligence --
discrimination, generalization, learning, memory, insight, abstraction,
problem solving, and the like. But before we can begin to research the
physical basis of g, do we first need to discover all of the brain's design
features that make these functions possible? I don't think so. The question of
what causes the various cognitive functions of the brain to be positively
correlated is a very different question from that of understanding the
specific operating mechanisms of each of these functions.
As a heuristic proposition to encourage research in this "vertical" search
for the neurological causes of g, I propose the following working hypothesis:
Individual differences in human behavioral capacities do not result from
differences in the brain's structural operating mechanisms per se, but rather
are the result of other aspects of cerebral physiology that modify the
sensitivity, efficiency, and effectiveness of the basic information processes
that mediate the individual's responses to certain aspects of the environment.
I'm placing my bets on the search for those aspects of brain physiology
responsible for g as most likely to generate the next path-breaking
discoveries in differential psychology and human biology. I have been told by
experts that the technology to do this already exists. So, looking ahead, I
see my principal endeavor to be sparking the interest of qualified scientists
in the brain sciences and helping them solicit the necessary resources to
pursue this "vertical" investigation of g.
-----------------
A New Twist on Jensenism by ALAN S. KAUFMAN, Yale University School of
Medicine
Jensenism is redefined, not in terms of his notions about the genetics of
intelligence, but in terms of the personal qualities and beliefs that have
made Jensen a researcher of note: going against convention. tackling
controversial topics with empiricism, refusing to be intimidated by threats
and picket lines, and being flexible enough to modify his beliefs. These
aspects of Jensen are illustrated by the author's personal experiences with
the man and his research.
My own, personal dictionary, not to be found in any bookstore or publishing
house, has a different definition of Jensenism, one that more accurately
portrays the man and his work:
Jensenism, n. (I) the art of going against the grain of conventional
psychological wisdom; (2) the belief that no topic is too holy or taboo to
reside beyond the grasp of scientific, empirical inquiry; (3) the ability to
remain steadfast in one's beliefs--sometimes with a touch of
arrogance--despite threats, accusations, denunciations, and attacks; (4) the
flexibility to allow one's own strictly held beliefs to be overturned by new
empirical discoveries; after Arthur R. Jensen (born 1923), U.S. educational
psychologist, who has practiced each of these tenets during his impressive
research career [1955-present].
I have long been an admirer of Arthur Jensen's approach to research. I
disagree with some of his conclusions, especially those concerning genetics
and race differences, but I applaud his commitment to the scientific process.
And, quite simply, the man is brilliant.
I remember when I first came face-to-face with Jensen's brilliance. The
Journal of Special Education had organized a special issue in 1984 devoted to
the controversial test that I co-authored with my wife Nadeen, the Kaufman
Assessment Battery for Children (K-ABC; Kaufman & Kaufman, 1983). Many
luminaries in psychology were invited to write articles about some aspect of
the K-ABC, and I was asked to read through all of the articles and write a
rebuttal article. The package of 13 articles arrived at my home just before I
was to drive to the airport for a cross-country trip. I took the package with
me and spent the next five hours reading each article and feverishly taking
notes for my rebuttal. Though the group of contributors included Anne
Anastasi, J.P. Das, and Robert Sternberg, among others, I had a good feeling
as I read through the first dozen articles. I was not worried about rebutting
the key points made by the various authors; I was feeling confident, even a
bit cocky.
Then I got to Jensen's article, which was at the bottom of the pile. As I
began to read his criticisms of the K-ABC, I began to sweat. One line from a
movie kept weaving in and out of my consciousness: As the Sundance Kid (Robert
Redford) and Butch Cassidy were being pursued by some relentless unknown
enemies, Sundance asked repeatedly, "Who are these guys?" As I read page after
page of Jensen's insightful critique, involving cognitive complexity,
Spearman's hypothesis, and indifference indicators, I kept subvocalizing the
words, "Who is this guy?" Of course, I knew quite well who he was; it just
never occurred to me that he was so familiar with my work and that he would
start his attack with smoking guns. The other authors wrote articles filled
with text, opinion, mid sometimes emotion. Jensen buttressed his text with
original data analyses that occupied four new tables and six new figures. He
used these analyses to challenge and provoke, to some extent, but mostly to
inquire, to seek the truth.
He used the K-ABC subtests to assess the validity of Spearman's hypothesis
(i. e., the notion that the magnitude of black-white differences in a set of
tasks is positively correlated with the tasks' g loadings). He obtained a
correlation of .58 for the 13 K-ABC sub-tests, virtually identical to the
value of .59 for a larger group of 121 cognitive tasks (Jensen, 1984),
impelling him to conclude that "the K-ABC tests cannot be regarded as at all
atypical; they conform to Spearman's hypothesis at least as well as many other
tests" (p. 395). That finding supported his overall perspective about the
K-ABC, and he might have left it at that. But he proceeded to point out a
finding that was opposite to his arguments: "The regression line for the K-ABC
tests. . .falls significantly below the regression line. . .for all 121 tests.
. . .That is, the K-ABC tests show considerably smaller differences than would
be predicted from their g loadings. This phenomenon poses what may be the
major puzzle of the K-ABC" (Jensen, 1984, p. 395). And, indeed, Jensen enjoys
solving puzzles. He delighted in formulating thought-provoking hypothesis
after hypothesis to attempt to solve this puzzle. I disagreed with most of his
ruminations, on Spearman's and other hypotheses, citing data or facts that I
perceived to be contrary to his notions (Kaufman, 1984). Yet, I couldn't help
but tip my hat to his objectivity and insight: "The tactics for writing the
articles. . . vary quite a bit, ranging from the brilliant, data-based,
meticulous critique of certain key aspects of the K-ABC expounded by the noted
Arthur Jensen [to the emotional responses of some others]" (Kaufman, 1984, p.
410).
About a year after being so thoroughly impressed by Jensen's empiricism,
wisdom, and sense of fairness, I had the chance to see him in action, and get
to know him personally, at the 1984 American Psychological Association meeting
in Anaheim. Jensen was giving a paper on several topics that included
Spearman's hypothesis, his K-ABC research, and black-white differences in IQ
and achievement. The media, naturally, was not far behind, and a circus
atmosphere developed, with reporters, picketers, video cameras, and security
guards everywhere. Jensen was escorted into the large, packed room by the
guards and he showed not the slightest trace of intimidation. He began his
address with blunt remarks about the large achievement discrepancies between
blacks and whites, differences that were not explainable by simple
environmental variables. I was taken aback by the directness of his statements
and his interpretations on a topic that invariably invites hemming, hawing,
apologetic statements, and back-stepping. I guess I shouldn't have been so
surprised in view of his writings on the topic, but I had never heard him
speak before and was expecting a small dose of political correctness. Instead,
I witnessed something more akin to sublime self-confidence blended with
in-your-face arrogance.
That evening, Nadeen and I joined Jensen, Cecil Reynolds, and one or two
other psychologists for dinner. Our Son, James, then 10 years old and now a
Ph. D. student of Robert Sternberg's at Yale, had been watching TV that
afternoon and saw the demonstrations against Jensen the psychologist and
threats against Jensen the man. James, out of fear, pleaded for us not to join
Jensen for dinner, but settled for a solemn promise that we wouldn't sit too
close to him. Dinner was thoroughly enjoyable as Jensen, though a bit
uncomfortable with the spotlight, entertained everyone with tales of
harassment and intrigue stemming from his notoriety. I recall him telling of a
TV talk show host's duplicity; the host (I believe it was Mike Wallace) made
Jensen look foolish when he changed the questions that actually aired from the
actual questions that were asked during the taped interview.
I have always enjoyed Jensen's ability to revisit the old in psychology and
come away with something new. His research on reaction time is excellent and
thought provoking. A simple twist on Galton's initial tasks for measuring
intelligence, long relegated to historical status within the field of
psychology and long believed to be an "off target" attempt to measure
cognitive ability, and Jensen was able to produce an apparently valid measure
of IQ. A sophisticated empirical treatment of the g factor, likewise dismissed
by mainstream psychology as a concept that is primarily of historical
importance, and Jensen re-established g as an invariant construct of potential
value. One might disagree with the meaningfulness of g and dispute the
theoretical basis or practical utility of the g factor, but the quality of
Jensen's research on the general factor demands that his findings and
conclusions not be taken lightly or dismissed cavalierly.
The net result of his research and writing on these formerly historical
topics is to reinterpret history. Galton's original intelligence test focused
on sensori-motor abilities and, though powerfully influential in the emergence
of the IQ concept in the United States and Europe, Galton's test was
ultimately declared invalid and was replaced by Binet's IQ test. Binet had the
insight to allow errors of measurement to invade the science of intelligence
and relied conceptually on Spearman's g factor in providing a rationale for
his choice of cognitive tasks for his battery. Subsequently, the g approach
was replaced by Wechsler's multi-score instruments, and theories from
Thurstone to Guilford to Horn that greatly downplay g; even the latest
revision of the Stanford-Binet yields subtest and area scores and relies on a
blend of Thurstone and Horn-Cattell as a theoretical foundation. But the
careful research by Jensen on reaction time and the g factor forces historians
and those involved in the clinical assessment of intelligence to rethink the
contributions of Galton, Spearman, and Binet, and to realize that the early
instruments may have been more on-target than initially believed. Galton, in
particular, may have missed by a few inches instead of a few miles.
Intriguingly, Jensen's research on reaction time and g is not only tied to the
past; it also may provide a link to the future as assessment enters the
computer-based stage of examining EEGs and CT scans for, potentially,
increasingly objective measurement of intelligence (Eysenck & Barrett, 1985;
Jensen, 1985).
As a trainer of school and clinical psychologists in intellectual
assessment for a quarter-century, I have found some of Jensen's research and
theorizing quite valuable. The research that impressed me for its simplicity,
yet far-reaching implications, was his work on Wechsler's Digit Span (Jensen &
Figueroa, 1975). So much had been written on the potential impact on
intelligence test scores of environmental variables such as motivation and
perseverance and of cultural variables such as the relevance of the stimuli
used in test questions. Evaluating the importance of these variables is
difficult because of their multifaceted complexity. Yet, Jensen's Digit Span
research was ingenious because it effectively held these variables constant.
Why would an examinee be more or less motivated or persevering when responding
to Digits Forward versus Digits Backward, tasks that utilize the identical,
culturally neutral stimuli? The research results that revealed quite different
individual variation on the repetition of digits in the forward versus
backward sequence were provocative and could not be easily dismissed by
proponents of the key role of motivation or culture loading in accounting for
group differences.
Jensen's hierarchical Level I--Level II theory of intelligence, simplistic
as it is, provides clinicians with a valuable method for interpreting profile
fluctuations when more conventional explanations (such as verbal--nonverbal)
do not suffice. When interpreting intelligence test profiles, I have always
considered it to be a mark of "intelligent testing" to be able to apply
diverse theories as explanations for a child's or adult's subtest fluctuations
(e. g., Kaufman, 1990, 1994). For the purpose of profile interpretation,
complex theories are usually less practical or effective than simple theories
for grouping subtests into alternative, relevant patterns that may reveal a
person's cognitive strengths and weaknesses. Jensen's memory--reasoning
dichotomy has proved to offer a useful alternative interpretive strategy for
understanding a person's profile when the fluctuations in that profile suggest
that the test's global scales cannot be meaningfully interpreted. For example,
memory-reasoning sometimes fits the data better than Wechsler's
Verbal-Performance split, the K-ABC's Sequential-Simultaneous division, or the
Stanford-Binet IV's fluid-crystallized dichotomy. In view of the fact that of
the alternative theories mentioned, only Jensen's is hierarchical, the
application of Level I-Level II theory to profile interpretation adds an
additional dimension to the mix, a dimension that sometimes has implications
for educational applications.
My own research disputes some aspects of Jensen's most controversial
statements regarding the intellectual abilities of blacks versus whites. On
the K-ABC, for example, one of the Achievement subtests is Faces & Places, a
test of general information that uses a visual-vocal instead of an
auditory-vocal format; thus, instead of responding orally to a question such
as "Who is Martin Luther King, Jr.," the child must respond orally to a
picture of Dr. King. This K-ABC subtest assesses range of general knowledge,
as does Wechsler's Information subtest. Yet, unpredictably, the apparently
culture-loaded Faces & Places subtest produces trivial black-white differences
whereas Wechsler's information subtest yields among the largest racial
differences observed on conventional intelligence tests (Kaufman, 1994;
Kaufman & Kaufman, 1983). My interpretation is that the legacy of large racial
differences has maintained when the tests have been the same old tests used
since the time of Binet and World War I. When a new task is tried, even when
it is an apparent shift of a kaleidoscope such as Faces & Places relative to
Information, then the racial differences may disappear. In fact, the
black-white difference was also small (as was the Hispanic-white difference)
for adolescents and young adults on an adult analog of the general information
task called Famous Faces (Kaufman, McLean, & Kaufman, 1995). Furthermore, a
new fluid reasoning task called Four-Letter Words, clearly a Level II task
from Jensen's system, also produced much smaller than predicted race
differences for a large sample of adolescents and adults (Kaufman, Chen, &
Kaufman, 1995). These findings reinforce the notion that the so-called
"constant difference" of about one standard deviation between test scores of
whites and blacks may be largely a function of the limited selection of
traditional tasks that defined virtually all tests of intelligence from the
past. Race differences on the new breed of intelligence tests that has
proliferated in the past two decades, many of them theory-based, may not
conform so closely to the findings of tasks from the Binet-Wechsler tradition.
Yet, despite my disagreements with some aspects of Jensen's research and
writing, I remain steadfast in my admiration for his stubborn insistence that
no topic is too holy to be scrutinized by empirical analysis; that no
interpretation of data is too politically incorrect to permit a
straightforward expression of one's scientific opinion; that threats and
intimidation are not effective methods for thwarting creativity and
expression; that some of the best inspirations for research can be found in
the historical annals of psychology among discarded and disavowed ideas; and
that one should be ready and willing to abandon strictly held beliefs if new,
compelling data should come along to suggest that the old ideas may be wrong.
To me, Jensen is the quintessential scientist.
--------------------
Jensen and Intelligence by NATHAN BRODY, Wesleyan University
Jensen's Contributions to the study of intelligence are discussed. The
paper considers his writing on the topic of racial differences in scores on
tests of intelligence. The paper concludes with a discussion of his research
on the correlates of the g vector.
JENSEN AND RACE
". . . it is a peculiar sensation this double consciousness, this sense of
seeing oneself through the eyes of others, of viewing one's soul by the rape
of a world that looks on in amused contempt and pity. One ever feels his
twoness -- an American, a Negro:..."
W.E.B. DuBois, Souls of Black Folks
This quotation, taken from a book published in 1903, is a doubly apt
introduction to Jensen's work on race and intelligence, it reminds us of the
effects of beliefs about racial differences on African-Americans who
experience "the sense of seeing oneself through the eyes of others. . .by the
tape of a world that looks on in amused contempt..." It is also descriptive of
the perception of Jensen's work by many hi the field of Psychology. Just as
those he writes about are forced to see themselves through his lens, others
see him through the lens of someone whose views about racial differences they
may abhor or reject.
Jensen's contributions to an understanding of individual differences in
intelligence extend far beyond a discussion of racial differences, but it is
his work on race that often serves to define his contributions. Therefore, a
discussion of his work on race is an apt beginning to an evaluation of his
overall contributions. Jensen (1974; 1977) published one of the best studies
demonstrating that extremely poor schooling could result in a cumulative
deficit in the intellectual functioning of African-Americans. He used a
sibling control design to demonstrate that African-American children attending
schools in the segregated south in the 1950s exhibited a cumulative decline in
intelligence relative to the intelligence of their younger siblings. He also
found that this effect was not present for African-American children attending
schools in Berkeley, California. These studies are illustrative of Jensen's
imaginative ability to obtain data that address a critical issue. Jensen's
results are buttressed by an analysis of the consequences of deprivation of
formal education associated with the decision of the Prince Edward County
School Board in Virginia to avoid compliance with a court ordered
desegregation plan (Green, Hoffman, Morse, Hayes, & Morgan, 1964). Green et
al. found that African-American children who were deprived of the opportunity
to attend public schools exhibited declines in intelligence of approximately
six points per year for each year of deprivation of formal schooling. Jensen's
results and the results of the Green et al. analysis are probably the two most
convincing studies in the literature indicating that educational influences
can reduce the intellectual functioning of African-Americans.
Robert Sternberg once wrote that he did not know why Jensen used his
formidable psychometric knowledge and talent to address this particular issues
(Sternberg, 1985). The choice of any of our research topics is mysterious and
not illuminated by somewhat simplistic and reductionist analyses of political
motives. I rather think, perhaps wrongly, that my interest in the field of
intelligence derives in part from a personal and moral imperative I feel that
compels me to differ with Jensen with respect to his views on race and
intelligence. Nevertheless, I believe that anyone who wishes to write about
the issue of race and intelligence must acknowledge Jensen's formidable
contributions to this topic and his comprehensive knowledge of this area of
research. Jensen's book on bias in testing is an extraordinarily thorough and
scholarly analysis of the issue of test bias (Jensen, 1980). I like to compare
this book with another book that I admire greatly, Paul Meehl's monograph on
Statistical vs. Clinical Prediction (Meehl, 1954). Both books serve to define
the principal issues that must be understood in addressing the topics that
they consider. Both books develop their arguments with unusual clarity and
sophistication. And, to a remarkable extent, the conclusions reached in both
books have stood the test of time and become part of the canon of empirically
established generalizations that define our knowledge of important topics.
Jensen established what is now close to the received wisdom of knowledgeable
students of intelligence -- tests of intelligence are equally valid indices of
the performance of individuals who differ with respect to their racial
identification. In several technical senses of the term, they are not biased
-- a conclusion endorsed in the recently published report of the American
Psychological Association's task-force on intelligence composed of individuals
with diverse views of the field (Neisser et al., 1996).
I do not agree with Jensen's argument, developed in great detail in his
forthcoming book on g, that genetic differences contribute to differences in
performance on tests of intelligence between African-American and other
racially identified groups (Jensen, 1998). I believe that his argument in
favor of a genetic hypothesis is not well grounded and I hope to publish an
analysis of my reasons for not accepting his arguments. It is easy for those
who know little about Jensen's views or the detailed analysis of research he
presents in support of his views to dismiss his arguments out of hand. It is
hard to dismiss his arguments (but I believe possible to do so) if one reads
him carefully and is informed about the literature. I believe that the reasons
for group differences in scores on tests of intelligence can not be
ascertained from the available data. Whether a determination of the reasons
for the group differences in scores would be theoretically or socially useful
is hard to know -- it may depend in part on the reasons for the difference and
what we can do to remediate the difference or to minimize its impact. And,
whatever our differences may be about this issue, there is at least one belief
about race and intelligence that we all share -- within group racial
differences are larger than between group differences.
Race does not define a person's score on a test of intelligence (or, for
that matter, any other characteristic other than race). I remember reviewing a
paper by Jensen dealing with an analysis of the relationship between head
circumference and the g vector that included data derived from two different
racial groups (Jensen, 1994). In my review I noted that his discussion of his
findings was not well-supported by his analyses and I suggested that he needed
to rewrite his discussion to present a somewhat more cautious and weaker
conclusion than he had presented. Jensen, on this occasion, agreed with me,
and wrote a very generous letter to the editor of the Journal thanking me for
my suggested recommendations and changed the article to reflect my criticisms.
I think that this episode is illuminating. Jensen is not an ideologue or a
person who is not able to respond to criticism in a fair way. He is a
scientist with formidable technical skills who strives for an understanding of
the topics that he addresses. In this regard, his work is a model of
scientific decorum. We should all strive to emulate his ability to test our
beliefs against a recalcitrant reality that often is resistant to our ability
to represent it in distorted ways. In the long run, if we are clever and
honest, it will impose its structure and truth on us rather than ours on it.
"g" VECTORS
In my opinion, Jensen's most important contribution to the field is
contained in his new book on the g factor (Jensen, 1998). In the first paper
dealing with g, Spearman attempted to determine the g loadings of different
measures of intelligence (Spearman, 1904). For much of this century, it has
been understood that tests differed in their g loadings and there was a
consensus about the kinds of tests that had the highest g loadings. Carroll's
comprehensive re-analysis of the canon of correlation matrices derived from
diverse measures of intelligence provides ample support for the proposition
that tests with high loadings on gf have higher g loadings than other tests
(Carroll, 1993). So, too, Marshalak, Lohman, and Snow's multidimensional
scaling analysis of tests of ability demonstrates that tests with high
loadings on gf such as the Ravens have higher g loadings than other tests
(Marshalek, Lohman, & Snow, 1983). An examination of the contents and
intellectual processes required for correct solution of tests that have high g
loadings provides a basis for speculations about the nature of g.
Jensen (1998) has taken the analysis of g beyond the realm of metaphorical
speculation. He derives g loading values for test batteries and then uses the
vector of g loadings as a parametric index that can be related to other
measures. These analyses provide a nomological network of laws and relations
surrounding g that serves to specify the theoretical meaning of g construed as
a hypothetical construct that is a variable component of different measures of
intelligence.
Jensen (1998) links the g vector to several biologically relevant vectors.
He notes that Pedersen et al. (1992) obtained heritability values for
different tests in a battery of tests of intelligence administered to a sample
of older Swedish adult MZ and DZ twins reared together and apart. The vector
defining the heritability of the tests is correlated with the vector defining
the independently ascertained g loadings, r = .77. Jensen provides additional
evidence based on Wechsler sub-test g loadings indicating that the vector of g
loadings is correlated with the vector of heritability values for Wechsler
sub-tests.
Jensen reports other results indicating that the g vector is linked to
biological indices. He analyzed data on head size and intelligence and
obtained a vector for different tests of intelligence that represented the
correlations between measures of head size and scores on different tests of
intelligence (Jensen, 1994). This vector was correlated with the g loading
vector. Head size is an imperfect index of brain size and the relationship
between head size and intelligence indicates that intelligence is related to
brain size. This establishes that the g vector is linked to a biological index
of intelligence.
Jensen (in press) reanalyzed the data obtained from a French adoption study
reported by Capron and Duyme (1989). This study used a complete
cross-fostering design to study the effects of variations in social class
background of biological and adopted parents on the IQ of adopted children.
Previous analyses of these data indicated that children's IQ was influenced in
an additive manner by the social class background of both adoptive and
biological parents. The latter influence was found to be stronger than the
former. Jensen obtained a vector defining the magnitude of the difference in
Wechsler sub-test scores for adopted children reared in high and low social
class families. He also obtained another vector defining the difference in
sub-test scores of the Wechsler test for adopted children whose biological
parents differed in social class background. This latter vector correlated
with the vector defining g loadings for the sub-test scores, r = .53. The
comparable correlation between the g loading vector and the vector of
differences in sub-test scores defined by the social class background of an
adopted child's adopted parents was .01. These data indicate that the nature
of the influence of biological and adopted parents on an adopted child's IQ is
different. The former influence varies with the g loading of the test and the
latter influence does not, apparently influencing components of variance in an
IQ test that are unrelated to g. This highly original analysis adds to the
evidence suggesting that the g vector is a biologically influenced component
of the variance in diverse measures of intellect and this analysis provides
evidence that the nature of the influence on IQ of biological and adopted
parents is both qualitatively and quantitatively distinct.
Jensen's analyses of the g vector also include studies relating the vector
to vectors defining the predictive validities of sub-test scores on the
Wechsler tests for measures of academic performance. He obtained correlations
between g vector scores and the vectors of correlations between Wechsler
sub-test scores and high school student's rank in class and college student's
grade point average. The correlation with the g vector for the high school
sample was .53 and the comparable correlation for the vector derived from the
college student sample was .83. These analyses indicate that the predictive
validity of a test of intelligence for a measure of academic success is
related to the g loadings of the test.
Jensen's analyses of the correlates of g vectors provide the quantitative
underpinning for what has long been apparent -- g is a biologically influenced
heritable component of the commonality among diverse measures of intellect
that is related to the ability of individuals to acquire knowledge in formal
academic contexts. Perhaps we have always known this, but following Jensen's
highly original use of analyses of the correlates of g vectors we know this
with a kind of quantitative precision not heretofore available.
Jensen's work on the correlates of the g vector reveals some of his best
attributes -- an ingenious ability to develop quantitative analyses that
address fundamental issues in highly original ways that advance our knowledge
of critical issues in the field.
Transtopia
- Main
- Pierre Teilhard De Chardin
- Introduction
- Principles
- Symbolism
- FAQ
- Transhumanism
- Cryonics
- Island Project
- PC-Free Zone